Print Friendly and PDF

Translate

Method, Structure, and Development in al-Fârâbï’s Cosmology

|


Method, Structure, and Development
in al-Fârâbï’s Cosmology


Islamic Philosophy, Theology
and Science

Texts and Studies

Edited by

Emilie Savage-Smith

Hans Daiber

Anna Akasoy

VOLUME 85

The titles published in this series are listed at brill.nl/ipts


Method, Structure, and
Development in al-Fârâbï’s
Cosmology

By

Damien Janos

 

' 1 6 8 * ‘

BRILL

LEIDEN BOSTON

2012

This book is printed on acid-free paper.

Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data

Janos, Damien.

Method, structure, and development in al-Farabi’s cosmology / by Damien Janos.

p. cm. -- (Islamic philosophy, theology, and science, ISSN 0169-8729 ; v. 85)

Based on the author’s thesis (Ph. D.)--McGill University, 2009.

Includes bibliographical references (p. ) and index.

ISBN 978-90-04-20615-1 (hardback : alk. paper) 1. Farabi. 2. Islamic cosmology. I. Title.

 

 



Acknowledgements.................................................................. xi

Abbreviations......................................................................... xiii

Introduction............................................................................... 1

I      Cosmology, the Sciences, and the Scientific Method......... 11

1.     The Late Antique Greek and Early Islamic Contexts..... 11

1.1.     Some Biographical Notes........................................ 12

1.2.     The Dual Legacy of Greek Astronomy and

Philosophy................................................................. 16

1.3.     Early Islamic Cosmological Trends......................... 26

1.4.     Cosmology in al-Fârâbï’s Philosophical Treatises

and the Problem with Mahdi’s Hypothesis............... 38

2.     Astronomy and its Place in the Philosophical Curriculum     43

2.1.      Astronomy and Astrology and their Subject Matter 44

2.2.      The Principles of Astronomy.................................. 57

2.3.      The Primacy of Metaphysics and its Impact

on Cosmology........................................................... 73

2.4.      Al-Fârâbï and the Later hay1 ah Tradition.............. 82

3.     Demonstration and Analogy: A Tension in

al-Fârâbï’s Method........................................................... 84

3.1.      The Evidence for and against Demonstration.......... 84

3.2.      The Limits of Human Knowledge and the Role

of Analogy................................................................ 94

3.3.      Transferred Terms (asma manqülah) and

Transference (naqlah)............................................... 98

4.     Conclusion.................................................................... 111

II      The Architecture of the Heavens: Intellects, Souls, and Orbs    115

1.     The Celestial Bodies..................................................... 115

1.1.     Orbs, Spheres, Planets, and Stars......................... 115

1.2.     Al-Fârâbï and Ptolemy on the Planetary Models... 119

1.3.     The Celestial Souls............................................... 128

2.     The Separate Intellects............................................... 142

2.1.      The Origin of al-Fârâbï’s Ennadic Scheme.......... 142

2.2.      A New Problem.................................................... 162


2.3.      The Nature, Activity, and Knowledge of the

Separate Intellects................................................. 167

2.4.      The Special Case of the Agent Intellect.............. 174

2.5.      Intellect and Form................................................ 176

3.     The First (al-awwal)................................................... 180

4.     Unity and Multiplicity................................................ 190

5.     Conclusion.................................................................. 201

III      Matter and Creation: A Shift in Paradigms?................... 203

1.     The Nature of Celestial Matter................................... 203

1.1.     Al-Fârâbï’s Hylic Terminology........................... 203

1.2.     A Survey of Celestial Matter in al-Fârâbï’s

Philosophy............................................................ 206

1.3.     Four Explanations of al-Fârâbï’s Theory

of Substrate (mawdu)............................................ 222

2.     The Origin of Matter: From Creationism to Eternal

Causation..................................................................... 235

2.1.      Aether and Creationism: An Exercise

in Harmonization.................................................. 236

2.2.      Ihsa‘ and Aghrad: Two Transitional Works?...... 256

2.3.      A Common Cosmogonical Paradigm.................. 266

2.4.      Conclusion........................................................... 279

2.5.      Falsafat Aristu ta lis............................................ 283

2.6.      The Eternalist Paradigm: Ara’, Siyasah, Tahsil,

Fusul, and Fi l-'aql............................................... 286

2.7.      Causation, Compositeness, and the Celestial

Substrate............................................................... 304

3.     Strengthening the Developmentalist.............. Hypothesis    312

4.     Conclusion.................................................................. 325

IV      The Aporia of Celestial Motion...................................... 333

1.     The Various Motions of the Heavenly Bodies........... 333

2.     The Causes of Celestial Motion................................. 339

2.1.      Nature and Motion: An Impasse......................... 339

2.2.      Quwwah............................................................... 345

2.3.      Intellection as a Cause of Motion........................ 348

3.     The Problem of the Particular Motions of the Planets 355

3.1.    Ibn Sïnâ and the Different Models of Planetary Motion             356

3.2.      A Hypothetical Reconstruction of al-Fârâbï’s

Kinematic Model.................................................. 362

3.3.      Celestial Kinematics and the Classification of the

Sciences in falsafah.............................................. 369

4.     Conclusion.................................................................. 376

Conclusion............................................................................. 379

Appendix 1............................................................................. 383

Appendix 2............................................................................. 397

Bibliography.......................................................................... 403

Index...................................................................................... 427


This book grew out of my Ph.D. dissertation submitted to McGill University in February 2009. While some of the views expressed are identical, the bulk of the book has been rewritten and its structure drastically modified. I have found it particularly challenging to achieve this task, and this for two main reasons. First, the scholarship on al-Fârâbï is increasing rapidly, and it is difficult to keep track of all the new studies being published on this fascinating and enigmatic thinker. In the mere two years since the completion of my dissertation, scores of articles have appeared, some of them of crucial relevance to the con­tents of this work. Second, virtually every aspect of al-Fârâbï’s philo­sophical system is the object of controversy or serious disagreement among scholars. This is true not only of his main philosophical doc­trines, but also of the authorship or authenticity of many of his works. Even his exact name and place of birth are disputed, which shows the intractable nature of the subject.

In spite of these challenges, I strove in the present work both to syn­thesize the recent scholarship on al-Fârâbï’s metaphysics and cosmol­ogy and to open new analytical perspectives in order to contribute to a resolution of some of the most outstanding problems regarding his thought. In this regard, there are many people I have had a chance to meet these last few years who have helped me in various ways with my research. I am grateful to all of them, but I would like to express my profound gratitude in particular to:

-     My former supervisors at the Institute of Islamic Studies at McGill University, Professor Robert Wisnovsky and Professor Jamil F. Ragep. Their support and encouragement during and after my stud­ies at McGill played a decisive role in the writing of this book, and I greatly benefited from their nuanced and penetrating approach to the study of Greek and Arabic intellectual history. At McGill, I am also grateful to Professor Carlos Fraenkel, Professor Stephen Menn, Mrs. Sally Ragep, Mr. Adam Gacek, Eliza Tasbihi, and Heather Empey.

-     At Ruhr-Universitat Bochum, I am indebted to Professor Gerhard Endress and Professor Hans Hinrich Biesterfeldt and, at the IKGF


Consortium, Professor Volkhard Krech, Professor Stefan Reichmuth, Dr. Marion Steinicke, to my former colleagues, Professor Jason Neelis, Dr. Georgios Halkias, Dr. Abhishek Singh Amar, Dr. Al Makin, as well as to the other scholars I had the chance of meeting during my stay in Bochum.

- In Gottingen, my deepest appreciation goes to Professor Sebastian Günther, Professor Jens Scheiner, and Dr. Monika Winet, as well as to my other colleagues at the EDRIS Courant Research Centre “Education and Religion” at Georg-August Universitat (funded by the German Initiative of Excellence). Many thanks also to Hamada Hassanein for his help with some of the Arabic transliterations.

Finally, I benefited greatly from the knowledge and insight of Professor Thérèse-Anne Druart, Professor Hans Daiber, Professor Frank Griffel, Professor Heidrun Eichner, Dr. Anna Akasoy, Dr. Philippe Vallat, and Dr. Olga Lizzini, all of whom provided valuable feedback on sections of this book or on some of the ideas it broaches. I am grateful to all of them, but take full responsibility for any shortcomings and for the interpretations articulated in this study.


ABBREVIATIONS

CAG=Commentaria in Aristotelem graeca.

EI2=Encyclopaedia of Islam, Second Edition.

EI3=Encyclopaedia of Islam, Third Edition.

Proclus:

Elements=Elements of Theology

Alexander of Aphrodisias:

Mabâdï=Risâlah ft mabadi l-kull

Neoplatonica arabica:

Mahd al-khayr=Kalam ft mahd al-khayr

Al-Fârâbï:

Aghrad=Ft aghrad al-haktm ft kull maqalah min al-kitab al-mawsüm bi-l-hurüf

Ara=Mabâdi ara ahl al-madïnah al-fadilah

Burhan=Kitab al-burhan

Da âwâ=Al-da‘awa l-qalbiyyah

l-‘aql=Risâlah ft l-‘aql

ma yanbaghï=Fï ma yanbaght an yuqaddama qabl taallum al-falsafah

Fusül=Fusül muntazaah

Fusül mabâdi’=Fusül mabadi ara’ ahl al-madïnah al-fadilah

Hurüf=Kitâb al-hurüf

Ihsa=Kitab ihsa l-’ulüm

Ithbat=Risalah ft ithbat al-mufariqat

Jam‘=Kitâb al-jam bayna ra’yay al-haktmayn

Jawâbât=Jawâbât li-masail suila ’anha

Müstqa=Kitab al-müstqa l-kabtr

Radd=Al-radd ’ala Yahya l-Nahwt

Siyasah=Al-siyasah al-madaniyyah

Tahstl=Kitab tahstl al-sa’ddah

Ta‘ltqdt=Kitdb al-taltqat

‘Uyün=‘Uyün al-masail

Ibn Sïnâ:

Isharat=Kitab al-isharat wa-l-tanbthât

Mabda=Al-mabda wa-l-maad

Najah=Kitab al-najah

Shifa=Kitab al-shifa

Maimonides:

Guide=The Guide of the Perplexed


Al-Fârâbï (d. 950 CE), also known as the ‘Second Teacher’ or ‘Second Master’ (al-muallim al-thant) after Aristotle in the Arabic tradition, is unanimously regarded as one of the great philosophers of the Middle Ages. As early as 1869, the Bohemian orientalist Moritz Steinschneider published a detailed study of this thinker’s life and works, thereby inaugurating a long tradition of Fârâbïan scholarship in the West. However, in spite of the sustained academic interest this work triggered and the publication of several recent books devoted to al-Fârâbï, his cosmology has not yet been the object of a specialized monographic study.[1] This is regrettable, given the crucial role it played in shaping the subsequent development of medieval Arabic and Jewish thought. Al-Fârâbï’s cosmological model was the one adopted by Ibn Sïnâ (or Avicenna) (d. 1037 CE); it was (in its Avicennan form) the main object of attack of al-Ghazâlï’s (d. 1111 CE) Tahafut al-falasifah; and it was this same model that was in turn defended and criticized by Ibn Rushd (d. 1198 CE) and Maimonides (d. 1204 CE). As D. De Smet recently showed, it also exercised a deep influence on the Ismâ'ïlï tradi­tion and especially on H amid al-Dïn al-Kirmânï (d. 1021 CE).[2] The profound and variegated legacy of al-Fârâbï’s cosmology in Arabic intellectual history calls for a sustained investigation and a clearer understanding of this aspect of his philosophy.

This study provides a new interpretation of al-Fârâbï’s cosmology and philosophical development through an analysis of the Greek and Arabic sources and a contextualization of his life and thought in the cultural and intellectual milieu of his time. It attempts to reconstruct a comprehensive yet nuanced picture of al-Fârâbï’s theories of the struc­ture and essence of the heavenly world, of the various principles that govern it, as well as of the human capacity to study it. On the one hand, the book analyzes a cluster of key cosmological and metaphysical con­cepts, namely, celestial substance, causation, intellection, and motion, whose articulation in al-Fârâbï’s works marked an important shift in early Arabic intellectual history. In addition to partially tracing the


genealogy of these concepts in the ancient Greek philosophical back­ground, the book seeks to identify some of the stages of adaptation and transformation they went through in the early Arabic context and to define the new meaning they acquired in al-Fârâbï’s thought as a result of this process. On the other hand, al-Fârâbï’s philosophical activity is defined in light of the social, cultural, and intellectual climate of his day. The main purpose of this dual textual and contextual approach is to study al-Fârâbï’s thought as the philosophical expression of a par­ticular time and place, namely, the vibrant and cosmopolitan society of tenth-century Baghdad. This approach, which has not been fully exploited in the past in Fârâbïan studies, can best enable us to grasp the historical development of his philosophical ideas. While it is not with­out its own pitfalls, this framework provides a valuable corrector to the ahistorical approach that has so often been relied upon to interpret al-Fârâbï’s philosophy.

Emphasis is placed on the relation between astronomy, physics, and metaphysics, the ‘chief cosmological sciences,’ and on how these disciplines interrelate in terms of both methodology and content in the Second Teacher’s cosmology. The study adopts an interdiscipli­nary framework that bridges the history of astronomy and philosophy and pays special attention to the place of astronomical theories in the Second Teacher’s cosmology, an issue that is still poorly understood with regard to this thinker and to the falasifah in general. In that sense, this book may be regarded as a case study of how astronomical theory fits into the broader philosophical system of a medieval philoso­pher.[3] To what extent is this science reconciled—or does it conversely interfere—with the other philosophical disciplines? To what extent is al-Fârâbï’s astronomical model indebted to Ptolemy (d. ca. 168 CE), and how does it relate to the Arabic astronomical tradition? What role do astronomy, physics, and metaphysics play in explaining the causes of celestial motion, a crucial problem in medieval cosmology? In order to shed light on these issues, I examine the interactions—and some­times the tensions—between these sciences in al-Fârâbï’s works. This approach has the advantage of bringing together various disciplines that have evolved in separate directions over time, but which many medieval thinkers regarded as being closely linked or interrelated.

Al-Fârâbï’s method and his interpretation of the various philosophi­cal and scientific sources are analyzed in detail. One of the study’s overarching aims in this regard is to show that al-Fârâbï was able to elaborate a new cosmological model chiefly as a result of a sustained and creative interpretive approach to the Greek and Arabic textual traditions. I argue that al-Fârâbï’s philosophical method should be regarded as a complex exegetical process whose main feature was the interpretation of Aristotle’s theories in light of the late antique philo­sophical tradition, consisting of both commentaries on Aristotle and independent works. Various in-depth case studies of how al-Fârâbï brought about this project are provided: his interpretation of Aristotle’s unmoved movers, of celestial matter, and of the intellectual activity of the immaterial existents are a few striking examples discussed in the analysis. It is in this sense that one may speak of al-Fârâbï’s harmoniz­ing project, which extended not only to the various currents of Greek philosophy, especially late antique Aristotelianism and Neoplatonism, but also included the works of ancient Greek astronomers, especially Ptolemy. The cosmological synthesis that emerged from his protracted engagement with these texts was due both to volitional and accidental factors, but it resulted in any case in the elaboration of a new cosmo­logical paradigm that provided later thinkers with a framework for rec­onciling astronomy with physics and metaphysics.

This cosmological model may be seen as the culmination of a long intellectual development marked by several tensions, which are also discussed in the study. Indeed, al-Fârâbï’s exegetical approach was nei­ther static nor monolithic, and it underwent various shifts in direction and perspective due to his dynamic understanding of the Greek works and factors emanating from his social and cultural environment. Accordingly, a central thesis articulated in this book is that al-Fârâbï’s cosmology underwent a clear evolution and can be divided into two distinct periods, which correspond to two different cosmological mod­els or paradigms and to a rough chronology of his life and output. Through a discussion of the doctrinal and bio-bibliographic evidence, chapter 3 introduces a ‘developmentalist hypothesis,’ according to which al-Fârâbï’s cosmology shifted from a creationist position, which he upheld during his early Baghdad period, to an eternalist position that crystallized during a later phase of his life and coincides with the end of his stay in Baghdad and his travels to Syria and Egypt.

In addition to classifying and analyzing the evidence supporting this hypothesis, this study attempts to explain some of the social and reli­gious factors that may have triggered this development and enabled al-Farabi’s mature cosmological theories to materialize. In conjunction with the examination of the Greek philosophical sources, the book contextualizes al-Farabi’s cosmology within the intellectual climate of his day, in order to reconstruct a more comprehensive picture of his intellectual trajectory and of his shifting philosophical priorities. The analysis focuses, among other issues, on his intellectual formation in Christian philosophical and theological circles in Baghdad, his likely familiarity with al-Kindi’s (d. after 870 CE) and Abû Bakr al-Razi’s (d. 925 CE) works and legacies, as well as his awareness of recent devel­opments in Arabic science, especially Arabic astronomy. An approach that combines these cultural and biographical factors together with a study of the Greek sources can best explain the complexity of the Second Teacher’s thought and the apparent discrepancies in his works.

In connecting al-Farabi chiefly with the late antique Greek tradition of philosophical exegesis, this book builds on several scholarly contri­butions in Farabian studies, especially those of M. Maróth, C. D’Ancona, and P. Vallat, and is also indebted more broadly to studies on al-Farabi’s Neoplatonism, especially by T.-A. Druart.[4] Accordingly, this study focuses particularly on the Greek commentatorial tradition and especially the legacies of Alexander of Aphrodisias (fl. ca. 200 CE), Themistius (d. ca. 390 CE), Simplicius (d. ca. 560 CE), Philoponus (d. ca. 570 CE), and Proclus (d. 485 CE), whose works played a decisive role in shaping both the specific issues that al-Farabi addressed in his cosmology and the solutions he elaborated. I devote a special place in the analysis to the Arabic translations and adaptations of Proclus’ works, especially Mahd al-khayr, the Arabic version of Elements of Theology, since this work was the likely medium through which al-Farabi assimilated Proclean ideas. I attempt to explain how al-Farabi used the Proclus arabus as a conceptual apparatus to construe Aristotle’s cosmology in a new light and to articulate original solutions to old cosmological problems, as can be seen with respect to celestial sub­stance, existence, and motion. Moreover, al-Farabi’s exegetical achieve­ment and his complex theory of celestial causality and intellection define him as an exponent of certain key aspects of Neoplatonic metaphysics in Islam and as an heir to the late antique pagan philo­sophical worldview. Consequently, al-Fârâbï is presented throughout the analysis as an active and creative agent, rather than as a passive recipient, of the Greek philosophical heritage, and one who keenly adapted and transformed it to fit his own philosophical project.

In carrying out this source criticism, this study focuses on several texts from late antiquity and from within the Fârâbïan corpus itself that have been either ignored or have not been the object of extended discussion in the secondary literature on al-Fârâbï. This is the case, for instance, of several late antique physical and metaphysical commentar­ies, such as Alexander’s and Simplicius’ commentary on and paraphrase of On the Heavens, Themistius’ paraphrase of Metaphysics, Geminus’ astronomical works, Ptolemy’s Almagest and Planetary Hypotheses, and Alexander’s and Syrianus’ commentaries on Metaphysics. I also devote much attention to the various texts forming the Neoplatonica arabica, which have seldom been the object of a detailed comparative analysis. In this connection, this study pays particular attention to the form in which al-Fârâbï read these works, since the process of translat­ing from Greek to Arabic was often accompanied by a fair amount of doctrinal adaptation, as can be seen with regard to the various Arabic versions of Aristotle’s Metaphysics and the Proclus arabus. Illuminating al-Fârâbï’s interpretation of these works in the form in which he read them appears a necessary step to fully grasp the development of his cosmology.

With regard to al-Fârâbï’s corpus, the study focuses primarily on his main philosophical treatises, such as Ara’ and Siyasah, but it also deals with understudied works such as Müstqa and Burhan, as well as many other logical treatises, which contain a wealth of information on al-Fârâbï’s scientific method and cosmological doctrines. In addition, both the main chapters of the book and appendix 1 include texts whose attribution to al-Fârâbï remains uncertain. This is the case of Taltqat, Uyün, Ithbat, Daawa, and more importantly of Jam’ and Jawabat, two works whose authorship has recently been questioned by M. Rashed.[5] An investigation of their cosmological contents is called for, both in order to settle their status vis-à-vis the Fârâbïan corpus and to high­light the often interesting cosmological theories they formulate.

The results accumulated throughout this study and the new develop- mentalist interpretation it articulates question previous ideas con­cerning al-Fârâbï’s philosophical affiliations and the structure of his corpus. In doing so, it participates in the ongoing debate concern­ing many aspects of al-Fârâbï’s thought and works and intends to offer new insight into these vexed issues. The present book challenges the view that the Fârâbïan corpus can be divided neatly into ‘Aristotelian’ works and ‘personal’ or ‘Neoplatonic’ works, and it proposes a new division of the Fârâbïan corpus in light of the developmentalist hypoth­esis. In this respect, the analysis also reassigns a new status to works that have recently been considered spurious or of doubtful author­ship, and it discusses some of the reasons that can account for the dis­crepancies between these works and the rest of the Fârâbïan corpus. Moreover, it provides an alternative explanation of al-Fârâbï’s use of the Neoplatonica arabica and of its place in his metaphysics, defining it as a key factor underlying the evolution of his thought. Finally, the study also redefines the much studied concept of emanationism in light of his general metaphysics of causation, thereby challenging the seman­tic specificity of this concept in his cosmology. In so doing, this book seeks to establish al-Fârâbï’s cosmology and his views on the question of the creation of the world firmly within the current scholarly discus­sion of these issues in Arabic intellectual history.[6]

Attaining these goals will provide an alternative to the interpretive paradigm of al-Fârâbï’s philosophy elaborated by M. Mahdi, which has until recently prevailed in Fârâbïan studies. Although several mono­graphs on al-Fârâbï have appeared in recent years, they focus primarily on his political philosophy and perpetuate either explicitly or implicitly the Strauss-Mahdi paradigm, with the result that al-Fârâbï’s cosmology has still not received the thorough study it deserves.[7] As D. Gutas has written, “the prevalence of the Straussian interpretation of al-Fârâbï has had a chilling effect on mainstream studies of this very significant philosopher.”[8] To Mahdi’s claim that al-Fârâbï elaborated a “political cosmology” devoid of scientific value and designed to stand merely as a metaphor for the inhabitants of the virtuous city, this book argues that it should be regarded rather as a coherent worldview grounded in the most up-to-date physical, metaphysical, and astronomical theories of his time.[9]

Chapter 1 deals with al-Fârâbï’s methodology, which rests on a complex conceptualization of the scope and interrelatedness of the sciences. The central question that informs the discussion is an episte­mological and methodological one: through which rational means and disciplines can human beings study the heavens and know the princi­ples that govern them? Emphasis is placed on the method of astronomy, its relation to physics and metaphysics, the various techniques used for establishing its principles, the place of observation and experience, and the nature of the proofs associated with these sciences. In addition, the connection between al-Fârâbï’s logical and metaphysical treatises is also addressed, with the view of showing the interplay between these various facets of his thought.

Chapters 2 to 4 focus on some key doctrines of al-Fârâbï’s cosmol­ogy. Chapter 2 reconstructs the basic structure of his cosmological model and discusses the various physical and immaterial entities that constitute it. It provides an analysis of the Greek and Arabic sources al-Fârâbï consulted and sheds light on his interpretive approach to these texts. In this respect, the study addresses specific cosmological questions that are crucial to understand the Second Teacher’s cosmol­ogy, and by implication, the later history of Arabic cosmology. How did he interpret the Aristotelian theory of the unmoved movers in Metaphysics Book Lambda? How do these movers relate to the celestial orbs? What role does the principle of intellect play in his cosmology and what texts may have shaped his views on the subject? This chapter provides a clearer understanding of the place of Aristotelian and Neoplatonic sources in al-Fârâbï’s cosmology and of how he interpreted them and used them to devise his own system.

Chapter 3 surveys and collects the disparate and fragmented evi­dence on celestial matter that can be found in al-Fârâbï’s corpus, with the aim of reconstructing his views on this important cosmological question. His views on celestial matter are furthermore contextual­ized within the debate about the creation of the world, raising the ques­tion of how God and the immaterial beings relate to the physical cosmos. The analysis focuses primarily on the concepts and terminol­ogy of causation articulated in the Second Teacher’s works, particularly with respect to how they are applied to the various immaterial beings of his cosmology. Al-Fârâbï’s debt to Neoplatonic thought is empha­sized through a comparative analysis of his works and the Greek and Arabic Proclus, enabling a more nuanced assessment of his affilia­tion to late antique metaphysics and of his attitude toward Islamic monotheism.

Finally, chapter 4 attempts to reconstruct the Second Teacher’s the­ory of celestial motion on the basis of the rare passages dealing with this question in his works and by using evidence drawn from Ibn Sïnâ’s treatises. Particular attention is devoted to the role played by physics, metaphysics, and astronomy in al-Fârâbï’s explanations of how the orbs and planets move, to the question of kinematic causality, and to the relation between the separate intellects and the celestial orbs. This chapter provides insight into various key issues that should be of inter­est to those interested in the history of medieval kinematics.

The study therefore provides a detailed analysis of a cluster of concepts—celestial matter, intellection, causation, and motion—which constitute the building blocks of al-Fârâbï’s cosmological model and define him both as an heir and creative contributor to the cosmological legacy of late antiquity. On the other hand, it will not deal at any length with the much studied question of the nature and role of the Agent Intellect in al-Fârâbï’s philosophy, since technically speaking, the Agent Intellect is exclusively occupied with the sublunary world and plays no role in superlunary causation and motion. Little will be said about the related issues of how the Agent Intellect impacts on human intellection and on the epistemological connection between the human intellect and the heavenly world.[10]

Given al-Fârâbï’s importance for the subsequent history of medieval thought, this study should be of interest to those dealing with Jewish, Christian, and Islamic cosmology and metaphysics. In addition, it pro­vides a comparative analysis of Ibn Sina’s and al-Fârâbï’s views on numerous themes. Hence, the results should also be of interest to stu­dents of Ibn Sina’s philosophy and of the post-Avicennan philosophical tradition in Islam.


CHAPTER ONE

COSMOLOGY, THE SCIENCES, AND
THE SCIENTIFIC METHOD

1. 'The Late Antique Greek and Early Islamic Contexts

Al-Fârâbï’s cosmology can be explained by the legacy of Greek science and philosophy on the one hand and the intellectual developments that characterized early Islamic civilization on the other.[11] With regard to the former, al-Fârâbï inherited a dual cosmological tradition: an astro­nomical one embodied chiefly in the Ptolemaic works, as well as per­haps in some minor astronomical treatises by various Greek authors; and a philosophical one contained in the Aristotelian corpus and its commentaries, as well as the Arabic adaptations of Neoplatonic works, especially the Proclus arabus and Plotinus arabus. This duality is reflected in the Fârâbïan corpus itself: while his commentary on Almagest was inscribed in an ancient astronomical tradition that endured until his time, his so-called ‘emanationist’ treatises, Ara and Siydsah, cover a variety of physical, metaphysical, and political issues and are more in the vein of philosophical works such as Plato’s Timaeus and Republic, Aristotle’s Metaphysics, and Proclus’ Elements of Theology.[12] Hence, one may from the outset raise the questions of how al-Fârâbï perceived this heritage, whether he attempted to achieve a reconcilia­tion of these two disciplinary traditions, and how his corpus was adapted accordingly. In turn, this raises the question of the place occu­pied by astronomy, physics, and metaphysics in al-Fârâbï’s approach to cosmology. The degree of his acquaintance with contemporary astro­nomical research and his interest in scientific methodology are factors that should be taken into consideration. These questions will form the backdrop of chapter 1, but first I wish to say a few words concerning al-Fârâbï’s biography.

1.1.    Some Biographical Notes

I will not provide a detailed account of al-Fârâbï’s biography in what follows, since very few facts about his life are known with certainty. Moreover, readers can now choose between two authoritative accounts, a skeptical and ‘minimalist’ article by D. Gutas, and a more elaborate yet speculative account by P Vallat.[13] Rather, I will limit myself to high­lighting a few aspects of al-Fârâbï’s life that can help us to better under­stand the formation and development of his philosophy. Abû Nasr al-Fârâbï was born in 870 CE, most likely in the district of Fârâb situ­ated on the Jaxartes River (also known as Syr Darya) in Turkestan.[14] Surprisingly, al-Fârâbï’s birthplace has never been properly discussed in scholarly works on this thinker, and so a few comments are in order. Far from being a cultural backwater, the broad regions of Khurasan and Transoxania had been for centuries an arena of exchange and inter­action between peoples of various linguistic and religious backgrounds, including pagans, Buddhists, Zoroastrians, and later Christians and Muslims. Hellenistic influences also reached these regions as a result of Alexander the Great’s eastern campaigns and the establishment of Hellenistic kingdoms in Asia. Moreover, this vast geographic area entertained commercial and cultural contacts with the Turkic peoples and ultimately with China through land routes heading north. Farab itself, the district in which al-Farabï was presumably born, was by no means negligible. According to al-Muqaddasï, who flourished in the tenth century CE, it consisted of several towns, including one, Farab (named after the district), which boasted fortifications, a communal mosque, markets, and a citadel, and was allegedly inhabited by some 70,000 people.[15] Even allowing for some exaggeration, this indicates that Farab was not an insignificant settlement. Al-Fârâbï is said to have been born either in Farab itself or in the nearby village of Wasïj, but in either case his early years would have been spent in this cosmopolitan and culturally multi-faceted environment, a fact which can help to explain his later views on the relativity of religions vis-à-vis the univer­sality of philosophy.

In view of this regional history and of the existence of urban centers in the heart of Farab, it is likely that al-Farabfs philosophical formation began before his arrival in Baghdad. Apart from the district of Farab itself, there were several other cities in Transoxania and Khurasan, which, by the late ninth and early tenth century, hosted a vibrant and diverse intellectual scene. Merw, for instance, possessed an important library and was a cultural center characterized by Christian, Islamic, and Hellenistic features. Several Christian thinkers, including al-Farabfs teacher Yûhanna ibn H aylan (d. between 908-932 CE) and Ibrahïm of Merw, the teacher of Abû Bishr Matta ibn Yûnus (d. 940 CE), as well as the influential Barmakid family, hailed from this city.[16] Merw and Khurasan in general were the home of a school of theology that pro­duced several notable thinkers, such as Ibn al-Rawandi (fl. 850 CE) and Abû l-Qasim al-Ka‘bi al-Balkhi (d. 931 CE), whose writings may have been known to al-Farabi.[17] Finally, Merw was the city from which the Abbasid revolution was launched, indicating its profound ideological and religious importance during this period. Thus, it seems plausible that al-Farabi acquired the rudiments of his education in the cities of Transoxania and Khurasan, even though it cannot be decided with cer­tainty when and under which circumstances he first arrived in Baghdad.

Perhaps the most significant aspect of al-Farabi’s biography I wish to highlight here—and one about which we possess crucial evidence—is his early intellectual formation at the hands of Nestorian Christian thinkers. Although al-Farabi’s relation with the Nestorians is attested after his arrival in Baghdad, it is possible that he had been in contact with them prior to his arrival in the City of Peace, since the Nestorians had established a solid presence throughout the north-eastern Islamic lands, especially Merw. It is from this city—an important center of Nestorian thought and culture—that missionaries travelled to Central Asia and even China to spread their faith.[18] At any rate, al-Farabi him­self asserts that he studied logic with the Christian Yûhanna ibn H aylan, a report later confirmed by al-Masudi, and he in addition probably attended some of the classes of Abû Bishr Matta ibn Yûnus, another Nestorian thinker whom he surely met and whose translations of Aristotle he presumably read. Finally, it would seem that al-Farabi also studied grammar with Ibn al-Sarraj (d. 929 CE).[19] From what we can gather from this scarce biographical information, then, Yûhanna ibn Haylan and Abû Bishr Matta ibn Yunus are the two individuals who are likely to have had the strongest philosophical impact on the young al-Farabï. For this reason, and because they will be frequently men­tioned throughout this book, it is worthwhile to say more about these two figures.

Abû Bishr Matta ibn Yûnus al-Qanna’ï, henceforth Matta ibn Yûnus, was fluent in both Syriac and Arabic and was one of the outstanding representatives of the Christian Aristotelian circle in early tenth­century Baghdad. He studied first in the religious school of Mar Mari at Dayr Qunna and then in the City of Peace with a group of scholars who allegedly had come from Merw. Apart from his debate with the Arabic grammarian Abû Sa‘ïd al-Sïrafï, Matta ibn Yûnus is chiefly known both for his numerous translations of Aristotle from Syriac and for his own commentaries on some of these Peripatetic works. It is per­haps not insignificant that Matta ibn Yûnus chose to translate Posterior Analytics and Metaphysics, as well as other Aristotelian works dealing with the heavens and their impact on the sublunary world—part of On the Heavens and its paraphrase by Themistius, On Generation and Corruption with the commentaries of Alexander and Olympiodorus, and Meteorology with Olympiodorus’ commentary—for these are pre­cisely the works that shaped al-Fârâbï’s cosmological method and doc­trines. This list of works points to the important place that cosmology occupied alongside logic in the circle that developed around Matta ibn Yûnus, an interest that was apparently transmitted from teacher to disciple.[20]

Chiefly because his works have survived only in fragmentary state, if at all, but also because his debate with Abû Sa‘ïd al-Sïrâfï has monopo­lized the attention of scholars, Matta ibn Yûnus’ surviving writings have been hardly studied at all. This hampers any attempt to compare his theories to those of al-Farabï. It also makes our understanding of how indebted the latter was to his teacher in the physical and meta­physical fields more difficult. While I already alluded to the common interest these philosophers shared in cosmology, it is likely that Matta ibn Yûnus’ influence on al-Farabï extended to specific concepts and theories. For instance, some of Matta ibn Yûnus’ cosmological views on creation and causation, on the substance of the heavens, and on their impact on the sublunary world may have been instrumental in orient­ing al-Farabfs early cosmological position. For this reason, one section of this book (ch. 3, 2.3.3.) will be devoted to analyzing the surviving excerpts of Matta ibn Yunus’ commentary on Physics and exploring the potential influence his cosmological views had on al-Fârâbï.

While we possess some valuable information concerning Matta ibn Yünus’ life and works, virtually nothing is known about al-Fârâbï’s other official teacher, Yühannâ b. H aylân, who is described by al-Fârâbï himself as his main instructor in logic. Even though some scholars have speculated that the two men studied in Harrân, we possess virtually no evidence on the circumstances surrounding their encounter.[21] None of Ibn Haylân’s works has survived, and the biographical data that can be retrieved from the sources is meager and limited to a few scattered bio­graphical remarks.[22] Yet when taken together, these facts concerning al-Fârâbï’s education at the hands of Christian thinkers are important and should be taken into account when assessing various aspects of his works and thought. They explain from the outset some of the striking features of al-Fârâbï’s output: its emphasis on logic and cosmology, its inclusion of numerous commentaries on Aristotle, and its concern about the relation between religion and philosophy. These elements will, on several occasions in this book, be brought to the fore of the discussion in an effort to combine a doctrinal and biographical analysis of al-Fârâbï’s philosophy.

The biographical sketch given above shows that al-Fârâbï’s interest in cosmology first developed as a result of his philosophical formation with the Christian Peripatetics, especially in connection with the com­position of his own commentaries on the physical works of the Aristotelian corpus. It is to this aspect of his output and to the various kinds of Greek and Arabic sources that shaped al-Fârâbï’s cosmology that I presently wish to turn.

1.2.    The Dual Legacy of Greek Astronomy and Philosophy

1.2.1. Aristotle, the Late Antique Commentators, and al-Fârâbts Commentatorial Activity

Like most medieval cosmologists, al-Fârâbï relied primarily on Aristotle’s On the Heavens, Physics, and Metaphysics, which had been translated into Arabic at least once before or during his lifetime.[23] These Aristotelian works provided medieval thinkers with a coherent and elaborate cosmological model, whose various theories, however, were not always easy to reconcile with one another. Many of the cosmologi­cal issues studied by al-Farabi, such as the substance of the heavenly bodies, the organization of the heavenly orbs, their intellection and motion, and their relation to God, stem from these seminal works. But in many instances, he departs from Aristotle by developing his own interpretations, salient examples being his theories of heavenly matter, intellection, causation, and motion (discussed in ch. 2-4).

Apart from some of his propaedeutic works, such as Ihsa’, Fï ma yanbaghï, and Falsafat Aristütalïs, al-Farabi’s familiarity with the Aris­totelian corpus can be gauged from his commentaries on the Organon and from the bibliographic information concerning his commentato- rial activity. While his commentaries on or summaries of Categories, On Interpretation, Topics, Prior Analytics, Posterior Analytics, as well as on Rhetoric, are all extant, Ibn al-Qifti and Ibn Abi Usaybiah also men­tion other commentaries on Physics, On the Heavens, and Meteorology, which surely contained a wealth of information on al-Farabi’s cosmol­ogy, but which unfortunately have not survived, except for a short excerpt of Physics preserved in Latin.[24] On the other hand, al-Farabi does not seem to have written a full commentary on Metaphysics, a somewhat surprising fact given the importance of Book Lambda in his cosmology.[25] Hence, in spite of the fact that virtually all of the commentaries al-Farabi wrote on natural philosophy have vanished, the bio-bibliographic reports indicate that he assiduously studied the main works of the Aristotelian corpus, with a special emphasis on the Organon and on the physical treatises, many of which deal with the heavens and cosmological phenomena.

This emphasis on logic and cosmology can be explained convinc­ingly by al-Fârâbï’s early philosophical training with the Christian Peripatetic thinkers, who on the one hand specialized in the study of the Organon, and on the other hand showed a marked interest for Aristotle’s cosmology and translated many works dealing with this topic.[26] This highlights the continuity between the philosophical activ­ity of Matta ibn Yûnus and al-Fârâbï and helps us to better understand some of the roots of his thought. That al-Fârâbï quickly attained profi­ciency in this adapted curriculum and in the study of Aristotelian logic in particular is attested by the Arabic historiographical tradition, which describes him by the honorific title of ‘Second Teacher’ or ‘Second Master.’ This title at once shows the importance of his commentatorial works and his esteemed status as an interpreter of the Stagirite in the Arabic tradition, even though our knowledge of this aspect of his phi­losophy is in many ways fragmentary.[27]

Al-Fârâbï’s extant commentaries are valuable not only for their capacity to help us understand how he interpreted Aristotle, but also because they provide some insight into his philosophical method and the evolution of his thought. In this respect, and although little is known about the chronology of al-Fârâbï’s works, it may be assumed that he wrote most of his commentaries during an early phase of his life, when he was studying under Yûhannâ ibn H aylân and possibly Mattâ ibn Yûnus in Baghdad.[28] The practice of writing commentaries

was very common in the Christian intellectual milieu he frequented in Baghdad and may be regarded as a continuation of the Alexandrian academic tradition, which had also devoted a privileged place to the writing of commentaries and to the study of logic in its philosophical curriculum. Yûhanna ibn H aylan and Yahya ibn ‘Adi, a teacher and student of al-Farabi respectively, were well-known translators of, and commentators on, the Aristotelian corpus and contributed actively to spreading Aristotelian philosophy to the Middle East.[29] Regardless of how much credibility should be ascribed to the traditional narrative concerning the transmission of the Alexandrian philosophical curricu­lum to Baghdad, it is undeniable that al-Farabi’s early philosophical phase is inscribed in a well-established tradition of commentatorial writing and studying that has its roots in late antiquity, but one of whose main offshoots flourished in Syriac circles in ninth- and tenth-century Baghdad.

The historical context sketched above represents the first hint that al-Farabi’s philosophical initiation and his interpretation of Aristotle were shaped by some of the social, cultural, and intellectual circum­stances prevailing in the Baghdad of his time. In turn, this indicates that al-Farabi’s approach to philosophy may have evolved throughout his career, as he gradually distanced himself from this early philosophi­cal framework characterized mainly by the study of Aristotle and the writing of commentaries. Research on al-Farabi’s logical works, such as K. al-qiyas and K. mudkhal ila l-qiyas, K. al-'ibdrah, and K. al-khatabah (works based on Prior Analytics, On Interpretation, and Rhetoric respec­tively), has shown that from the very outset, he did not slavishly follow Aristotelian logic in an uncritical way, but rather developed his own theories and elaborated on several concepts merely alluded to in the original Greek texts.[30] As this book will show, the same may be said about al-Fârâbï’s cosmological theories. By way of illustration, accord­ing to Maimonides in Guide, al-Fârâbï’s Physics commentary argued that different degrees of celestial matter should be ascribed to the dif­ferent types of celestial bodies in the heavens. This view not only marks an elaboration on Aristotle’s aether theory as it is exposed in On the Heavens, but also differs from al-Fârâbï’s own doctrine of celestial sub­stance as it appears in his other works, especially in his metaphysical treatises.[31] This simple fact suggests that al-Fârâbï’s no longer extant commentaries on On the Heavens and Physics may have already initi­ated a process of transformation of Aristotle’s cosmology, thus pointing to a creative approach to these cosmological problems early in al-Fârâbï’s life. It also raises the possibility (explored in detail in chapter 3 of this book) that the views articulated in the presumably early commentato- rial works such as Physics and On the Heavens were later abandoned by al-Fârâbï when he wrote his mature philosophical treatises.

Needless to say, the loss of al-Fârâbï’s commentaries on Physics, On the Heavens, and Meteorology represents a tremendous impediment for our understanding of his cosmology. The loss of On the Heavens is par­ticularly acute due to the place that this work traditionally occupies in the cosmological systems of ancient and medieval thinkers. This is all the more true in the case of al-Fârâbï, who appears to have elabo­rated a new cosmological model in Ára and Siyasah that had a lasting influence on subsequent thinkers.[32] The disappearance of al-Fârâbï’s commentaries on Physics and On the Heavens also renders an assess­ment of his relation to the ancient commentators more difficult. It was customary for Greek exegetes to discuss the views of previous or con­temporary authors in their own account of Aristotle’s works. On the Heavens in particular was one of the most debated texts and became a locus of scholarly contention in the late antique period. The Greek philosopher Simplicius offers a good example of this practice: a wealth of information about other thinkers (e.g., Alexander of Aphrodisias, Ammonius son of Hermeias, and Philoponus) can be extracted from his commentary on this work. But because al-Fârâbï’s commentaries on the Aristotelian physical treatises have vanished, we have only lim­ited information about his exegetical method and the degree of his reli­ance on the late antique Greek commentators. This problem is compounded by the fact that he is usually reluctant to mention previ­ous thinkers by name and to acknowledge the debt he owes them, which makes it difficult to gauge the originality of his thought.[33]

In spite of this, the bio-bibliographic sources ascertain that al-Fârâbï could have read several late antique Greek commentaries on logic, natural philosophy, and metaphysics in addition to the Aristotelian works. Most of these commentaries were translated into Arabic either before or during al-Fârâbï’s life and had become part and parcel of the philosophical education of his day. For instance, he may have consulted all or part of Alexander’s and Philoponus’ commentaries on Physics, Alexander’s commentary on On the Heavens and on some chapters of Metaphysics, as well as Themistius’ paraphrases of the two latter works. This information is crucial to understand al-Fârâbï’s cosmology, which often builds upon the theories that these thinkers articulated in their attempt to tie up the loose ends in Aristotle’s thought and legacy. When one realizes that Mattâ ibn Yunus and Yahyâ ibn Adï, who belonged to the same Baghdadi circle as al-Fârâbï, figure prominently among the translators of these Greek commentaries, then the connection between al-Fârâbï and the late antique authors acquires a new significance.

Finally, and as a complement to Aristotle and the late antique commentaries, al-Fârâbï read Arabic recensions or adaptations of Neoplatonic works, although he did not write commentaries on them.[34] Although little is known about the context in which these works were studied—they do not seem to have occupied a central place in the cur­riculum of al-Fârâbï’s Christian teachers—they nonetheless played a vital role in shaping some of his cosmological and metaphysical doc­trines.[35] These works devote much attention to the cosmic principles of soul and intellect and their various effects, the nature of the stars, the influence of the celestial bodies on the sublunary world, not to mention the many excerpts that discuss creation and causality. That al-Fârâbï knew this corpus well, especially the Proclus arabus, and integrated several of its theories into his own cosmological model will represent one of the main results of the source analysis provided in this book. As chapters 2 and 3 will show, nowhere is this Neoplatonic dimension more explicitly and forcefully expressed than in al-Fârâbï’s conception of the activity and causation of the intellectual substances and of how God relates to the world. As a result, his theories sometimes depart significantly from Aristotle’s doctrine. What remains to be clarified, however, is whether he genuinely ascribed these works to Aristotle or did so only for apologetic reasons, and the degree to which the corpus he consulted differs from the recensions now in our possession. The foregoing remarks aimed to delineate the late antique philosophical sources that al-Fârâbï could have read and used to elaborate his cos­mology. To complete this picture, it is necessary to say a few words about al-Fârâbï’s reception of the Greek astronomical sources.

1.2.2. Did al-Fârâbï Write a Commentary on Ptolemy’s Almagest?

In addition to his various commentaries on Aristotle, al-Fârâbï is credited by the bio-bibliographers with a commentary on Ptolemy’s Almagest.[36] Al-Fârâbï had direct access to Ptolemy’s main astronomical works, as both Almagest and Planetary Hypotheses were translated into Arabic during the ninth century.[37] The impact of these Ptolemaic works can be felt throughout his corpus. The arrangement and order of the planets as described by al-Fârâbï, his views on the various motions of the orbs, and his endorsement of the epicycles and eccentrics are all Ptolemaic elements that he integrates in his cosmology. In addition to these foundational Ptolemaic writings, it is possible that al-Fârâbï also had access to more minor Greek astronomical works (such as parts of Aratus’ poem), as well as excerpts from Geminus’ (fl. first century CE) Introduction to the Phenomena, and Simplicius’ commentary on On the Heavens, two works which contain significant passages on the astronomical method.[38] In any case al-Fârâbï’s knowledge of ancient Greek astronomy was substantial enough for him to write about its method and to take its findings into account when elaborating his own cosmology.

The question of whether al-Fârâbï truly penned a commentary (sharh) on Ptolemy’s Almagest is important, since it has a direct bearing on the proper understanding of his cosmology. Yet it is also a com­plicated one that has generated much confusion. In what follows, I describe chronologically the various stages in the history of this puz­zle. According to the medieval bio-bibliographers, the Second Teacher wrote a commentary on Almagest as part of his mathematical output, which both al-Qiftï and Ibn Abï Usaybi'ah mention under the title Sharh kitab al-majistt, although al-Fârâbï himself never refers to it in his extant works. Two manuscripts—one in the British Library in London and the other in the Majlis Library in Tehran—bearing this title and attributed to al-Fârâbï were listed by Sezgin in GAS and by Rosenfeld and îhsanoglu in their prosopographic study of Arabic astronomers.[39] The first attempt to study this work systematically was made by a team of Soviet scholars in the 1970s, which provided a Russian translation of the British Library manuscript, together with a substantial introduction and endnotes.[40] But it was shown subse­quently by B. Goldstein that the British Library manuscript, which Kubesova et al. claim to be the only surviving copy of al-Fârâbï’s Sharh, should in fact be attributed to Ibn Sïnâ.[41] Following Goldstein, I myself can attest that although al-Fârâbï’s name is mentioned on two occasions in the first folios of this manuscript, a comparison of its structure and contents with Ibn Sïnâ’s Tahrir al-majisti as published in the mathematical section of Shifa indicates that we are essentially deal­ing with two versions of the same text.[42]

Furthermore, and to add yet more confusion to this state of affairs, my attempt to obtain a copy of the Majlis Library manuscript proved unsuccessful, as the staff could not find or even identify the alleged manuscript. While I despaired for some time thinking that no exem­plar of Farabi’s commentary had survived, I was informed recently and incidentally that a microfilm copy of the Majlis Library manuscript was made and preserved in the Al-Asad Library in Damascus. Unfortunately, I was not able to consult the Al-Asad Library microfilm in time to include its contents in my study, nor was I even able to ascertain its authenticity. Given the unpredictable history associated with al-Farabi’s commentary, it should be confirmed first, that the Al-Asad copy is indeed a commentary on Ptolemy’s Almagest, and second, that it is by al-Farabi himself and does not consist in another misattribution. In any case, with one manuscript re-attributed and the other one van­ishing, the Al-Asad copy represents for the time being the only hope to retrieve al-Farabi’s putative commentary from obscurity. I can only wish that research on this text be carried out in the near future, be it only to settle a very confusing issue.

The foregoing considerations raise the following question: given the still complete absence of positive manuscript evidence, can a commen­tary on Almagest still be securely attributed to al-Farabi? This question is even more pressing when one realizes that the reports of the Arabic bio-bibliographers are often dubious. Although no definitive answer can be put forward at this point in time, there does not seem to be any a priori reason to reject the authenticity of this attribution. As the examples of Ibn Sina and Nasir al-Din al-Tû si show, it was common for medieval Arabic philosophers to practice astronomy and to summarize or comment on Ptolemy’s Almagest. Moreover, part of al-Farabi’s com­mentary was apparently criticized by a later scholar interested in astronomy.[43] Hence, in the absence of any decisive evidence pointing to the contrary, it should be assumed with some caution that al-Farabi was indeed the author of such a commentary.

Several points concerning al-Farabi’s astronomical activity may be inferred from his composing a commentary on Almagest. First, although he dedicated himself primarily to other sectors of philosophy such as metaphysics and logic, he was sufficiently interested in astronomy to write an entire treatise on Ptolemy’s Almagest. In that sense, al-Farabi was continuing a late antique tradition that harkens back to scholars such as Theon of Alexandria (d. ca. 405 CE), as well as Proclus’ Hypotyposis and Simplicius’ commentary on On the Heavens (two works that contain numerous digressions on Ptolemaic astronomy) and, in the early Islamic period, also includes al-Kindi.[44] All of these thinkers have in common the fact that they took Ptolemaic astronomy into account when redacting their cosmological works, either to criti­cize and ultimately reject it (as did Proclus) or to assimilate some of its theories (as did al-Kindi and al-Farabi). Second, it indicates that al-Farabi was cognizant of the various planetary theories devised by Ptolemy to explain the celestial phenomena, as well as with the techni­cal terminology used in such queries. In fact, astronomical terms such as ‘epicycles’ (aflak al-tadwtr) occasionally appear in al-Farabi’s philo­sophical treatises, thus proving that he had read technical works on the subject.[45] In brief, then, it would seem that the Second Teacher enter­tained a genuine interest in mathematical astronomy, even though little evidence on this aspect of his work has survived.

This being said, it is difficult to define the exact nature of al-Farabi’s astronomical activity. Did he limit himself to writing a commentary on Almagest, or did he, like Ibn Sina, carry out observations and col­lect astronomical data? Al-Farabi’s remarks in Müstqâ on the value of observation and experience in astronomy and on the relation between scientific theory and practice indicate that his astronomical interest may have included a practical dimension.[46] This is also sup­ported biographically by his protracted stay in Baghdad, a vibrant center for astronomical research during the ninth and tenth centuries.[47] The available evidence nevertheless does not allow us to confirm this hypothesis.

1.3. Early Islamic Cosmological Trends

Al-Farabi’s cosmological theories should also be contextualized in terms of the religious, philosophical, and scientific activity that devel­oped during the first centuries of Islam. In this regard at least three important elements come into play: traditional Islamic cosmology, the philosophical precedents of al-Kindi and Abû Bakr al-Razi, and the development of an Arabic astronomical tradition.

1.3.1.    Traditional Islamic Cosmology and Early kaldm

The first Islamic centuries witnessed the emergence of a traditional cosmology that has its roots in various passages of the Qur’an and in some hadiths. This ‘Qur’anic’ or ‘traditionalist’ cosmological model quickly became widespread in Islamic society, due to the exalted status of these texts in Muslim worship and scholarship. It also gradually infiltrated other Arabic literary genres such as poetry, creeds, tafsir, sirah, and mi’raj accounts. Briefly, it presents the universe as consisting of seven superimposed earths and heavens, with God’s throne (arsh) and footstool (kursi) occupying the space above it.[48] There is some ambiguity concerning the shape of these seven heavens, which could be either domed or complete orbs surrounding the earth, depending on one’s interpretation of the relevant verses. The celestial bodies, i.e., the sun, moon, and stars, occupy the space of the lowest heaven and move through the firmament by gliding in their orbits, while celestial oceans or rivers encircle the entire structure. As for the earth, it is pre­sumably flat and is compared to a carpet that has been spread by God. Finally, it is important to stress that all of these heavenly entities were created by God for the welfare and benefit of human beings and to help them perform their various daily tasks and activities.[49] This model (Figure 1), which assumed the role of a paradigm for many Muslim theologians and traditionalists, endured well into the early modern period, as can be seen in the works of the fifteenth-century author al-Suyûti.[50]

God's Throne ( 'arsh) and footstool (kurst)

 

Figure 1: The Quranic cosmological model consisting of the seven heavens and earths

A quick comparison between al-Fârâbï’s cosmology and this Quranic model enables one to perceive the gap that separates them and the very different sources and traditions from which they stem. While the Qur anic model is indebted to previous Biblical sources and ultimately to ancient Mesopotamian culture and religion, the roots of al-Fârâbï’s model, in contrast, can be traced back to the Greek philosophical and scientific traditions of late antiquity.[51] In addition, and contrary to many other Arabic thinkers, one does not perceive in his works any effort to reconcile the Ptolemaic worldview with the Quranic scheme of seven earths and seven heavens and with Islamic cosmology in general.[52] On the contrary, some of al-Fârâbï’s theories, such as the ensoulment of the heavenly bodies, the eternity of celestial motion, and the causation of the separate intellects, are not compatible with the tra­ditional Islamic understanding of the universe and of God’s relation to His creation.

Although al-Fârâbï shows no interest for the Quranic cosmological model, one should not conclude that the Islamic theological tradition was not instrumental in shaping some aspects of his cosmology, be it only in reaction to it. Indeed, the model outlined above seems to have been prevalent in traditionalist Muslim circles and not among the the­ological groups that assimilated some aspects of Greek philosophy, especially the Mutazilites and some Ash'arites. Although little is known about the early cosmology of these theologians, S. Pines, H. A. Wolfson, and A. Dhanani have shown that kalam was already actively engaged in physical and cosmological pursuits during al-Fârâbï’s life and that the Muslim theologians debated among themselves and against the phi­losophers about various physical issues.[53] It is therefore not unreason­able to surmise that al-Fârâbï was cognizant of these theologians’ position on important topics such as the creation of the universe, atom­ism and the nature of celestial matter, as well as the ontological status of the celestial bodies, even though it is objectively difficult to establish concrete links and textual parallels between these thinkers. In this con­nection, U. Rudolph has in two recent papers argued that al-Fârâbï was aware of some of the debates taking place in the theological circles of his day and that there is a structural overlap between his treatises and contemporary theological works.[54] As J. van Ess argued some time ear­lier, it is possible that he intended to refute the views of individual theo­logians hailing from Khurâsân, notably Ibn al-Râwandï and Abû l-Qâsim al-Balkhï.[55] Indeed, the doctrines of these Khurâsânï theolo­gians had spread to a geographic area comparatively closer to al-Fârâbï’s homeland than to the Abbâsid capital.[56]

In addition to the Muslim mutakallimün, it is possible that the doc­trines of the Christian theologians inspired some of al-Fârâbï’s ideas with regard to cosmogony. Al-Fârâbï’s formative years, spent in the company of the Baghdad Christian commentators and philosophers, not only influenced his understanding of Aristotle, but may also have been decisive in shaping some of his views on the question of the crea­tion of the world. It is well known that al-Fârâbï in Jam’ attributes a creationist position to Aristotle, a view which may also be defended in some of his other treatises. Assuming for the time being that these writings are authentic, can the view they put forth be attributed to the influence of theological ideas on al-Fârâbï’s early intellectual forma­tion? While this question will be discussed in detail in chapter 3, suffice it to say here that the dialectic between the doctrines of the philoso­phers and those of the Christian and Muslim theologians is an impor­tant element of the early history of Arabic thought and should be borne in mind when analyzing the works of the falasifah.[57]

1.3.2.    Early Arabic Philosophical Precedents

The role of previous Arabic philosophers, especially al-Kindï and Abû Bakr al-Râzï, in shaping the approach and content of the Second Teacher’s cosmology represents another important aspect of the prob­lem. They were the two most outstanding figures of the pre-Fârâbïan Arabic philosophical tradition and had already elaborated complex cosmologies, which, like al-Fârâbï’s, assimilated Greek ideas and theo­ries to address the theological and philosophical problems of their day. Al-Kindï plays a particularly important role in our story, for to our knowledge he is the first Arabic philosopher to develop a full-fledged cosmological model that relies on a substantial amount of astronomi­cal data and to show some interest for this science. Al-Kindï wrote extensively on cosmology and was particularly interested in astron­omy and astrology, as his numerous writings on these subjects testify.[58] Like al-Fârâbï, al-Kindï is said to have commented on Almagest, and again like al-Fârâbï, he integrates a large share of astronomical, and more specifically Ptolemaic, material in his treatises. Furthermore, he attempted a systematic reconciliation of Ptolemaic astronomy and Aristotelian and Neoplatonic physical and metaphysical theories.[59] This philosophical approach is also pursued with utmost dedication by al-Farabi in his own cosmological works, although it is unclear in his case whether he knew the true origin of the Arabic Neoplatonic texts he read.[60] Finally, key to both of these two thinkers’ cosmologies were the Neoplatonica arabica, which significantly shaped their interpreta­tion of Aristotle and also provided important concepts that were used as starting points for independent elaborations.

Al-Kindi may be said to have anticipated some important features of al-Farabi’s and Ibn Sinas cosmological projects. He was perhaps the first to address some of the challenges and problems that these thinkers dealt with, such as the place of astronomy and astrology in philosophy. As I will argue in chapter 3, al-Kindi may also have exercised a pro­found doctrinal influence on al-Farabi’s early years, especially with regard to the cosmological model al-Farabi adhered to during his stud­ies with the Christian thinkers in Baghdad. Although the impact of the works emerging from the al-Kindi circle may not have had a pro­found impact on the Christian Peripatetics (judging from what remains of their corpora), it conversely played a decisive role in the case of al-Farabi’s philosophy.[61] One example of al-Kindi’s potential influence pertains to al-Fârâbi’s early theory of celestial matter and its relation to the creation of the world, which may be directly indebted to al-Kindi. Al-Fârâbï’s discovery of al-Kindi’s philosophy may have occurred before his arrival in Baghdad, since after his death in ca. 867 CE al-Kindi’s works and ideas had spread through his disciples to the regions of Khurâsân, which the young al-Fârâbi presumably crossed on his way to the Abbâsid capital.[62] The story of how al-Fârâbi may first have assimilated and then gradually broken away from this Kindian tradition is one of the concerns of the present study.

Yet with regard to al-Fârâbi’s ‘standard’ cosmology, i.e., the one expounded in the works whose authenticity is not debated, such as Ára and Siyasah, and in spite of some basic structural resemblances, the two thinkers worked within quite different methodological perspec­tives. They also articulated drastically divergent cosmological doctrines on key points such as the creation of the world and the motion of the planets and orbs. Al-Kindi’s worldview follows that of the Greek tradi­tion in many respects, but it also contains distinctly Islamic character­istics, which are for the most part lacking in al-Fârâbi. For instance, al-Kindi holds that the entire heaven obeys God’s command, which it expresses in its regular, harmonious circular motion. Although it is intrinsically incorruptible, the heavens are not eternal and will pass away when God wills.[63] Hence, in addition to its subtle combination of Ptolemaic, Aristotelian, and Neoplatonic features, what distinguishes al-Kindi’s cosmology is the omnipresence and omnipotence of God. God not only brings the universe into being, but He also inspires the heavenly motion, and He will eventually destroy His creation. What we witness, then, is a cosmology subordinated, so to speak, to a theol­ogy, in which God is presented as the only real and eternal being.

This cosmological approach was no doubt shaped by al-Kindï’s belief in the fundamental compatibility between Islam and philosophy. As will be shown later on, the cosmology al-Fârâbï articulates in his late trea­tises is radically different from the model outlined above, primarily because it does not endow the Godhead with such an active role in the creation and governing of the heavens.

The question of why al-Fârâbï generally ignores his predecessor al-Kindi and never explicitly mentions or cites his works requires an explanation, especially since al-Kindï had elaborated the most coher­ent cosmological model before al-Fârâbï’s time. One explanation has to do with the lack of availability or the limited diffusion of al-Kindï’s writings in tenth-century Baghdad. For al-Kindï, whose career reached a peak under al-Ma’mûn and al-Mutasim, subsequently fell in disfa­vour under al-Mutawakkil, under whose rule many of his treatises were likely destroyed or dispersed as a result of the jealousy and scheming of courtiers. Al-Kindï’s posthumous philosophical influence extended primarily to the north-eastern parts of the Islamic lands, to Transoxania and Khurâsân rather than Baghdad, areas whence his most distin­guished disciples hailed.

Yet this interpretation is not entirely satisfactory, for al-Kindï’s teach­ings were transmitted well into the tenth century and to thinkers who dwelled in Baghdad, as can be seen in the case of al-Amirï (d. 992 CE).[64] Moreover, the fact that the Kindïan tradition flourished espe­cially in geographical areas that were comparatively close to al-Fârâbï’s homeland and which he at any rate would have had to cross on his way to Baghdad also argues against it. It is therefore more plausible that al-Fârâbï’s silence was deliberate and intended as a mark of disapproval concerning both the method and content of al-Kindï’s philosophy. If the hypothesis defended later on in this book according to which al-Fârâbï was first influenced by al-Kindï and subsequently departed from his fundamental views on cosmology and theology is correct, then it is understandable that al-Fârâbï would later have ignored this thinker. Indeed, some of the Second Teacher’s mature doctrines may be construed as implicit responses to the Kindïan tradition on specific issues such as the creation of the world and the cause of celestial motion.

Turning to Abû Bakr al-Râzï, we are dealing in this case with a very different kind of cosmology, whose sources are somewhat obscure, although they evoke numerous features of Platonic philosophy. Unlike al-Kindï, al-Râzï is not a creationist in the orthodox theological sense and upholds instead the existence of five eternal principles that are the cause of all the other beings: soul, matter, time, space, and God. Al-Râzï thus asserted the eternity and uncausedness of various cosmic princi­ples apart from the Godhead, a relatively rare position in Arabic intel­lectual history. The universe taken as a whole, however, is not eternal and undergoes periods of destruction and recreation out of a primeval state, due to the activity of the demiurge, who mixes soul and matter together to form the various beings. Moreover, although few writings by al-Râzï have survived, it seems that he was not as interested as al-Kindï and al-Fârâbï in the nature of the celestial bodies and in astronomy. A quick glance at al-Râzï’s cosmology shows that it differs substantially, both in its doctrines and sources, from al-Fârâbï’s cos­mology and that it does not address the issues that were later to occupy the Second Teacher, such as celestial intellection and causality. It there­fore could not have served as a model for it except in the negative sense that al-Fârâbï may have consciously reacted to the main cosmological tenets formulated by al-Râzï.[65]

Hence, in spite of the importance that al-Kindï, al-Râzï, and al-Fârâbï attribute to cosmology and the fact that each one of them elaborated a quite original cosmological model, their systems have little in common in their essentials, a fact which testifies to the vitality and diversity of cosmological speculation during the ninth and tenth centuries in Islam. Such are their differences that one may even speak here of three differ­ent cosmological paradigms, which rely on different sources and prin­ciples, and which experienced diverging fates in later Islamic thought. While al-Râzï’s intriguing Platonizing worldview virtually disappeared with its originator, al-Kindï’s and especially al-Fârâbï’s cosmological models (including their views on creation) were destined to have a pro­found impact on later generations of thinkers.

It should be stressed that although al-Fârâbï does not mention al-Kindï and al-Râzï by name in his extant writings, it is likely that he knew their doctrines well. Not only did these thinkers evolve in the same cultural and geographical sphere, but many of al-Farabi’s theories may be seen as responses to specific ideas developed by these earlier thinkers. After all, al-Kindi and al-Razi were the authors of the main Arabic cosmological models al-Farabi could have turned to in his youth. What this indicates is that al-Farabi was able—partly due to the sources he consulted, and partly due to his own engagement with these scholars’ legacy—to elaborate a new cosmological model that departed substantially from that of his illustrious predecessors. In turn, this sug­gests that al-Farabi’s cosmology was elaborated over a protracted period of time and through a process of assimilation, rejection, and transfor­mation whose various facets need to be carefully reconstructed.

1.3.3. The Growth of ‘ilm al-hayah

Finally, our picture of the early Islamic context in which al-Farabi’s cos­mology took root should include some comments on Arabic astron­omy during the eighth, ninth, and tenth centuries. Although there existed a traditional form of astronomical practice among the Arabs of the pre-Islamic era, mathematical astronomy in Islam developed directly out of the translation of Indian, Persian, and especially Greek scientific works.[66] Early Arabic astronomers regarded Ptolemy as the astronomical authority par excellence, and his main work, Almagest, defined the methodological horizon within which they operated. This, however, did not prevent them from modifying some features of the Ptolemaic legacy and from significantly expanding the corpus of observational data they inherited from antiquity. Indeed, Arabic astronomers placed a new emphasis on observation and systematically corrected the astronomical tables they inherited from India and Greece. Vast observational programs were patronized and implemented by some of the Abbasid caliphs, especially al-Ma’mûn, which resulted in the composition of new ztjes or astronomical tables. In addition, reputed Arabic astronomers such as al-Farghani (d. after 861 CE), Thabit ibn Qurra (d. 901 CE), and al-Battani (d. 929 CE) were actively engaged both in spreading Ptolemy’s theories through their various writings and in revising or perfecting some of the findings of previous scientists. Their manuals contributed to the dissemination of astro­nomical knowledge and of the geocentric model and its system of nested orbs among educated laypersons and the social elites. It is of lit­tle surprise, then, that the contemporary philosophers and many theo­logians shared this common scientific worldview.

Furthermore, Arabic astronomers were aware of the need to improve Ptolemy’s explanation of how the mathematical models posited by astronomy relate to the physical world. This led them to reflect on vari­ous aspects of the astronomical method and to theorize on the relation between astronomy and the other sciences, particularly natural phi­losophy. In most cases, their goal was to harmonize physics and astron­omy and to develop geometric models of planetary motion that would fully correspond to physical reality. Although this trend developed to its full extent in the post-classical hayah literature and found an out­standing embodiment in the works of al-Tûsï, early Arabic astrono­mers significantly prepared the way for this advance.[67]

It is this latter aspect in the development of ‘ilm al-hayah that is relevant to our analysis of al-Fârâbï’s cosmology, since this particular endeavour on the part of Arabic astronomers overlaps with the early history of falsafah. Indeed, both groups reflected on the relation and interactions between the various sciences and on the principles of the astronomical discipline in particular. Now, this is a question that also preoccupied the Second Teacher. Not only did he write works in which he discusses the classification, status, and method of the philosophical sciences (including astronomy)—as in Ihsa ’, Burhan, and Müstqâ—but al-Fârâbï’s own attempt at providing a cosmological synthesis betrays a similar concern for harmonizing the latest astronomical findings of the age with the main principles of Aristotelian physics. Thus, the Arabic astronomers and al-Fârâbï were engaged in what was in many ways a similar project, an unsurprising fact given the general scientific priori­ties of the age and the frequent interplay between ‘ilm al-hayah and falsafah throughout their history.[68] Like the Arabic astronomers, al-Fârâbï regarded Ptolemy as the foremost authority in the field of astronomy, in the same manner that he held Aristotle as a paragon in the study of logic and philosophy. This means that al-Fârâbï would have felt the need to reconcile these two authorities. But unlike the case of the astronomers, who limited their efforts to the field of astronomy, in the case of al-Fârâbï and later Ibn Sïnâ, this problem of reconciling Ptolemy and Aristotle had offshoots that extended to many other parts of their philosophy, as can be seen in their treatment of celestial motion, causation, and intellection.

The output of ninth- and tenth-century Arabic astronomers enables us to gauge the progress achieved in mathematical astronomy during the early Islamic period and indicates the extent to which Ptolemaic material had been assimilated and naturalized within Islamic culture, including falsafah. These astronomical works represent potentially important sources which the Second Teacher and other philosophers may have consulted. But precisely for this reason, and because of the high standard of this science during al-Fârâbï’s time, it is not always possible to gauge how much of this thinker’s astronomical knowledge is derived directly from the Ptolemaic texts as opposed to through the intermediary of Arabic authors. This is the case, notably, of Planetary Hypotheses, Ptolemy’s second most important astronomical treatise, which is not mentioned expressly by al-Fârâbï in any of his writings, but which seems to underlie some of his cosmological theories, espe­cially his theory of planetary motion (see ch. 4). Al-Fârâbï could have read parts of it in the form of a short Arabic recension or alternatively the contents of this work could have reached him through the interme­diary of contemporary Arabic astronomical texts. This being said, al-Fârâbï does not mention any contemporary Arabic astronomer by name, and for this reason we may surmise that he had first hand access to the Arabic translations of Ptolemy, including at least parts of Planetary Hypotheses.[69]

This overview of the Greek and early Arabic textual and historical contexts places al-Fârâbï squarely at the confluence of various scien­tific, philosophical, and theological traditions, all of which, it may be surmised, left an imprint on the Second Teacher’s method and thought. In view of the foregoing, there can be little doubt that al-Fârâbï’s cos­mological horizon extended beyond the legacy of Greek philosophy and was informed by a number of other intellectual factors stem­ming from his own cultural environment. Al-Farabi’s cosmology was shaped just as much by early Muslim and Christian theology and by the development of Arabic astronomy and philosophy as by the transla­tions of the Greek philosophical and astronomical texts that he read. This diversity of stimuli and outlooks can help to explain al-Farabi’s intention to elaborate a new and state-of-the-art cosmological model, both with regard to its synthetic tendency and to the fact that it may often be seen as a reaction to other cosmological ideas endorsed by his predecessors or contemporaries—at any rate, this represents the working hypothesis of the present book.

1.4. Cosmology in al-Fârâbï’s Philosophical Treatises and the Problem with Mahdi’s Hypothesis

Al- Farabi also discussed cosmological questions in independent works in addition to his various commentaries on Aristotle and Ptolemy. However, only a fragment of this output is extant. With regard to the physical works, there are substantial citations from his treatise On Changing Beings, as well as the treatise Against Philoponus. While al-Farabi’s Physics commentary was probably written in the style of the late antique exegetical tradition and consisted of lemmata accompa­nied by his personal remarks, On Changing Beings was an independent treatise loosely based on Physics 8 that covered a wide diversity of phys­ical topics, such as motion, time, and the nature of sublunary beings. Both the Physics commentary and On Changing Beings are frequently mentioned by later authors, such as Ibn Bajjah, Maimonides, and Ibn Rushd, which shows that al-Farabi’s views on natural philosophy were widely read by later Muslim and Jewish authors.[70] As for Against Philoponus, it is a polemical treatise on the subject of aether that was intended as a reply to the philosopher and theologian John Philoponus. It represents a valuable source for our purposes, in spite of the difficulty of its interpretation.[71]

It should be noted that in addition to these works, al-Fârâbï com­posed several other, albeit no longer extant, treatises which addressed specific cosmological issues. This was the case of Kitab ft anna harakat al-falak sarmadiyyah, Kitab al-nujum, and of Kitab al-tathtrat al-ulwiyyah, three works mentioned by Ibn al-Qiftï and which dealt with specific cosmological issues.[72] Finally, one should mention the intriguing reference to a Risalah ft hudüth al-‘dlam given by Brockel- mann in GAL.[73] Since al-Fârâbï is laconic on various key issues of his cosmology, such as his theory of celestial motion and the issue of the eternity of the world, the loss of these works is regrettable.

Fortunately, however, al-Fârâbï provides lengthy cosmological descriptions in other works that have survived, especially in his emana- tionist treatises, Ara and Siyasah. Thanks largely to these two works, it is possible, on the basis of the information they contain, to reconstruct his cosmology with a satisfactory degree of precision. The emanationist treatises, by far our most important sources for al-Fârâbï’s cosmology, contain two main sections: the first one, broadly speaking, deals with metaphysical and cosmological issues; the second one focuses on human psychology, prophetology, and virtuous and corrupt political entities. This structure is not fortuitous: the microcosm of the individ­ual human being and of human societies should ideally reflect the order and harmony of the universe, a sequence which shows the impact of cosmology on al-Fârâbï’s political theories. In the first part of these treatises, al-Fârâbï provides a detailed description of the heavens and of the principles governing them, intertwining physical, metaphysical, and astronomical ideas. He devotes many pages to the substance of the celestial bodies and their hierarchical order, as well as to the nature and activity of the celestial souls and separate intellects. These entities, which lie beyond the orb of the moon, are in a sense the counterpart of the beings in the sublunary realm, and their perfect harmony and order stand as a model for the ideal human life. This explains the close sym­metry al-Fârâbï establishes between cosmology, human psychology, and the ideal political organization. These works testify not only that Ptolemy’s influence on al-Fârâbï extended beyond the latter’s commen­tary on Almagest, but also that it was integrated in a larger cosmologi­cal framework drawing on a variety of other intellectual trends.

At this point it is necessary to address an objection formulated by M. Mahdi regarding al-Fârâbï’s cosmology and the contents of Ara and Siyasah, which, if true, would deprive these treatises of much of their philosophical value. Mahdi contends that Árü’ and Siyasah do not express al-Fârâbï’s true cosmological doctrines and should be inter­preted instead as political metaphors or pseudo-scientific accounts addressed to the inhabitants of the virtuous city. As Mahdi writes, these treatises do not “embody either Alfarabi’s theoretical philosophy or his practical philosophy, but are only examples of the kind of regimes that can be constructed by political philosophy.”[74] In other words, the cosmology described by al-Fârâbï fulfills a purely rhetorical func­tion and is devoid of a scientific foundation. It may best be called, as Mahdi suggests, a “political cosmology.”[75] Central to Mahdi’s argument is the claim that Árü’ and Siyasah are the only works that draw on Neoplatonic doctrine and that develop an emanationist system, while al-Fârâbï’s “scientific or philosophic works proper” are free of any such elements.[76]

Mahdi is undoubtedly right in pointing to the political relevance of al-Fârâbï’s cosmological theories. Indeed, they form the backdrop against which his prophetology and political system unfold and bear an intricate link with other aspects of his thought. But it is important to stress that it is al-Fârâbï’s cosmology and metaphysics that are the foun­dation on which politics can be developed, and not vice versa, as Mahdi would have it. This point has been aptly shown by P Vallat in his recent monograph, which redefines al-Fârâbï’s political ideas in light of the late antique, especially Neoplatonic, metaphysical tradition.[77] It is also borne out by textual evidence. Al-Fârâbï repeatedly stresses in his works the primacy of the theoretical sciences and their demonstrative method, the certain knowledge they produce, and the fact that the practical disciplines and politics are to be modeled on them.[78] On the other hand, al-Fârâbï nowhere states that his cosmology should be con­strued as a political metaphor, nor is there any textual evidence in his works to support this view.

As will be argued in various sections of this book, al-Fârâbï addresses the same issues and articulates identical cosmological theories— including what Mahdi calls emanation—in some of his other treatises, such as Müstqâ, Falsafat Aristü ta lis, and Risalah ft l-‘aql, which bear no concrete link to politics. This shows that the emanationist treatises do not differ radically from the rest of al-Fârâbï’s output and that Mahdi’s division between “popular” and “philosophical” works, or between “Neoplatonic” and “Aristotelian” works, is unfounded. Far from being a mere by-product of al-Fârâbï’s political reflection, the cosmological ideas presented in Ára and Siyasah are in fact a direct continuity of the Greek philosophical (especially commentatorial) tradition of late antiquity, and they may be seen as original re-elaborations of old philo­sophical issues and problems. A study of some of the key cosmological concepts that al-Fârâbï discusses shows that he engaged critically with the Greco-Arabic sources and that he elaborated his theories through a process of criticism and assimilation, the product of which appears in these texts.

Furthermore, the fact that these treatises incorporate much of the astronomical knowledge available during al-Fârâbï’s time (ch. 2, 1.1. and 1.2.) indicates that he made conscious efforts to root his cosmol­ogy in a valid scientific approach. Like Aristotle and Ibn Sïnâ, al-Fârâbï was aware that a successful cosmological model could only be devised if one paid close attention to astronomical findings and to how these relate to physical and metaphysical theories. The very fact that later Arabic thinkers, such as Ibn Sïnâ and al-Kirmânï, considered al-Fârâbï’s cosmology a serious and viable philosophical model and adopted some of its main features indicates clearly that these thinkers did not inter­pret it merely as a political metaphor, but rather as a coherent sys­tem grounded in scientific theory. This was also the opinion of al- Ghazâlï, who deemed it necessary to compose an entire book, Tahafut al-falasifah, to refute the cosmological model of these philosophers.

Finally, a word must be said about the structure and title of these works. In this regard, Mahdi’s decision to call the emanationist treatises “political” is reductionist, as they are divided into two main sections, only the latter of which deals properly speaking (and only partly) with politics. As for the first section, it discusses the various physical and metaphysical principles that constitute and govern the universe, thereby stressing the primacy of metaphysics and cosmology over politics both in the order of existence and in the order of philosophical instruction. In this respect, and as U. Rudolph stressed, the title of these works has been too often distorted. With respect to Ára, for instance, the theories discussed are primarily not (political) “views” or “opinions” («ra’), but rather philosophical “principles” (mabadï), which only subsequently can be expressed in terms of opinions (ara) in a political context; hence, the full title of the treatise: Mabadt ara ahl al-madtnah al-fâdilah.[79] And in the case of Siyasah, its alternative title Mabadt l-mawjüdât seems more appropriate, since in this case as well the work begins by enumerating the various ontological principles that underlie the universe. It is only subsequently that al-Fârâbï explains how these may serve as axioms for the views and imitative practices performed in human societies. For all of the reasons discussed above, Mahdi’s inter­pretation of al-Fârâbï’s cosmology seems unjustifiably reductionist.[80]

Apart from the emanationist treatises, other works by the Second Teacher also shed valuable light on various aspects of his cosmology, both in terms of method and content, especially Ft l-aql, Müstqâ, Fusü l, Tahstl, and Ihsa’. These works were not written with the express pur­pose of discussing cosmological issues, but they contain much, albeit scattered, material that should be assembled and carefully examined. Also noteworthy are two treatises on astrology, which will be analyzed in detail in a later section, as well as some of al-Fârâbï’s logical works, such as K. al-qiyas, Fbârah, and Burhan, which provide insight into his method and key scientific concepts that appear in his cosmological dis­cussions, such as experience and induction.

In addition to this group of authentic texts, there is a cluster of works whose authorship is unclear or has recently been challenged by scholars. It consists chiefly of Jam, Jawabat, Ithbat, Taltqat, ‘Uyun, and Daawa, all of which will figure prominently in the forthcoming analysis. Indeed, the motivation for studying these works is twofold. First, some of them, such as Jam, play a potentially crucial role in the modern understanding of al-Fârâbï’s philosophy, and they have in this respect been the object of considerable scholarly attention in recent years, which must be taken into account. Yet in my view, some key aspects of their cosmological doctrine have been misconstrued, which calls for a continuation of the ongoing dialogue on their nature and authenticity. Second, these works discuss important and sometimes strikingly original cosmological doctrines that are well worth analyz­ing for their own sake, and which are of interest not only with regard to al-Fârâbï’s cosmology, but with regard to early Arabic cosmology in general.

All in all, then, al-Fârâbï discusses cosmological topics in various types of works and in different kinds of philosophical contexts. In spite of the fragmentary state of the Fârâbïan corpus, especially with regard to its commentaries, the evidence contained in these works, when added to the reports of later medieval authors, enable one to recon­struct a relatively satisfactory picture of his cosmology, in spite of the fact that some links are inevitably missing. The literary diversity of al-Fârâbï’s output can be explained by the fact that he was the recipient of a complex and multifaceted cosmological tradition, which was encapsulated in various kinds of philosophical and astronomical works. This diversity of textual genres is mirrored by the diversity of the disci­plines that participate in the cosmological inquiry and by the complex­ity of al-Fârâbï’s philosophical method. It is to these issues that I now wish to turn.

2. Astronomy and its Place in the Philosophical Curriculum

The previous paragraphs helped to delineate some of the main trends prevalent in the intellectual milieu frequented by al-Fârâbï, as well as the nature of his output. One important aspect of the heritage under­lined above is the corpus of Greek astronomical texts translated into Arabic during the ninth and tenth centuries, which played an impor­tant role in shaping the faldsifah’s cosmology. Like many Greek phi­losophers before him, al-Fârâbï believes that it is necessary to take into account the findings accumulated by the astronomers in order to elab­orate a valid cosmological and metaphysical system. How did he per­ceive the place of astronomy in philosophy and how did he understand the method of this science? My aim in the following paragraphs is to shed light on al-Fârâbï’s conception of the method and epistemic foundations of astronomy, on how it may benefit the philosophical enterprise, and on how it relates to the other philosophical sciences, particularly physics and metaphysics. Medieval thinkers in general relied on all or a combination of these disciplines to elaborate their cosmology, but they were often in disagreement as to their respective scope and method. Following these various lines of inquiry will enable us to situate al-Fârâbï within the history of Greek and Arabic astron­omy and provide a case study of an early Muslim philosopher’s knowl­edge of this science. Before doing so, however, it is necessary to address the important question of how al-Fârâbï perceived the relation between astronomy and astrology.

2.1. Astronomy and Astrology and their Subject Matter

The conception of how astronomy relates to astrology has varied con­siderably from culture to culture over the centuries. In the case of early and classical Islam, these two disciplines were not always clearly distin­guished, but many thinkers were aware of a fundamental epistemologi­cal gap between the mathematics-based method of astronomy and the more speculative approach of astrology. While some Muslim authors practiced these two disciplines conjointly during their lifetime without worrying unduly about their relation, others vehemently advocated a demarcation between astronomy and astrology on the basis either of their incompatible method or of their different rapport to religious orthodoxy.

One of the turning points in the history of astronomy’s emancipa­tion from astrology in Islam is usually situated in the eleventh cen­tury and explained in terms of the advances made in mathematical astronomy and the appearance of more elaborate classifications of the sciences. Ibn Sïnâ is often hailed as a key figure in this transition. He was one of the first thinkers to distinguish the two disciplines conceptually and terminologically, and the systematic criticism of astrology he articulated contributed to shaping future perceptions on the topic.[81] Ibn Sïnâ regarded astronomy as an independent and well-delineated science possessing its own subject matter and method primarily defined by its use of mathematical proof. In his Risalah ft aqsam al-ulum al-‘aqliyyah, for instance, he describes astronomy (‘ilm al-hayah) as a mathematical science (‘ilm riyadt) that is exclusively concerned with the external aspects of superlunary phenomena, while astrology (ahkam al-nujum) is classified as a sub-branch of the physical science (al-ta btiyyah.).[82] In proposing such a scheme, the shaykh al-rats departed from the earlier classifications of the sciences devised by al-Khwarizmi, al-Farabi, and others, which had subsumed astrology and astronomy under a single, overarching science known as ‘ilm al-nujum[83] From Ibn Sina onward, ‘ilm al-hayah gradually replaced ‘ilm al-nujum in the mainstream philosophical and theological tradi­tions and came to refer exclusively to mathematical astronomy.[84] [85]

It has not been sufficiently emphasized, however, that many features of Ibn Sinas anti-astrology position were anticipated nearly a century earlier by al-Farabi, who in several of his works had attempted to sepa­rate astronomy from astrology as well as to distinguish between the valid and invalid parts of astrology itself. Starting with Ihsa’, which contains al-Farabi’s most systematic description and classification of the various philosophical disciplines, one reads that the “science of the stars” (‘ilm al-nujum) is one of the mathematical sciences and com­prises two parts: astrology or rather, judicial astrology (‘ilm ahkam al-nujum), and mathematical astronomy (‘ilm al-nujum al-ta‘ltmt)7 The second part, astronomy proper, investigates the exterior aspects of the heavenly bodies, those that pertain to numbers and measurements, such as the sizes, distances, and motions of the planets. As for the first part, astrology, it focuses on the heavenly indications and signs that enable humans to predict future events and to know past and present events. Al-Farabi therefore draws a distinction between astronomy and astrology in Ihsa ’ that is based on both terminology and subject matter, but he does not take the extra step to separate the two disciplines. Rather, his classification of the sciences presents them as two branches of a single, integrated discipline called ‘ilm al-nujum, and in that sense it differs significantly from Ibn Sinas account. At any rate, this classifi­cation and the use of the generic expression ’ilm al-nujum seem to have been widespread during this period, and they can also be found in the works of other authors such as al-Khwarizmi and the Ikhwan al-Safa’.[86]

Al-Farabi elaborates on the various sub-branches of astrology in two treatises that he wrote to this effect: Risalah fï fadïlat al-’ulüm wa-l- sind’at, also known as Maqalah fïma yasihhu wa-layasihhu min ahkam al-nujum, and Maqalah fï l-jihah allatïyasihhu ‘alayhâ l-qawlfï ahkam al-nujum[87] Before I examine these treatises, it would be helpful to con­textualize them within the Abbasid society of the ninth and tenth cen­turies and thus to illuminate the circumstances in which these works originated. The early Abbasid caliphs, such as al-Mansûr, al-Mahdi, Hârûn al-Rashid, and al-Ma’mûn, were staunch supporters of astrol­ogy and hosted numerous astrologers at their court in Baghdad.[88] These astrologers fulfilled the purpose of advising the caliphs and their entou­rage of auspicious dates for the realization of important undertakings, such as military battles, the signing of treaties, the foundation of cities, etc. At a more intimate level, they also provided genethlialogical infor­mation about high-ranked individuals and insight into their future accomplishments. Apart from the court astrologers themselves, some of the prominent figures of Abbasid intellectual life, such as the Mu'tazili theologian al-Nazzam (d. ca. 845 CE) and the philosopher al-Kindi, fully embraced astrological pursuits and even wrote treatises on the topic. Together with the foremost practitioners of this science, such as Abû Ma'shar al-Balkhi (d. 886 CE) (also a student of al-Kindi), they defended the legitimacy and methodological soundness of astrol­ogy, while at the same time aiming to establish it on a more secure Aristotelian theoretical foundation.[89]

Yet not everyone in Abbasid society recognized the soundness of astrology and the trustworthiness of the court astrologers: this was the case of the legal scholar al-Shâfi‘ï (d. 820 CE) and the theologians Abû l-Hudhayl (d. ca. 840 CE) and al-Ash'ari (d. 935 CE). A debate on the status of astrology involving the Mu'tazili Abû l-Hudhayl allegedly took place at the court of the Caliph al-Mamûn, during which Abû l-Hud- hayl criticized the astrologers’ claim to know future events.[90] Regardless of whether this debate actually took place, it illustrates a certain tension in the Muslim perception of astrology during this period.

It is this tense and contradictory situation with respect to the status of astrology that al-Farabi would have found upon his arrival in Baghdad and, later on, at the courts of Sayf al-Dawlah in Damascus and Aleppo. In fact, we know that al-Qabisi (d. 967 CE), one of the great astrologers of the classical period of Islam, dedicated an astro­logical treatise to Sayf al-Dawlah himself, thus indicating the latter’s patronage of this art.[91] This state of affairs may have motivated al-Farabi to articulate his own views on the subject and to clarify both the method of astrology and the place it should occupy in the philosophical cur­riculum. In this regard, we know that at least one of his treatises on the subject (discussed below) was written at the express request of a scholar in need of help to distinguish the valid and invalid aspects of the astro­logical discipline.

Returning to the two astrological treatises mentioned above, they articulate several important points that should be discussed in detail. One notices from the outset that al-Farabi uses the terms ahkam « al-nujum to refer to astrology both in the title and body of these two works, and thus that their terminology overlaps with that of Ihsa’. This is significant insofar as it shows that the Second Teacher used this for­mula consistently and that he differentiated astrology from astronomy, which he called in contrast either ‘ilm al-nujüm al-talïmï (as in Ihsa’ and Burhan) or ‘ilm al-hayah (in a minor treatise).[92] In terms of their contents, the main thrust of the argument put forth in these two works is that only some aspects of astrology are sound and permissible from a philosophical point of view, namely, those that study the physical influence of the heavenly bodies on sublunary beings. The main exam­ple given by al-Fârâbï is the effect that the heavens have on growth and corruption. As he explains, the celestial bodies cause heat (sukhünah or hararah) to develop in the sublunary world as a result of the light they emit.[93] In this case, the scientist can rely on observations (arsad) and experience (tajribah) to study these effects, two concepts which, as will be shown shortly, also play an important role in the astronomical method.[94] This sub-branch of astrology would nowadays correspond to a combination of biology and climatology, and in view of this it is easier to understand retrospectively why Ibn Sïnâ transferred astrology to the field of natural philosophy.[95] Al-Fârâbï is furthermore willing to accept the theory that the celestial bodies have an impact on the humors com­posing the human body, and in that sense that they may influence peo­ple’s behaviour to a certain extent.[96]

According to al-Fârâbï, these sublunary events or occurrences (umür) have causes (ilal or asbab—both terms are used here), namely, the stars and planets, which means that they can be grasped by the intellect through experience. What makes this possible is the fact that these events happen “for the most part” (ala l-akthar). They do not happen necessarily or always, due to the fact that there are various obstacles that can impede the actualization of the celestial influences, whether natural, such as cold air rising from the earth, or volitional, such as human decisions. In contrast to these events that happen for the most part and can be grasped through experience, there are acci­dental events (umür ittifaqiyyah), which seldom occur and which do not possess well established causes. In this case, experience can be of no help.[97] All the astrological predictions concerning human actions fall in this category, which explains why al-Fârâbï holds that they can­not be known with any certainty. For these accidental events, which happen neither necessarily nor for the most part, humans can only speculate as to their causes and establish fanciful correspondences. It is this practice which al-Fârâbï holds responsible for the bad reputation associated with astrology.

It is on this distinction between what can be known through experi­ence and what escapes human reason that al-Fârâbï grounds his main refutation of the astrological discipline. These aspects of astrology that focus on accidental events are considered invalid, because they rest on an inadequate empirical foundation and make use of flawed analogi­cal reasoning. For example, al-Fârâbï ridicules the claim that an eclipse or the vision of something red in the heavens is supposed to announce the death of a king or an important dignitary.[98] According to him, this method establishes a fallacious correspondence between the heav­enly sign and a sublunary event that is not grounded in a valid scien­tific approach. The very fact that the same conjunction of events (i.e., the eclipse or the color red and the death) cannot be seen to reoccur regularly through experience is enough to testify that the conclusion drawn by the astrologers is unfounded. Hence, because such purely hypothetical predictions cannot be vindicated by experience, al-Fârâbï categorically rejects the idea that astrology can lead to the knowledge of future events and that it represents a valid form of divination.[99]

Consequently, one realizes that the crux of al-Fârâbï’s criticism of astrology does not focus on the rejection of celestial causation on the sublunary world—a phenomenon which can be attested through obser­vation, and a proposition which in any case al-Fârâbï endorsed from his reading of Aristotle’s physical treatises—but rather on the denial that: a) physical properties such as coldness and heat can be ascribed to the planets and stars themselves; b) that the planets and stars are signs or symbols warning humanity of impending events that will necessar­ily occur; and c) that all celestial effects always and necessarily occur, a view which does not take into account the various obstacles—both physical and volitional—that impede their realization. As a corollary, al-Fârâbï believes that human will escapes the determinism of the stars, rendering the astrological project ultimately vain.[100]

For all of these reasons, it is not surprising that al-Fârâbï excludes these kinds of astrological pursuits from the realm of certain philo­sophical knowledge. The invalid part of astrology should be avoided altogether, as it does not belong to true scientific practice. Given the absence of a clear precedent in the early Arabic philosophical tradi­tion, the insight al-Fârâbï provides into the various methodological aspects of astrology and the fact that he anticipated several key features of Ibn Sïnâ’s attitude are remarkable. This is all the more striking when one realizes that al-Kindï and his circle had endorsed astrology and counted at least one famous astrologer (Abû Ma'shar) in their midst.[101] And while al-Fârâbï’s attitude toward astrology may have had several

parallels in some of the contemporary theological circles, no extant kalam work of this period contains an investigation of the defects of astrology that can be compared to al-Fârâbï’s treatises.[102] In light of these remarks, Nallino’s assertion that al-Fârâbï’s refutation of astrology is “childish” and inefficient cannot be accepted.[103]

It is interesting that al-Fârâbï’s treatment of astrology in these trea­tises informed the cosmological discussion in his other philosophical works. Indeed, the condemned aspects of astrological practice find no place in Ára and Siyasah. On the other hand, al-Fârâbï does discuss in these same works the physical influence that the planets have on gen­eration and corruption through their heat and light, and, like al-Kindï, he made the planets efficient causes for the generation and corruption of sublunary beings.[104] Al-Fârâbï therefore included some physical observations that overlap with the licit part of astrology.

In contrast to the ambiguity surrounding the classificatory status—if not the subject matter—of astrology, al-Fârâbï clearly perceives astron­omy as a mathematical science together with arithmetic, geometry, music, optics, statics, and mechanics.[105] This means on the one hand that mathematical astronomy does not deal with the celestial bodies as physical causes, as does physics or the physical part of astrology. On the other hand, it implies that the method of astronomy is based on mathematics and is therefore able to yield certain proofs that do not depend on irregular phenomena. But before discussing the method of astronomy in detail—the task of the next section—we must look into what al-Fârâbï says concerning its subject matter. In Ihsa ’, the subject matter of astronomy (ilm al-nujum al-taltmt) is divided into three parts. The first one deals with the exterior aspects of the heavenly bod­ies, such as their shapes, positions, sizes, and distances. It also includes an examination of the earth and asserts its stationary position in the world. The second part deals with all aspects of celestial motion, both the general motion shared by all the celestial orbs and the particular motions of the planets. The third part focuses on the earth and related geographical, climatological, and demographical questions. Due to its importance, I provide a new translation of the relevant passage of Ihsa ’:

Mathematical astronomy [‘ilm al-nujum al-ta'lîmî] examines three aspects of the celestial bodies and the earth:

First, [it examines] their shapes, the positions of some of them vis-à- vis others, and their order in the world, as well as the sizes of their bodies, the relations that exist between them, and the measures of the distances between them. [It also shows] that the earth as a whole does not move from its place or in its place.

Second, [it examines] how many motions the celestial bodies have and the fact that all of their motions are circular. [It studies] those [motions] that are common to the planets and other non-planetary bodies, and those [motions] common to all the planets as well as those that are spe­cific to each. [It also examines] the number of each kind of these motions, the directions toward which they move, and from which direction each one of these motions originates. It also makes known the means to estab­lish the place of each star one by one in the parts of the zodiac at each moment and with the totality of its kinds of movements.

It investigates also into everything that is concomitant with the celes­tial bodies and each one of their motions in the zodiac and what pertains to the relation between them due to their conjunction, separation, and the diversity of their places vis-à-vis one another.

In brief, [it examines] everything that pertains to their motions insofar as it does not relate to the earth, like the eclipse of the sun.[106] [And it inves­tigates] everything that occurs to them on account of the place of the earth among them in the world, as in the case of the eclipse of the moon. [It looks into] the number of these attributes, in what state and at what time and how often they appear, like the rising and setting [of the sun] and other such things.

Third, it studies the inhabited and uninhabited regions of the earth. It establishes how many parts are inhabited and how many are its major regions which are the climes, and it classifies the places that happen to be inhabited at a particular time, as well as the place of each inhabited region and its organization in the world. Moreover, it studies what necessarily affects each one of the climes and inhabited zones, due to the common revolution of the world in the universe [dawrat al-alam al-mushtarakah li-l-kull], which is the cycle of day and night, on account of the position of the earth: like the rising and setting of the sun, the length of days and nights, and other similar things. All of this is comprised by this science.[107]

Al-Fârâbï’s general exposition of the subject matter of astronomy is significant insofar as it anticipates the later descriptions found in the Arabic astronomical tradition or ‘ilm al-hay’ah. The scheme outlined above reflects what was later known in hay’ah works as a distinction between hay’at al-ard and hay at al-sama, the former belonging to the third part of the Ihsa’ account, the latter to the first and second parts.[108] The inclusion in the subject matter of astronomy of what today belongs to the disciplines of geography and climatology is one of the marking features of this classification. But I am mostly inter­ested here in the first two parts of al-Fârâbï’s description, which focus on the superlunary world. Al-Fârâbï’s outline indicates that astron­omy focuses on bodies (ajsam), although it is limited to studying the exterior aspects and properties of the celestial bodies, which it exam­ines in abstraction from matter.[109] It is not expressly suited to inquire into their inner substance. This is the task of physics, although we shall see that there is a considerable degree of overlap between these sci­ences in the mind of the falasifah. In any case, this explains why al-Fârâbï in this passage says nothing about the nature of the orbs and about aether, the simple element of the heavens according to the Peripatetic tradition.

That the investigation into the celestial substance is primarily reserved for physics, not astronomy, is confirmed by another section of the same work. There al-Fârâbï explains that the second part of the physical science must investigate “whether simple bodies exist, and if they do what kind of bodies they are, and how many they are.”[110] By “simple bodies,” al-Fârâbï means not only the four sublunary elements (fire, air, earth, and water), but also aether, the Aristotelian first body or fifth element, which is a simple, incorruptible substance; in fact, Aristotle’s discussion of aether in On the Heavens 1.2 is explicitly men­tioned.[111] According to al-Fârâbï, then, astronomy and physics are sep­arate sciences, which nevertheless study two different aspects of the same subject matter, i.e., the celestial bodies. While astronomy studies the exterior aspects of the planets, such as their motions, sizes, and distances, physics inquires into their substance, what they are made of, and how this substance relates to the sublunary elements. It is notable that al-Fârâbï’s presentation of the subject matter of astronomy and physics agrees with Aristotle’s, Geminus’, and Simplicius’ views on the subject, thus testifying to a continuous philosophical position on this issue. These thinkers made a distinction between the physical study of the cosmos (embodied in the On the Heavens tradition) and the astro­nomical approach, which is basically mathematical and examines the celestial bodies by abstracting them from their matter.[112] This position is also encountered several centuries later in the work of hay’ah practi­tioners such as al-Tusï.[113]

More should be said about al-Fârâbï’s classification of astronomy as a mathematical science, a view which has a long and diversified history in antiquity. Plato in Republic 7, Aristotle in Metaphysics 12.8.1073b and possibly in Physics 2.2,[114] Ptolemy in Almagest, and Simplicius in his commentary on Physics 2.2, had all classified astronomy as a math­ematical science. This is not to say, however, that these thinkers regarded the relation between mathematics and astronomy in the same way. There are significant differences in their approaches, which are due, among other things, to the status of mathematics in their philosophy. In the case of Plato, for example, mathematics is inextricably linked to his theory of the forms and of an ideal world beyond the realm of sense perception. Mathematical objects have a privileged status due to their immateriality and their ontological proximity to this purely intelligible dimension, although Plato did not go as far as Speusippus in making them the primary entities of his metaphysical doctrine. This explains why Plato in Republic argues that astronomy should be studied “by means of problems, as we do geometry.”[115] For Plato, astronomy is non­physical and does not deal primarily with bodies; rather, it deals with “true numbers” and “geometrical figures.”[116] If this mathematical approach to astronomy is adopted, it can lead us closer to the divine world, and it should play an important role in the curriculum of the guardians.

In the case of Aristotle, his intention in defining astronomy as a mathematical science is grounded in both methodological and meta­physical issues. Aristotle believes that astronomy is primarily interested in the exterior aspects of the celestial bodies, which it studies regard­less of their inner nature and composition. In contrast to the physi­cist, it is the privilege of the mathematician to be able to conceive of objects without their matter. However, unlike Plato and many later Neoplatonists, Aristotle rejected the idea that mathematical objects have an extramental existence. As for Ptolemy, he had a completely dif­ferent conception of the mathematical dimension of astronomy. He may have been influenced in some ways by the Platonic and Neoplatonic tendency to treat mathematics as a special discipline that bears a close relation to the ideal world of intellect or voûç.[117] But Ptolemy’s interest in mathematics is overwhelmingly tied to his methodological commit­ments and his conception of scientific accuracy. Ptolemy undermines physics and metaphysics as cosmological disciplines on the grounds that they provide inaccurate or unverifiable insights into the universe. Mathematics, on the other hand, is able to formulate proofs that are logically compelling and demonstrative in essence. This accounts for Ptolemy’s interest in observation and in the accumulated planetary data of past astronomical endeavours. Ptolemy’s interest in mathemat­ics is therefore primarily methodological and epistemological, and he sees this science as the foundation of sound astronomical practice.[118]

Al-Fârâbï’s conception that astronomy is a mathematical discipline is likely to have been informed by the Alexandrian school tradition and may best be described as a hybrid between the Aristotelian and Ptolemaic positions. On the one hand, al-Fârâbï broadly follows Aristotle’s classification of the sciences and the idea that astronomy focuses on the exterior aspects of the celestial bodies, as Ihsa’ makes clear. He also follows Aristotle in rejecting the existence of immaterial mathematical objects outside the human mind (sec. 2.2.2. below). However, he at the same time emphasizes the observational and empir­ical dimensions of astronomy in Müstqâ (sec. 2.2.1. below), a trend which can be traced to both Aristotle and Ptolemy and which may in addition have been stimulated by the emphasis on scientific observa­tion characteristic of the Arabic astronomical tradition.

At this point, the differences between astrology and astronomy appear clearly. Al-Fârâbï regards astronomy as a fully legitimate disci­pline, which occupies a central place in the philosophical curriculum as one of the mathematical sciences. Although it shares part of its sub­ject matter with physics, it possesses its own aims and mathematical approach. In view of this, it is not surprising that astronomy plays an important role in al-Fârâbï’s cosmology. This is borne out not only by his writing a commentary on Almagest, but also by the large share of astronomical features that he integrates in his metaphysical treatises, especially Ara and Siyasah. In contrast, al-Fârâbï rejects most aspects of astrology, because these fall neither within the physical nor the mathematical field. Al-Fârâbï therefore distinguishes between astron­omy and astrology in terms of their epistemological status, subject matter, and method. Nowhere are there signs of confusion between these two disciplines in his works; on the contrary, the Second Teacher is intent on criticizing one while fully endorsing the other.

From a historical perspective, al-Fârâbï’s views on astronomy and astrology occupy an intermediary position between the Ancient Greek authors and the Arabic hay’ah authors. In maintaining that astronomy and astrology are both part of the same overarching discipline, al-Fârâbï is in some sense following an ancient Greek trend that will later be abandoned by the hay’ah tradition of the post-eleventh century. Indeed, like ilm al-nujum, the Greek terms àorpovopia and àmpoÀoyia are inherently ambiguous and can mean both astronomy and astrology, depending on the context. As can be seen from the various entries in Liddell and Scott’s Lexicon and in Brill’s New Pauly, most Greek authors used these terms very loosely and without distinguishing clearly between the two disciplines.[119] Al-Fârâbï therefore shares this terminological ambiguity with the Greek tradition. But one should not place too much weight on the evidence in Ihsa ’, a treatise which draws on the Alexandrian academic tradition and which does not always fully reflect al-Fârâbï’s views as developed in his other works. We saw that the Second Teacher used a more precise set of terms in parallel to ‘ilm al-nujum when he wanted to refer specifically to astronomy or astrol­ogy. Unlike the Greek authors, then, al-Fârâbï could distinguish math­ematical astronomy clearly from astrology both at the terminological and conceptual levels if he wanted to. Moreover, he never embraced astrology the way Ptolemy did in his Tetrabiblos. On the contrary, his attempt to refute some aspects of astrology and to redefine the border between astronomy and astrology represent remarkable aspects of his work and a clear break with the Greek tradition. It also anticipated the more sustained critique conducted by Ibn Sïnâ and the later hayah practitioners.

2.2. The Principles of Astronomy

2.2.1. Experience, Observation, and Induction

One of the main issues addressed by al-Fârâbï in the first introductory section of Müstqâ concerns the epistemological foundations of the par­ticular sciences. In order to strengthen his arguments, al-Fârâbï com­pares music to other sciences such as astronomy and medicine, and by doing so provides insight into their method and epistemology as well. Al-Fârâbï begins by classifying the sciences in various categories depending on the method required to establish their first principles. '1 here are sciences, he tells us, whose first principles are acquired intui­tively and from a very young age. There are other sciences some of whose first principles are acquired in this manner while others are derived from separate sciences. Finally there are sciences that rely on both methods and in addition establish first principles through experi­ence.[120] Al-Fârâbï does not provide specific examples for the three cat­egories of sciences he posits. But it becomes clear upon further examination that astronomy belongs to the third category, which means that some of its principles are innate to humans, some are derived from other sciences, whereas still others are reached as a result of experience. In the following paragraphs, I discuss the latter two methods, namely, experience, and the transfer of principles from one science to another.

Al-Fârâbï’s Müstqâ contains, together with Burhân, his most system­atic and detailed exposition of the importance of experience, observa­tion, and induction in philosophy, and it is for this reason surprising that this text has attracted so little scholarly attention. Experience (tajribah) in particular is treated in some length in the Müstqâ.[121] Al-Fârâbï explains that it is grounded in the repeated sensation (ihsâs) of facts, and that it occurs when the intellect “acts” (yaf al), that is, when the intellect makes a universal judgement on the basis of these facts. As a result, experience can produce certain knowledge and provides us with some of the first principles necessary for demonstration. As al-Fârâbï puts it, “the things [al-ashya] acquired through experience [tajribah] become first principles [al-mabâdt l-ülâ] in demonstrations [barâhtn][122] Throughout his account, al-Fârâbï refers to Aristotle’s Posterior Analytics for support. He even quotes Aristotle to the effect that “sensation [hiss] is used in the principles of demonstration,” but he adds immediately afterward that by “sensation” Aristotle here means the kind of knowledge that leads immediately to experience.[123]

Al-Fârâbï provides more specific information on the role of experi­ence in astronomy. At one point he writes that “the situation of this science [the musical science] is like that of other sciences in which many of the principles [mabadt] are acquired through the experi­ence of sensibles [tajribat al-mahsüsât], as in astronomy [‘ilm al-nujüm] and most of optics and medicine.”[124] And shortly afterward, he adds that “many of the principles of astronomy are acquired by the observer as a result of an act of sensation through observations by means of instruments [kathtr min mabâdi ’ilm al-nujüm tahsulu li-l-nâzirfthi ‘an al-ihsâs bi-l-arsâd bi-l-âlât]”[125] According to al-Fârâbï, then, the astronomer may derive astronomical principles from the “experience of sensibles” and from “instrumental observations.” A similar point appears in Burhan, where al-Fârâbï describes experience (tajribah) as a source of knowledge for mathematical astronomy (ilm al-nujüm al-talïmï).[126]

Janssens argues in his article “Experience in Classical Arabic Philosophy” that experience and observation are two different concepts for al-Fârâbï.[127] He points out that experience has a claim to universal knowledge, and he adduces a number of convincing passages from al-Fârâbï’s works to buttress this point. But Janssens on the other hand does not define observation, nor does he give the Arabic term that would correspond to this concept in al-Fârâbï’s works. In fact, it would seem that al-Fârâbï does not systematically articulate a theory of obser­vation in the works studied by Janssens and in Müstqû. True, in the latter work, he refers to the “instrumental observations” (al-arsad bi-l- alat) of the astronomers, but it is unlikely in my view that arsad here refers to a full-blown theory of observation in the way that tajribah refers to a theory of experience.

On the other hand, in Müsïqa and in his logical works, al-Fârâbï consistently distinguishes experience (tajribah) from induction (istiqra) in a manner reminiscent of the other passages discussed by Janssens.[128] What, then, is the difference between these two concepts? As Janssens explains, experience involves an act of the intellect which can extract universal knowledge from specific events or facts and lead to certainty, whereas induction cannot provide certain knowledge. “Experience,” says al-Fârâbï in Burhan, “is what produces certitude of knowledge [al-yaqm] through a universal judgement [bi-l-hukm al-kullt]”[129] The role of intellect in experience is also underlined in Müstqa, which defines tajribah as “the determination of the sensation of various things a repeated number of times in order that the intellect may act with a special act and reach certainty.”[130] It is not com­pletely clear in this quotation what this “special act” (fi’l khass) of the intellect is supposed to be, but when juxtaposed to the previous pas­sage, one may conclude that it consists of a rational judgment (hukm). Confirmation of this appears in the definition of tajribah found in al-Fârâbï’s Talkhts jawami kitab al-nawamts li-Aflatün, which closely mirrors the one in Burhan: “the meaning of experience is the attentive consideration of the particulars of a thing, more precisely forming a judgment about the thing’s universality inasmuch as experience finds that universality in these particulars.”[131] The “special act” of the intellect in experience, then, is to form a judgment of the particular sensations and extract a universal meaning out of these particulars that represents certain knowledge. In contrast to experience, induction does not lead to universal, certain knowledge, and in al-Fârâbï’s view it seems closely related to observation and the gathering of data.

Experience is important both in the practical sciences, where it pro­duces phronesis (taaqqul), as al-Fârâbï suggests in Kitab al-millah,[132] and in the theoretical sciences, where it fulfills an epistemological func­tion in the acquisition of certain knowledge. Yet it is difficult to apply al-Fârâbï’s comments on induction and experience to astronomy, and he provides no clue as to how one should do so. In spite of this, it is possible that he conceived of induction in astronomy as being limited to, or equivalent to, observation, the “instrumental observations” con­ducted by the astronomer, which after some time form the basis on which experience can operate. A possible example of this occurs when the astronomer, having observed the sun, moon, and stars a repeated number of times, is able through experience to anticipate some of their motions.

A further point of interest in Müstqa is the distinction between the theoretical and practical sides of astronomy. The theoretical astronomer, al-Fârâbï tells us, need not know how to use astronomical instruments as long as he can rely on someone else to do the observations for him.[133] It is not obvious whether experience is meant to correspond to theory and observation or induction to practice, but what is clear on the other hand is that according to al-Fârâbï, astronomical theory depends on practice and on the empirical collection of data. If for some reason, al-Fârâbï explains, the theorist is not able to benefit from the help of an observer or does not possess the required technology to carry out the observations himself, then he must rely on the findings of his predeces­sors and can only provide limited theoretical insight into his field of research. Thus, although al-Fârâbï distinguishes theory and practice and values the former more than the latter, he admits that theory can achieve only limited progress if it is not supported by adequate practice and observation.

The emphasis on experience found in Müstqâ also appears in a cos­mological context in other works by al-Fârâbï. In one of the two trea­tises on astrology already discussed, al-Fârâbï explains that experience is necessary to understand the effects of the celestial bodies on sublu­nary existents, especially the manner in which the celestial bodies transmit heat to plants and other organisms.[134] Experience thus enables valid astrological inquiries to take place, i.e., those that study things that occur with regular frequency. Finally, the epistemological impor­tance of experience is highlighted in K. al-millah, where it is presented as a source of knowledge for the practicing physician.[135] Finally, Risalah ft l-khala shows that al-Fârâbï himself did not hesitate to carry out practical experiments to solve physical questions such as the existence of the void.[136]

The texts discussed above show that al-Fârâbï’s conception of experience had a wide application, which in any case transcended the astronomical field and extended into many other aspects of his phi­losophy. Al-Fârâbï regarded experience and induction as important features of the philosophical method—including the astronomical method—and this in spite of the essentially mathematical and abstract nature of astronomy. This feature can be explained partly by the impact of Posterior Analytics, which is quoted several times in Müstqâ. The importance this text played in shaping al-Fârâbï’s methodology with respect to the particular sciences cannot be underestimated, and it appears clearly when he writes that “the first principles of certain dem­onstrations in every science only reach the soul through the sensation [ihsas] of individual and particular things, as has been shown in the PosteriorAnalytics [al-análüfíqa l-akhtrah]”[137] It is probably al-Fârâbï’s thorough acquaintance with this text that can best explain the main methodological differences between him and his predecessor al-Kindï. One may also surmise that this text contributed to the conceptual and epistemological differentiation al-Fârâbï made between astronomy and astrology.

Al-Fârâbï’s discussion of experience, observation, and induction in connection with astronomy has several precedents in ancient philoso­phy and science, which should be discussed briefly. Aristotle alludes to the importance of heavenly observations in Book Lambda 8.1073b1- 20, a passage which expresses the view that astronomy undergoes peri­odic progress thanks to the gradual accumulation of astronomical data. An even more striking precedent occurs in Prior Analytics 1.30.46a19- 22, where Aristotle states that “astronomical experience supplies the principles of astronomical science.”[138] In Ptolemy’s Almagest, observa­tion is defined as one of the methodological pillars of astronomy, and one on which mathematical theories rely.[139]

As for the Arabic world, H. Wiesner has stressed the important function that sense perception, induction, and experience play in al-Kindi’s cosmology.[140] Furthermore, historians of Arabic astronomy have convincingly shown that Muslim astronomers not only inherited Ptolemy’s outlook, but also developed it considerably, placing new emphasis on the value of precise observation. This trend flourished with greater vigor after the eleventh century and culminated in the achievements of the Maragha School during the thirteenth and four­teenth centuries. However, it is also perceptible at an earlier stage. Already during the ninth and tenth centuries, Thabit ibn Qurra, al-Battani, and al-Farghani were scrutinizing the heavens, and their works show that they understood the value of precise observations in advancing astronomical knowledge.[141] Observational programs were carried out during this period, such as those in Damascus and Baghdad under the reign of al-Ma'mûn, which allowed for accurate and system­atic surveys of heavenly motions to be made. As a result, Arabic astron­omers corrected or refined a significant amount of the Ptolemaic data they inherited.

In light of the foregoing, it is not surprising that al-Farabi incorpo­rates experience and observation in the astronomical methodology. It is clear that he considers astronomy to be, at least partially, an empir­ical science, which relies on the accumulation of data through obser­vation and experience. Particularly noteworthy is his mention of “instruments” (alat), which betrays a keen interest in the quantitative dimension and practical side of the astronomical science. This empha­sis on the empirical aspect of astronomy and its gradual development as a science parallels al-Farabi’s views on the rise of philosophy as exposed in Hurüf and Fï zu hür al-falsafah.[142]

2.2.2.    Astronomy and Mathematics

It was shown previously that al-Fârâbï classifies astronomy as a math­ematical science in Ihsd’■ This classification is mirrored in other texts as well. In Nass al-tawti’ah, al-Fârâbï divides philosophy into four parts: mathematical, physical, metaphysical, and one which he calls al-‘ilm al-madant. Astronomy, or ‘ilm al-nujum, is comprised in the mathe­matical part. As for logic, it is merely a tool (âlah).[143] In Tahstl, astron­omy is also defined as one of the mathematical sciences alongside arithmetic, geometry, optics, music, statics, and mechanics, in a way reminiscent of Ihsâ’.[144] This same passage of Tahstl provides additional valuable information on how astronomy fits within the broader philo­sophical education and on its status within the mathematical field. Al-Fârâbï explains that students should start by studying those mathe­matical disciplines whose objects are completely removed from matter and consist of pure numbers and magnitudes, i.e., arithmetic and geometry. They are then encouraged to descend to those mathematical sciences whose objects are embodied in matter, such as music, astron­omy, and mechanics. Although al-Fârâbï does not elaborate on this point, the merit of this method is clearly that students can grasp the abstract and universal laws of mathematics without worrying about how they relate to material bodies. Once mastered, these mathematical laws and concepts can then be applied to specific groups of bodies and to particular objects. In other words, the student shifts from pure mathematics (geometry) to the various branches of applied mathemat­ics, such as music, astronomy, and mechanics. One notices that this method is essentially deductive and proceeds from abstract entities to concrete beings. It is one of two methods outlined by al-Fârâbï in Tahstl, the other being the physical method, which is analytical and proceeds from corporeal beings to their principles.[145]

But what is the place of mathematics in the method of astronomy? Since al-Fârâbï’s commentary on Almagest has not survived, it is diffi­cult to answer this question with any precision, nor is it possible to reconstruct any of his planetary models. In spite of this, a few hints throughout his corpus shed some light on his conception of mathemat­ics and on its role in the astronomical method. In Burhdn, the Second Teacher explains that some of astronomy’s principles are derived from mathematics, or, more precisely, from geometry (ilm al-handasah).[146] Al-Fârâbï does not elaborate on this brief statement, but he probably had in mind such fundamental principles as the perfection of the cir­cular shape, for instance, which was widely recognized by Greek and Arabic mathematicians. In addition, astronomy relies on basic geo­metrical figures such as circles, lines, and points to construct its models of planetary motion, the epicycles and eccentrics. Hence, the theoriz­ing of planetary motions and the representation of mathematical mod­els to explain them would not be possible without the principles of geometry.

Another key aspect of al-Fârâbï’s conception of mathematics can be extracted from Burhan and Aghrad. In these works, al-Fârâbï explicitly defends the view that mathematical entities can only be abstracted from matter in the human mind, but not in reality. When comparing metaphysics and mathematics in the latter work, al-Fârâbï states that

although mathematics is higher than natural science—since its subjects are abstracted from matter—it most certainly should not be called the science of metaphysics because its subjects are abstracted from matter only by human imagination, not actually.[147]

This statement indicates that although al-Fârâbï regarded mathematics as a useful tool to investigate the world around us and as a science pos­sessing its own method and subject matter, he did not, on the other hand, endow mathematical objects with a special metaphysical status or value. His view seems to have been informed by the scientific method of Aristotle and Ptolemy, rather than by the metaphysics of the Platonists and Neoplatonists, who had often elevated mathematical numbers to a divine or quasi-divine status. In this respect, al-Fârâbï departs not only from these Greek thinkers, but also from al-Kindï, who was apparently influenced by Proclus’ commentary on Euclid’s Elements, and accord­ing to whom mathematical objects possess an intermediary position between physical objects and intelligible beings.[148] In contrast, and as G. Freudenthal has shown, al-Fârâbï endeavoured to develop an ana­lytical approach to mathematics for didactic reasons (in addition to the synthetic, deductive method inherited from Euclid), and he strongly believed in the pedagogical virtue of proceeding gradually from con­crete physical bodies to more abstract geometrical entities.[149] Even in the case of mathematics, then, al-Fârâbï’s approach is grounded in the physical world and takes concrete bodies as its starting point. These remarks go hand in hand with the emphasis placed on experience and observation and on the quantitative aspect of astronomy, which were discussed in the previous section. They help to explain the intermedi­ary position of mathematics between physics and metaphysics in al-Fârâbï’s philosophical curriculum.

2.2.3.    Astronomy and Physics

The role of physics in the cosmological inquiry and its relation to astronomy were alluded to previously, but it is worthwhile providing additional insight into this important question. According to al-Fârâbï, physics studies the realm of corporeal beings, which may also be defined as the world (al-'dlam) and nature (al-tabt ah.).[150] The world or nature consists not only of all the sublunary hylomorphic beings, but also of the heavenly bodies, that is, the orbs, stars, and planets. Hence, the simple celestial substance and its properties fall within the scope of physics. As al-Fârâbï writes, physics studies “the heavens and its vari­ous parts as being made of a certain one matter [maddah ma ftha wâhidah]”[151] [152] This information, together with the fact that al-Fârâbï defends Aristotle’s theory of aether in an extant treatise, Al-radd ’ala Yahya l-Nahwt, indicates that at least during one period of his life, the Second Teacher endorsed the Aristotelian view that the heavens are made of a special, simple element, and that the study of this substance falls within the perview of natural philosophy.

Al-Fârâbï’s method with respect to celestial physics and its impor­tance for astronomy can be further fleshed out by relying on some of his comments in Tahstl- In one passage, al-Fârâbï explains that the method of the theoretical sciences relies on investigation (fah s) and inference (istinbat), techniques through which the principles of things can be established.142 With regard to physics, the implication is that the philosopher must examine the various classes or genera of bodies in order to identify their principles, which can in turn be used for further investigation. But since all bodies do not belong to the same genus, and since some are more knowable than others, the philosophical method must proceed through inference from those bodies that are more know­able to us to those that are less knowable. Accordingly, the philosopher begins by studying the simple elements, then minerals and plants, then irrational animals, and, finally, rational animals. But in doing so he should not limit himself to the principles of one genus; rather he should strive to give an account “of the principles of its principles, and of the principles of the principles of its principles, until he arrives at its ulti­mate corporeal principles.”[153]

This explains why the philosopher does not begin with the study of the celestial bodies directly, but rather with the study of sublunary bod­ies, which are the closest to human experience. It is only after having acquired knowledge of these perishable bodies that he may turn his attention to the heavens. At this point, he may rely on different tech­niques. One is analogical and consists in transferring certain proposi­tions applicable to the sublunary bodies to the celestial bodies. This is justified on the grounds that all of these beings share a common corpo­real nature. In addition to this analogical approach, observation also plays a key role, since the philosopher may draw certain physical prop­ositions from the perceived regularity and harmony of the celestial motions. One notices in this respect that observation and experience are concepts used both in the astronomical and physical method, albeit to different ends: in astronomy, they are a starting point for the accu­mulation of data and the construction of planetary models, whereas in physics they lead to the formulation of key principles (e.g., the perpet­ual heavenly revolutions point to the existence of a special element possessing circular motion by nature).

According to al-Fârâbï, the astronomers are dependent to some extent on the findings of the natural philosophers and on some of the principles established in celestial physics in the manner described above. Indeed, he mentions in Müstqa another source—apart from experience, observation, and geometry—from which the principles of astronomy are derived, namely, natural philosophy. As he writes:

Moreover, the case when we are unable to perceive certain harmonies is like the case in which many of the sciences have their first principles [mabddi'ha l-uwal] proven in other sciences, and the practitioner of this science takes an accepted principle which has been established in these [other] sciences. When he is asked to prove it, he refers to the specialists of these sciences. This is what the astronomer [munajjim] does when he wants to explain the causes [asbab] of the various motions of the celestial bodies that appear through observation [arsad]. He can only explain these causes, such as the eccentrics and epicycles [mithl al-dawair al-khanjah al-marakiz 'an markaz al-'dlam wa-aflak al-tadwir], when it is posited that these planetary motions are in themselves regular [mus- tawiyyah]. He is not able to prove [laysayumkinu anyatabayyana] this at all in astronomy, but only by borrowing accepted [premises] [musal- lamatan] from the natural scientists.[154]

This passage explicitly and vividly stresses astronomy’s dependence on physics. It does not, on the other hand, describe in any detail the kind of premises and principles that are borrowed from natural philosophy, although al-Fârâbï does provide a hint when he mentions that the celestial motions are regular (mustawiyyah). The assumption, which is not spelled out in the text, is that the heavens are made of a simple ele­ment that possesses a unique motion, namely, circular motion, which, in its constancy and harmony, befits the divine or semi-divine nature of the heavens. The idea of circular motion, which harkens back to Plato’s Timaeus, was elaborated in full by Aristotle in On the Heavens and sub­sequently became one of the fundamental philosophical assumptions underlying the works of many ancient and medieval astronomers.

More specifically, al-Fârâbï probably had On the Heavens 1.2-4 in mind when writing this passage of Müstqâ, in which he implicitly accepts the correlation between the simplicity of aether and the regu­larity of circular motion. Al-Fârâbï’s argument may be reconstructed as follows: astronomy is unable to account for the heavens’ regular and uniform motions if it does not refer to physics, which alone can explain the cause of this phenomenon through a discussion of simple bodies (especially aether) and the principles of motion and rest. What this means is that astronomy is dependent on the natural sciences for some of its principles and is thus not a completely self-contained discipline. Experience and observation, as well as the mathematical theories built on their data, are insufficient for one to acquire a comprehensive knowl­edge of the heavenly phenomena. Mathematics is not, as Ptolemy believed, the golden means and the only legitimate method at the dis­posal of the astronomer, nor is it the only path that leads to divine knowledge. Although problems pertaining to the exterior qualities of the celestial bodies, such as the sizes and distances of the planets, can be solved by astronomers through mathematics alone, knowledge of the causes and devices responsible for celestial motion requires that one transfer physical principles to astronomy, where they are used as first principles (mabadi uwal, which correspond to the Greek àp%ai). Only then can one account for the causes (asbab) of celestial motion, a term which reveals a concern for causality and in a sense marks the explanatory limit of the astronomical discipline.

The importance al-Fârâbï bestows on physical principles in astron­omy has one further implication with respect to his method. It suggests that he has in mind an astronomical account that is not purely abstract or geometrical, but rather in accordance with physical reality, and which integrates some of physics’ results regarding the corporeality of the orbs. This is vindicated by the fact that al-Fârâbï considered the celestial orbs and the various devices, such as the eccentrics and epicy­cles, to be concrete, corporeal entities. This viewpoint, which transpires in his general account of the structure of the heavens in Ára, will be discussed at greater length in the next chapter.

Al-Fârâbï’s view that astronomy is dependent on physics is likely to have been shaped by some of the ancient sources that reached him.[155] Aristotle in Physics 2.2 provides a discussion of the relation between astronomy, physics, and mathematics, which became a locus classicus for later reflections on the subject. According to the traditional inter­pretation (illustrated in Ross’ commentary), Aristotle concludes that astronomy is more physical than mathematical, but this view has recently been challenged.[156] Regardless of whether Aristotle ultimately defines astronomy as a mathematical or physical science, he stresses the connection between astronomy and physics due on the one hand to the corporeality and perceptibility of the heavenly bodies and on the other to their having motion. However, Aristotle does not explicitly state in this passage that astronomy is in any way dependent on physics for its principles.

Perhaps more relevant is Ptolemy’s attitude toward physics. It is well known that although he claimed to ground his method entirely in mathematics, he at times relied strongly on physics to elaborate some of his cosmological proofs and explanations. This can be seen, for instance, in his treatment of the heavens’ sphericity and his mention of aether in section 1.3 of Almagest. It is nevertheless in the work of Geminus that al-Fârâbï’s view finds the closest parallel. Al-Fârâbï’s gen­eral position concerning the importance of natural philosophy in astronomy is mirrored in Geminus’ Introduction to the Phainomena and especially in his shorter treatise entitled Concise Exposition of the Meteorology of Poseidonios.[157] In these treatises, Geminus (or Poseidonios as reported by Geminus) makes the following points. First, astronomy and physics focus on different aspects of the celestial bod­ies, the former on their motion and exterior characteristics, the latter on their substance. Second, both sciences use a different method to prove the same thing, but because the astronomer cannot know the true nature of superlunary things, he must take his first principles from physics. Finally, there is an emphasis on the study of causes.[158] The dependence of astronomy on physics appears clearly when Geminus writes that “he [the astronomer] must take from the physicist the first principles, that the motions of the stars are simple, uniform, and orderly.”[159]

As we have seen, all of these points may be found in al-Fârâbï’s writ­ings. Al-Fârâbï considers that astronomy and physics study different aspects of the same subject matter. He also presents physics as one of the sources from which astronomical principles are derived, and he cautions that astronomers can acquire only partial knowledge of the causes of celestial phenomena. In this regard, al-Fârâbï’s assertion that the astronomer must “borrow accepted premises from the natural sci­entists” strikingly echoes Geminus’ own statement that the astrono­mer “must take from the physicist the first principles.” These glaring parallels suggest that al-Fârâbï is indebted to a particular trend of Greek astronomical theory, which is perhaps most plainly embodied in Geminus. Did al-Fârâbï read part of the Arabic translations of Geminus’ works? This hypothesis is reinforced by the fact that, as Evans and Berggren write, Geminus’ “remarks constitute the clearest statement of this relationship [i.e., between astronomy and physics] we find in any of the Greek astronomical writers.”[160] Hence, regardless of the impact that Almagest and other Ptolemaic works had on al-Fârâbï, in this par­ticular instance the Second Teacher is closer to Geminus than to Ptolemy.[161] This in turn suggests that the Greek astronomical sources transmitted to the Arabic world were probably more diverse than pre­viously believed.

This picture of how physics and astronomy interact is further com­plexified by the fact that according to al-Fârâbï the various sciences can prove the same thing in different ways. In Burhan, he explains that astronomy and physics can muster different proofs and use a different method to establish the same conclusion. He provides the example of the sphericity of the heavenly bodies to illustrate this. Al-Fârâbï begins by explaining that when a thing has several causes (i.e., the four Aristotelian causes), then these causes can be demonstrated either by one or several sciences. If the four causes cannot be proven by one sci­ence, then various sciences might be required to provide knowledge of the different causes. Hence, physics, which studies bodies that are enmattered and possess a principle of motion, and mathematics, which studies objects and qualities abstracted from their matter, can identify different causes of the same existent. This is why al-Fârâbï concludes that these sciences can collaborate together and study the same object from different angles. According to him, there is therefore no contra­diction and opposition between the methods of physics and astronomy. He writes:

For this reason, it is possible for mathematics and physics to cooperate in [the examination of] a single thing, and for the former to provide a cause, and the latter to provide another cause. In this fashion the sphericity of the world and the sun and the moon is examined by both mathematics and physics.[162]

This statement conveniently encapsulates al-Fârâbï’s belief in the coop­eration of physics and astronomy. It also goes hand in hand with what was said previously concerning the place of astronomy and physics in the philosophical education. According to al-Fârâbï, the celestial bod­ies occupy an intermediary position in the philosophical curriculum and can be studied from two different angles: either by proceeding from pure mathematics to applied mathematics, i.e., from geometry to astronomy, or by pursuing the physical inquiry until it reaches the heavenly world and becomes celestial physics. Both methods are com­plementary and possess their own didactic merit, although in Tahstl al-Fârâbï advises students to start with mathematics.[163] This also means that astronomy shares a common boundary with celestial physics, for it is at the level of the celestial bodies that the mathematical and deduc­tive method of the former comes in contact with the analytical and inferential method of the latter.

The previous analysis should encourage us to re-examine some aspects of al-Fârâbï’s affiliation to the Aristotelian, Platonic, and Neoplatonic traditions. In his description of the astronomical method, al-Fârâbï appears as a thorough Aristotelian, and more specifically, as a careful reader of Posterior Analytics, although I endeavoured to show that he was also influenced by the theories of ancient astrono­mers, such as Geminus and Ptolemy, as well as by the development of Arabic astronomy. Al-Fârâbï attempted to apply some of Aristotle’s methodological ideas to particular sciences such as music and astron­omy, and his general conception of the classification of these sciences is indebted to this work. He is one of the earliest thinkers in Arabic thought to emphasize the importance of observation and experience. He clearly perceived the significance of the empirical approach in the development of the astronomical discipline and reflected deeply on the relation between scientific practice and theory.[164] Al-Fârâbï here departs markedly from many Platonists and Neoplatonists for whom all true knowledge consists of insights into the intelligible and immate­rial world and who in general discarded the realm of sense perception. This attitude can be witnessed in connection with astronomy in Syrianus’ commentary on Metaphysics and in the opening pages of Proclus’ Hypotyposis, two texts which contrast markedly with al-Fârâbï’s position.[165]

2.3. The Primacy of Metaphysics and its Impact on Cosmology

The previous section stressed the important role played by astronomy and physics in the cosmological inquiry as well as the interrelatedness of these sciences. According to al-Fârâbï, however, these disciplines can only yield limited insight into the heavens, because the ultimate principles of existence and causes of the celestial bodies are immate­rial and therefore can be studied neither by natural philosophy, which studies material bodies, nor by mathematics, which studies objects existing only in the human mind. Metaphysics on the other hand can provide knowledge of these immaterial causes and thus bring the inquiry into the celestial substance to its completion.[166] As al-Fârâbï explains in Falsafat Aristü ta lis on behalf of the Stagirite,

He [Aristotle] had to investigate also whether the substances of the heav­enly bodies consist of a nature or a soul or an intellect, or something else more perfect than these. These matters are beyond the scope of natural theory. For natural theory includes only what is included in the catego­ries; and it has become evident that there are here other instances of being not encompassed by the categories: that is, the Active Intellect and the thing that supplies the heavenly bodies with perpetual circular motion.[167]

In this passage al-Fârâbï intimates that metaphysics is necessary for two things: to define the true substance of the celestial bodies (which could very well be an immaterial principle like intellect) and to identify their cause of motion, which is described as a “thing” exterior to them. Here we see that the physical definition of the orbs and planets as sim­ple bodies put forth by the Aristotelian tradition does not stand for a full definition, since aether constitutes only the material aspect of their substance, which in addition may include immaterial principles such as soul or intellect. On al-Fârâbï’s reckoning, knowledge of the heavens’ substance and causes must depend on metaphysics, which alone can investigate these immaterial principles.

The approach underlying this view is explained in more detail in Fusül, where al-Fârâbï advises the student of theoretical philosophy to “[ascend] little by little in the things that need matter to be understood and conceived of until he comes to the celestial bodies.” Then he adds:

When he ends up at the celestial bodies, the rational soul, and the active intellect, he [the philosopher] transfers again to another rank. So it is necessary for him to inquire theoretically into the principles of their existence until he becomes aware of principles that are not natural. ... He also comes to a midpoint between two sciences—the science of natural things and the science of what is after the natural things—in the ranking of investigation and instruction.[168]

That the heavenly bodies mark the boundary between material and immaterial beings and thus between physics and metaphysics is also underlined in Tahstl, where one finds the following statement:

When one finally comes to enquire into the heavenly bodies and investi­gate the principles of their being, this inquiry into the principles of their being will force him to look for principles that are not natures or natural things, but beings more perfect than nature and natural things. They are also not bodies or in bodies. Therefore one needs another kind of inves­tigation here and another science that inquires exclusively into beings that are metaphysical. At this point he is again standing between two sci­ences: the science of nature and the science of what is beyond natural things in the order of investigation and instruction and above them in the order of being.[169]

These passages go hand in hand with another passage in Fusül, in which the celestial bodies are said to represent a distinct genus of existents whose status is intermediary between metaphysical beings and material beings. As al-Fârâbï writes, “There are three genera of existing things: those devoid of matter, celestial bodies, and material bodies.” And shortly after, he adds that “there are three worlds: spirit­ual, celestial, and material.”[170] The latter statement may strike one as somewhat peculiar, because the orthodox Peripatetic tradition divides the world in two dimensions, the superlunary and sublunary. This “two-sphere universe,” as T. Kuhn has called it, is one of the most recognizable features of medieval Aristotelian cosmological models. But al-Fârâbï is asserting here in a somewhat Platonic manner that the celestial bodies represent an intermediary world between the world of intelligible beings and that of corruptible existents.[171] Al-Fârâbï’s use of the term “world” (alam) should probably not be taken literally, but it does underscore the special status of the celestial bodies and their remoteness from the realm of generation and corruption. Although the notion of an intermediate celestial world is proper to this passage of Fusül, the idea that the celestial bodies constitute a distinct category or genus of existents is found in al-Fârâbï’s other writings. In Siyasah, which is also known by the more appropriate name Mabadi l-mawjüdat, the celestial bodies constitute one of six genera (ajnas) of bodies.[172]

The main ideas that emerge from these passages are that the heav­enly bodies occupy an intermediary position between the natural world and the intelligible world, and that it is necessary for this reason to rely on metaphysics if one wants to obtain a complete definition of their substance (jawhar) and principles (mabadi’). The need for metaphysics in this case is all the more conspicuous, given that al-Fârâbï endows the celestial bodies with intellects (‘uqül) that reflect on the higher imma­terial principles that are the separate intellects (ch. 2, 2.1-5.). Hence, although physics and metaphysics should both be employed in the cos­mological project, only the latter science can provide complete knowl­edge of the fundamental principles of the cosmos, which are immaterial and therefore lie beyond the realm of nature.

This notion of the primacy of metaphysics in the cosmologi­cal inquiry also has a direct bearing on the astronomical method. Al-Fârâbï’s view on this matter can be reconstructed not from Müstqa, but rather from his logical treatises and particularly Burhan, which is interested in the rules governing scientific demonstration and in defin­ing the interrelation of the sciences. We saw previously that al-Fârâbï holds observation and experience in high esteem, since these tech­niques produce some of the principles of astronomy and also enable the development of this science through the accumulation of data. However, this empirical method has a limit within cosmology, which is fixed, among other things, by the nature of the subject matter. It is understandable that observation is of no use when the causes of visible phenomena (here the planets and their motion) are by nature invisible and abstract and can only be apprehended intellectually. Accordingly, the study of these causes falls outside the realm of astronomy, but it does have an impact on the kinds of things the astronomer can legiti­mately seek to know and on the mode in which he knows them, par­ticularly with regard to celestial motion.

This partly explains al-Fârâbï’s belief that astronomy, like all the sec­ondary or particular sciences (al-ulüm al-juziyyah), is dependent on metaphysics for some of its principles, since it cannot establish its first principles on its own. Just as astronomy derives some of its premises from physics and geometry, so it derives some of its other premises from metaphysics. This view is articulated clearly in al-Fârâbï’s Burhan, which outlines a complex theory of the interrelatedness of the sciences. One key idea is that metaphysics, or “first philosophy” (al-falsafah al-ülâ), is the universal science that provides the particular sciences with some of their principles. Al-Fârâbï writes that

the particular sciences [e.g., physics, astronomy] are all below first phi­losophy, participating in it insofar as all their subjects are below the abso­lutely existent [al-mawjüd ‘ala l-itlaq]. This science will employ universal premises that all the particular sciences employ in the way we have described, while the particular sciences employ premises which are dem­onstrated in that science [first philosophy].[173]

And further on al-Fârâbï notes that metaphysics is the science that gives “the highest causes of the existents” (asbab al-mawjüdât al- quswa).[174] These points are echoed in Aghrad, where he explains that it is metaphysics that provides the principles and subject matters of the particular sciences.[175]

Furthermore, in Burhan, al-Fârâbï follows Aristotle’s distinction in Posterior Analytics 1.13 between knowledge of the fact and knowledge of the reasoned fact, which translates syllogistically into demonstration of the existence and demonstration of the cause, known in Arabic as inna and lima (or innt and limmt) proofs.[176] Knowledge or demonstra­tion of the existence is merely knowledge that (anna or inna) some­thing exists, whereas knowledge or demonstration of the cause is knowledge why (lima) this thing exists.[177] Al-Fârâbï explains in Tahsil that both kinds of demonstration are valuable for the philosopher and produce knowledge.[178] But in Burhan he grounds an important part of his exposition on this distinction and argues that it is always preferable for a philosopher to reach knowledge of the cause together with knowl­edge of the existence, rather than knowledge of the existence alone.

Now, metaphysics is the science which par excellence is able to pro­vide this kind of certain knowledge, since it studies the most funda­mental causes of being on which all substances ultimately depend. As al-Fârâbï writes, “the prior sciences provide the posterior sciences with knowledge of the causes or of the causes and existence together.”[179] In turn, this explains why the proper cosmological method must rely not only on particular sciences such as physics and astronomy, but also on metaphysics in order to provide a comprehensive account of the uni­verse that includes a causal explanation of its hidden principles. These principles identified by metaphysics, chief among them being the sepa­rate intellects, will be discussed in detail in the next chapter.

Al-Fârâbï regards the relation between astronomy, physics, and metaphysics as reciprocal, rather than unilateral, and he believes that the latter can in turn benefit from astronomy and the other particular sciences. Astronomy depends on metaphysics and physics for some of its principles, but it can in return contribute to these sciences by providing them with knowledge of certain existents with which phys­ics and metaphysics also deal. These existents chiefly consist of the planets and orbs, and an example might be the discovery of new stars through astronomical observation, as well as the calculation of their distances, sizes, etc. In this manner, astronomy can contribute to one’s knowledge of the existents subsumed under a certain genus, which may be of value to metaphysics as well. On the other hand, astronomy will not be able to explain why this particular star exists, a question which requires an aetiological account that transcends the astronomi­cal discipline.

But more significantly, astronomy may also shed light on the meta­physical beings such as the separate intellects, and particularly on the question of their number. This statement might appear more surprising at first glance, given that the immaterial existents do not fall within the subject matter of astronomy. Yet according to al-Farabi and later Ibn Sina, who follow Aristotle directly on this point, the question of the number of the separate intellects or unmoved movers hinges to some extent on the number of orbs identified by the astronomical disci- pline.[180] This view is reflected in Ibn Sinas statement in Metaphysics of Shifa that “the ultimate aim in this [metaphysical] science—namely, knowledge of God’s governance, knowledge of the spiritual angels and their ranks, and knowledge of the order of the arrangement of the spheres—can only be arrived at through astronomy,” and it is also inti­mated in Themistius’ paraphrase of Metaphysics.[181] These testimonies are important insofar as they show that the philosophical motivation for practicing astronomy partly stems from the belief that it may con­tribute to the progress of metaphysical knowledge.[182]

Accordingly, al-Farabi writes in Burhan that “things that are proven in astronomy are used as first premises in metaphysics and physics.”[183] And he elaborates on this point shortly afterwards by adding that

The prior sciences provide the posterior sciences with knowledge of the causes or knowledge of the causes and existence [wujüd] together, whereas the posterior sciences provide the prior sciences with knowledge of the existents alone. For example, the art of astronomy provides physics and metaphysics with [knowledge of] many aspects of the existents that are comprised by them.[184]

In this passage, al-Farabi is following the Aristotelian distinction between proof of the fact and proof of the reasoned fact, although his emphasis here is between two different kinds of knowledge (marifah): knowledge of existence alone and knowledge of existence together with knowledge of the cause. The particular, posterior sciences such as astronomy can benefit metaphysics by providing it with knowledge of certain existents and by formulating demonstrations of the fact, or innt proofs. Hence, whereas the premises borrowed by astronomy from metaphysics consist in knowledge of the causes (asbab), the knowledge that metaphysicians derive from astronomy can only be used as “evi­dential proofs” (dalail).[185]

In view of the foregoing, al-Fârâbï’s conception of the method of astronomy and of how the various sciences relate to one another may be schematized as follows:

 

Figure 2: The principles of astronomy and the interrelatedness of the sciences according to al-Fârâbï

It should be noted that the application of the innt /limmt distinction to al-Fârâbï’s classification of the sciences and to astronomy in particular raises several problems. As J. F. Ragep explains, Arabic astronomers interpreted this conceptual distinction in an idiosyncratic way. “In contrast with Aristotle,” he writes, “Arabic mathematical astronomers do not see themselves as giving proofs of the reasoned fact, but rather of the fact. These “facts,” however, are not observations but rather the configuration (haya) of the simple bodies.”[186] On the one hand, this point seems to correspond to al-Fârâbï’s position quite accurately. In the passage from Müsïqâ cited earlier, al-Fârâbï explains that the astronomer by himself cannot explain why the planets have regular, circular motions. As al-Fârâbï writes, “he is not able to establish [laysa yumkinu an yatabayyana] this at all in astronomy, but only by borrow­ing accepted [premises] [musallamatan] from the natural scientists.”[187] Since astronomy is dependent on physics and metaphysics for explain­ing the causes of celestial motion, it would seem that its capacity for limmï proofs is limited or even nil.

On the other hand, in the same passage of Müsïqâ, al-Fârâbï calls the eccentrics and epicycles “asbab” which suggests that other types of causes underlying celestial motion can be identified by the astronomer. The Second Teacher seems to be alluding here to an astronomical account that transcends the mere observation of phenomena and that can explain why motion occurs by relying on the planetary models. This interpretation assumes that the eccentrics and epicycles are bodies invested with a motive power and that they are thus part of the physical reality of the cosmos (see ch. 2, 1.1. and 1.2.). Accordingly, once the astronomer has borrowed the required principles from physics, he can then go on to elaborate his own proofs of why the planets move in par­ticular directions. In astronomical terminology, sabab can refer to an ‘explanation’ of a planet’s motion through models such as the epicycles and eccentrics. In this case, however, it is possible that al-Fârâbï is using the term asbab with the intention of conveying the dual meaning of ‘explanation’ and ‘cause.’ Not only was there a semantic overlap between the two concepts in Arabic philosophy, but al-Fârâbï clearly ascribes corporeal existence to the eccentrics and epicycles, thus potentially transforming them into causes of the planets’ motions. The latter are not merely abstract devices, but real bodies that play a role in the actu­alization of planetary motions.

This interpretation is reinforced by the fact that in al-Fârâbï’s philosophical works, sabab/asbab designates the causes or principles (mabâdi’) of existence of the lower entities. By way of illustration, God is described as a “proximate cause [al-sabab al-qarïb] of the existence of the secondary causes [i.e., the separate intellects or thawanï]” while the separate intellects themselves are “causes [asbab] of the existence of the celestial bodies.”[188] The term ‘cause’ surely has a different meaning in the metaphysical and astronomical contexts, in the sense that the eccentrics and epicycles are not principles of existence in the way that the separate intellects are. But the fact that al-Farabi describes these devices by means of the same term suggests that they may have an effi­cient role to play in the motion of the planets. In spite of this, it is unclear to what extent the eccentric and epicyclic models developed within the astronomical discipline and adopted by the philosophers represent a proof in the full sense and what their explanatory value is with respect to kinematic causality. Moreover, it is unclear whether the examination of the eccentrics and epicycles qua bodies and motive causes should still be considered a part of astronomy and should not rather be viewed as belonging to the field of physics.[189] Further research on these issues in the works of Arabic astronomers and philosophers is a desideratum.

2.4. Al-Farabt and the Later hay’ah Tradition

The idea that physics and metaphysics can be a source of astronomical principles is found several centuries later in the works of two of the most important hay’ah practitioners, Nasi r al-Din al-Tu si and Muayyad al-Din al-Urdi.[190] At the beginning of Al-tadhkirah ft ‘ilm al-hayah, al-Tusi explains that “those of its [astronomy] principles that need proof are demonstrated in three sciences: metaphysics, geometry, and natural philosophy.”[191] As was mentioned before, al-Farabi also believes that these three sciences provide some of the principles of astronomy, and he mentions geometry and physics explicitly. Furthermore, although al-Tusi does not elaborate on the metaphysical principles he has in mind, he subordinates some sciences to others and integrates astronomy in a hierarchy that culminates with metaphysics in a man­ner reminiscent of al-Farabi.

The emphasis placed by al-Fârâbï and the hay’ah practitioners on the role of physics does not stem only from a methodological concern about how to derive first principles, but also indicates a desire to pro­vide a comprehensive cosmological picture, i.e., one that can simulta­neously account for the mathematical theories behind celestial phenomena and for the physical arrangement of the orbs and planets. These thinkers believed that the physical laws at play in the superlu­nary realm had to be understood in order to elaborate a valid astro­nomical model that would be in agreement with reality.[192] Al-Fârâbï and al-Tusï share a common concern for the physicality of the astro­nomical models they discuss, and both thinkers endow the orbs with concrete existence. As al-Tusï writes: “Restricting oneself to circles is sufficient in the entirety of this science [astronomy] for whoever stud­ies the proofs. However, one who attempts to understand the principles [mabadi’] of the motions must know the configuration [hay’ah] of the bodies [i.e., must understand their physical configuration].”[193] Al-Tu sï then goes on to describe the deferent, concentric, and eccentric as orbs (aflak) and the epicycle as a sphere (kurah) possessing corporeal exist­ence. He also mentions the surface and thickness of these bodies, thus providing a detailed description of the physical features of his models. Al-Fârâbï also provides a description of these celestial bodies in Ára, although it is less detailed and occurs in a different philosophical context.[194]

Hence, al-Fârâbï’s approach is in many fundamental ways similar to that of these later hay’ah practitioners. These thinkers share the view that astronomy derives some of its principles from physics; that a valid astronomical model must exhibit a harmony between mathemati­cal theories and physical principles, which implies a physical inter­pretation of the heavenly orbs; and that ultimately it is metaphysics that represents the crowning science under which astronomy is subsumed. They were conversant with Almagest, On the Heavens, and Metaphysics and tried to integrate the various and sometimes conflicting theories expressed in these seminal works into a unified picture of the cosmos. This makes al-Farabi a link in the long chain that goes from Geminus, Ptolemy, and Simplicius, through al-Bïrûnï and Ibn Sina, to al-Tusi, al-‘Urdi, and the Maragha School of the thirteenth and fourteenth cen­turies. More specifically, there are obvious similarities between the astronomical outlook of Geminus, al-Farabi, Ibn Sina, and al-Tûsi, which enable one to perceive some continuity in the way these thinkers conceived of this discipline. If al-Farabi did not belong to the hayah tradition proper, he may nevertheless be said to have anticipated and adopted some of the essential features that characterized its later development.[195]

3. Demonstration and Analogy: A Tension in al-Fârâbt’s Method

3.1. The Evidence for and against Demonstration

Having clarified al-Farabi’s conception of the interrelatedness of the cosmological sciences and of the place and method of astronomy, I now wish to turn to other methodological and epistemological issues, and in particular to the question of the human capacity to know super­lunary phenomena. The previous discussion stressed the primacy of metaphysics in the cosmological inquiry and its unique ability to define the ultimate causes of reality. The questions that now confront us per­tain to the epistemological scope of this science and the method deemed appropriate to establish cosmological proofs. What is the place of dem­onstration (burhan) and of the other kinds of philosophical argumen­tation in al-Fârâbï’s cosmological works? And can the philosopher ever hope to fully understand the superlunary phenomena?

To begin with, it is necessary to inquire whether, according to al-Fârâbï, it is possible to formulate proofs of a cosmological nature, and if so, what kind of proof it is. This is all the more important, given that some medieval thinkers denied the capacity of human reason to solve cosmological aporias, and that some modern historians have questioned al-Fârâbï’s belief in demonstration. The first point is illus­trated by a passage of Guide in which Maimonides argues that Aristotle’s arguments in On the Heavens completely lack the certainty associated with the demonstrative method; and he adds that Aristotle himself was aware of this, yet wanted to convince his audience through rhetorical and dialectical means that the universe is eternal.[196] Maimonides’ stance on this particular issue rests on the claim that demonstrative argu­ments cannot be adduced to prove or disprove such conundrums, which lie well beyond the human ken. As Maimonides writes in the Guide,

it is impossible for us to accede to the points starting from which conclu­sions may be drawn about the heavens; for the latter are too far away from us and too high in place and in rank. And even the general conclu­sion that may be drawn from them, namely, that they prove the existence of their Mover, is a matter the knowledge of which cannot be reached by human intellects.[197]

Maimonides’ criticism of Aristotle raises the important question of the types of proofs and methods used by medieval authors in their han­dling of cosmological problems. What was al-Fârâbï’s position and how do Maimonides’ comments on the limits of human knowledge relate to his philosophy? There are no statements by al-Fârâbï that immediately come to mind that suggest that he shared Maimonides’ skepticism con­cerning cosmological knowledge. Nor is there any indication that al-Fârâbï limits demonstration to the mathematical method proper to astronomy, as Ptolemy had. Before we turn to a study of al-Fârâbï’s works, it should be noted that Maimonides himself provides evidence for the fact that al-Fârâbï would not have agreed with him. This is made clear when Maimonides writes:

However, you know Abu Nasr ’s [al-Fârâbï’s] interpretation of this exam­ple, what he made clear with regard to it, as well as the fact that he con­sidered disgraceful the notion that Aristotle could have doubted of the eternity of the world. He had an extreme contempt for Galen because of the latter’s saying that this was an obscure question with regard to which no demonstration is known. As Abu Nasr holds, it is clear and manifest, being proved by demonstration that the heavens are eternal whereas that which is within them is subject to generation and passing-away.[198]

According to Maimonides, then, al-Fârâbï believed that it is possible to settle the question of whether the world is created ex nihilo or is eternal through demonstrative proof. Both thinkers disagree on this crucial point: whereas Maimonides uses philosophical arguments that are as close as possible to demonstration, but which are in essence dialectical or rhetorical, to try to convince the reader and ultimately relies on scripture as the decisive criterion, al-Fârâbï believes that it is possible to formulate demonstrative arguments by relying on human reason alone. This, at any rate, is what may be inferred from Guide.

Maimonides’ testimony is partially vindicated by the information that can be gleaned from al-Fârâbï’s corpus. We know that al-Fârâbï paid particular attention in his works to the various types of argumen­tation at the disposal of philosophers (such as rhetoric, dialectic, and demonstration) and that he associated each type of discourse with a specific social activity or group, as his commentaries on the Organon and his emanationist treatises amply show. In these texts, al-Fârâbï carefully distinguishes between demonstration on the one hand, which is the privilege of the philosophers, and dialectical, rhetorical, and poetical modes of expression on the other, which are used by theolo­gians and other groups within society. In the following paragraphs, I wish to stress the connection al-Fârâbï establishes between philoso­phy and demonstration and show that in his view cosmological and metaphysical problems could be addressed demonstratively.

In K. al-jadal, in a passage which may or may not be the one implic­itly referred to by Maimonides above, al-Fârâbï describes two ways of approaching the question of the eternity of the world. He writes:

‘Is the world eternal a parte ante [azali] or not?’ [Topica, 1.11.104b14- 16]. ... This example he [Aristotle] proposes is very dialectical under one aspect, since when we say “is the world eternal a parte ante or not?”, inso­far as we employ this wording, it is not possible at all that we produce a certain syllogism [qiyas yaqini], neither of the fact that it is eternal a parte ante nor of the fact that it is not eternal a parte ante. For our word “the world” is an ambiguous word and, moreover, taken as indefinite. So, if the world is taken in its entirety in such a way, [it will be found to have] many parts, one of which is clearly not eternal a parte ante, another such that it is possible to produce about it a syllogism showing that it is eternal a parte ante, and another of unclear status. Thus, when we take the world in its entirety, it is sometimes eternity a parte ante which is imagined, and sometimes incipience, so that we always produce opposed syllogisms. The only way then is to examine, for each of its parts, whether it is eternal a parte ante or not, and in how many ways a thing can be eternal a parte ante, and in how many ways it is said to be not eternal. This is the method leading to the production of its demonstration [wa-hadha huwa l-tariq ila musadafah burhanihi], whereas according to the first method, it is not possible to produce its demonstration, the syllogisms produced being opposed syllogisms in each case.[199]

In this passage, which is obviously of primary importance to under­stand al-Fârâbï’s method, the author begins by expressing doubt as to whether syllogistic reasoning can solve the problem of the eternity of the world. If taken as a whole, this question can only lead the inquirer into conflicting opinions, and this is the problem of the dialectical approach. But true demonstration is ultimately possible if one breaks down the initial proposition into components that are then analyzed individually. Al-Fârâbï’s conclusion in this respect is explicit: “this is the method [tariq] leading to the production of its demonstration [burhan]”

The explanation given in Topica concerning the proper mode to carry out a cosmological demonstration is echoed in Tahstl, which shows the degree of al-Fârâbï’s preoccupation with this problem. In this work, al-Fârâbï reiterates the point that mustering demonstrative proofs in order to reach certain knowledge is a difficult task that is replete with all kinds of pitfalls. Most of the time, when people think they are using demonstration, they are instead relying on other non­demonstrative methods, which is why they reach different and some­times contradictory conclusions, or they apply demonstration only to part of what they seek, thinking that they are applying it to the entire thing sought, which again leads to a diversity of conclusions.[200] The main point to emerge from al-Fârâbï’s remarks is that aporias such as the question of the creation vs. eternity of the world are difficult to solve by relying on a single demonstration, since they contain various components and aspects that call for a variety of proofs and disciplines. Al-Fârâbï does not elaborate on how the philosopher should carry out this systematic breakdown of the initial problem into its constituent parts and on what disciplines he should rely to study them. But keeping in mind what was said previously concerning his method, one may hypothesize that this approach should, in al-Fârâbï’s view, rely on the fundamental notion of the interrelatedness of the sciences. Accordingly, and with regard to the problem of eternity, physics and astronomy may contribute to its solution by examining the substance and motion of the superlunary bodies, and metaphysics by examining beings in gen­eral and the immaterial existents and their influence on the corporeal world in particular. All of these sciences would therefore study one aspect of the problem by focusing on the objects that fall within their field.

The accumulated evidence in K. al-jadal and Tahsïl does not in any way invalidate al-Fârâbï’s belief in the value of demonstration. Rather, these passages support Maimonides’ testimony in an unequivocal way, even though they point to his awareness of the methodological diffi­culty of correctly implementing demonstration and of the reason why there are so many wide-ranging opinions on physical and metaphysical matters among the thinkers of his time.[201] While he endorsed demon­stration, al-Fârâbï was also fully aware of the discrepancy between the­ory and practice and of the necessity to adapt the inquiry and the philosophical method to the type of problem examined. This helps to explain why he proceeds carefully when addressing such complex ques­tions as the eternity of the world in his own works and why he does not provide elaborate and extensive proofs to this effect.[202] In this respect, it is not surprising that the passages cited above provide only limited information on al-Fârâbï’s own position concerning the question of the eternity of the world. This aspect of his methodology has far reaching consequences that should be borne in mind when analyzing his cos­mological doctrines.

At any rate, the views expressed in K. al-jadal and Tahsïl also find support in al-Fârâbï’s Burhân. Like its original Greek counterpart, Posterior Analytics, it is primarily devoted to the demonstrative syllo­gism (qiyâs burhânï) and reveals the extent of al-Fârâbï’s interest in the theoretical framework behind demonstrative reasoning. More specifi­cally, al-Fârâbï develops the theory of the burhân mutlaq (absolute or unconditional demonstration), which combines knowledge of the existent and knowledge of the cause, or put another way, consists in knowledge of the fact as well as the reasoned fact. In this passage, he makes it clear that this is the method that should be used in the theo­retical sciences, such as physics and metaphysics.[203] Now since the substance of the heavens, the existence of the separate intellects, and the creation or eternity of the world are questions that belong to phys­ics and metaphysics, al-Fârâbï certainly believed, at least in theory, that these questions ought to be answered using the demonstrative method.

Further evidence supporting al-Fârâbï’s belief in the possibility of cosmological demonstration may be gleaned from his non-logical texts as well. In Tahstl, the primacy of the theoretical sciences is asserted, as is its capacity to produce certain knowledge.[204] In Jam’, which, it should be noted, is a problematic work as far as its authenticity is concerned, al-Fârâbï explains that Plato and Aristotle gave “clear and persuasive proofs” (hujaj wadihah muqniah) and “demonstrations” (barahm) to settle cosmological questions such as the creation of the world, although he does not elaborate on this statement.[205] Furthermore, in Âra he writes

It follows necessarily from the specific being of the First that all the other existents which do not come into existence through man’s will and choice are brought into existence by the First in their various kinds of existence, some of which can be observed by sense perception, whereas others become known by demonstration [wa-baduhü malüm bi-l-burhan].[206]

Although al-Fârâbï does not identify these “other existents,” there is little doubt that they include both the celestial bodies and the imma­terial beings below the First Cause, the separate intellects. This is confirmed in another passage of the same work, when al-Fârâbï states that among the common first intelligibles (al-maqülat al-uwal al- mushtarakah)[207] that humans acquire are

the principles [mabadi‘] which are used for knowing the existents which are not the objects of man’s actions, and their primary principles and ranks: such as the heavens [al-samawat] and the First Cause [al-sabab al-awwal] and the other primary principles and what happens to come to be out of those primary principles.[208]

Al-Fârâbï unambiguously states not only that human beings are predis­posed for acquiring knowledge of the heavens, but that the “first intel­ligibles” that lead to such knowledge are commonly shared by all humans. Having listed the various things that “the people of the excel­lent city ought to know,” which include knowledge of the First Cause, of the immaterial existents, and of the heavenly bodies, al-Fârâbï goes on to explain that

these things can be known in two ways: either by being impressed on their souls as they really are [kama hiya mawjüdah] or by being impressed on them through affinity and symbolic representation. ... The philoso­phers in the city are those who know these things through demonstra­tions [bi-bamhm] and their own insight.[209]

The evidence from al-Fârâbï’s own hand coheres with modern recon­structions of his arguments. M. Rashed’s recent study of On Changing Beings shows that this treatise originally contained an argument aimed at refuting Philoponus and at establishing the eternity of time and motion, and, hence, of the world. Approaching the question from a dif­ferent angle, P. Vallat has convincingly shown that al-Fârâbï intended various passages of his works to stand as implicit arguments for the world’s eternity.[210]

On the basis of the cumulative evidence contained in al-Fârâbï’s log­ical and metaphysical treatises, one may conclude that the Second Teacher considered demonstration not only possible, but also the proper method to use in cosmological inquiry. Al-Fârâbï’s belief in the primacy and validity of demonstration is substantiated throughout his corpus in innumerable instances, and considerable effort is required to ignore them. Al-Fârâbï makes it clear that demonstration is the highest philosophical method and that it is the only true means for humans to acquire the intelligibles “as they really are.” The theoretical sciences that use demonstration are described as a model for the other kinds of arts and disciplines, even though the latter can only provide symbolic imi­tations or approximations of their results. In light of this, it is not sur­prising that al-Fârâbï equates burhan with falsafah in his introductory work Nass al-tawti’ah.[211] As G. Endress writes, “al-Fârâbï added to ear­lier concepts of philosophy in Islam the radically Aristotelian concept of philosophy as a demonstrative science which proves universally what in the particular sciences is deduced by particular ‘indications’ or ‘signs.’ ”[212] Al-Fârâbï accepted Aristotle’s concept of demonstrative proof and considered it philosophy’s task to provide certain knowledge of, among other things, cosmological questions like the eternity of the world.[213]

In spite of the foregoing, however, al-Fârâbï’s views on demonstra­tion and certain knowledge are sometimes difficult to reconcile with the method and style of his treatises. Indeed, al-Fârâbï does not sys­tematically implement his theory of demonstration in his extant cos­mological and metaphysical works. Although he adopted Aristotle’s syllogistics and theory of demonstration and accepted their applicabil­ity to cosmology, the question remains as to why his writings, and Ára and Siyasah in particular, are devoid of extensive demonstrative proofs. For example, al-Fârâbï, unlike Ibn Sïnâ, does not demonstrate the existence of the separate intellects, nor does he try to justify their number and explain why there cannot be an infinite series of intel­lects.[214] And unlike al-Kindï, al-Fârâbï does not provide any argument concerning the ensoulment and rationality of the celestial orbs as well as the question of whether they possess the senses of vision and hear­ing. More disturbingly, the Second Teacher does not articulate an explicit and elaborate proof for the eternity of the world in his later metaphysical treatises. This discrepancy between theory and practice must be accounted for.

One way of explaining it is to focus on the genre and purpose of these works. Ára and Siyasah possess a condensed, adumbrated for­mat that point to their potential didactic function. Whether these trea­tises are the embodiment of years of oral teaching and transmission, as Vallat suggests,[215] or were designed to convey in summary form the gist of al-Fârâbï’s mature philosophy, it is clear that their style and structure are not adapted to contain long, protracted arguments. Far from being a unique phenomenon in the history of Arabic philosophy and science, this type of treatise belongs to a wider literary genre char­acterized by this particular mode of exposition and which privileges a descriptive style over a demonstrative one. For example, the hay ah bastía h genre that developed in Arabic astronomy deliberately shunned demonstration.[216] In the philosophical tradition, short treatises such as Ibn Sïnâ’s Danesh-nameh and Mabda, as well as the Avicennan‘Uyün al-hikmah fulfill a similar function and contrast with his exhaustive «

treatment of philosophical topics in Shifa. This does not mean that these works are unscientific, but merely that their primary aim was to convey in a clear and condensed form doctrines that had been proved and discussed at length in other works. If al-Fârâbï’s Ára and Siyasah were designed to give this kind of philosophical overview or if they are the product of oral transmission, then it is understandable that they would shun elaborate demonstrations. Seen from this perspective, it would seem that, far from being exceptions, these works belong to a well-established scientific and philosophical tradition in medieval Arabic literature.[217] [218] One may reasonably surmise that al-Fârâbï pro­vided longer demonstrations in some of his other and no longer extant works, such as his commentary on Physics and perhaps his treatise entitled K. fï l-'ilm al-ilahi.20S

Al-Fârâbï’s reluctance to engage in protracted demonstrative argu­ments may nevertheless have deeper philosophical roots. As was stressed earlier, he was aware of the practical limitations and difficulty of demonstration, especially when it came to addressing general cos­mological problems. But his genuine interest in Aristotelian syllogistics may also have been counter-balanced by a penchant for the aporetic doctrine of the Neoplatonists and the notion of divine transcendence. It is in this connection that I wish to discuss an important epistemologi­cal concept, namely, analogy, which plays a crucial didactic and cogni­tive role in al-Fârâbï’s cosmology and in his philosophy as a whole.

3.2.    The Limits of Human Knowledge and the Role of Analogy

The analysis has up to this point underscored al-Fârâbï’s belief in the knowability of heavenly phenomena and in the possibility of adducing demonstrative arguments to prove their existence. Besides this positive evidence, however, a different picture emerges from other passages of al-Fârâbï’s works, suggesting that only a limited knowledge of the met­aphysical beings is possible. From a cosmological standpoint, this is problematic, insofar as these immaterial principles govern the celestial bodies, with the implication that they must first be defined in order for one to fully grasp the nature of the heavens. Although this kind of evi­dence does not contradict al-Fârâbï’s belief in demonstration, it raises the question of whether the human inquiry into the cosmos is after all limited.

In various passages of his works, al-Fârâbï displays a marked skepticism towards the possibility of acquiring direct knowledge of superlunary beings, especially of God. One gets the impression that he denies humans full access to the divine world. For example, in Jam, he writes:

Thus we say: since the Creator, may His Majesty be dignified, differs in substance and essence from anything else in that He is of a more vener­able, more excellent, and higher species, nothing is analogous to, resem­bles, or is similar to His substance either in truth or metaphorically. Yet, despite this, we cannot avoid describing Him and applying to Him some of these synonymous utterances [alfaz min hadhihi l-mutawati‘ah]. It is therefore necessarily requisite for us to know that with each utterance we state as one of His attributes, He remains in essence remote from the idea we conceptualize from that utterance.[219]

And later on he adds:

One should know that necessity dictates applying synonymous utter­ances from physics and logic to those subtle and venerable ideas that are exalted above all descriptions and divergent from all the things that come into being and exist naturally. ... Since necessity stands as an obstacle and intervenes between us and that, we limit ourselves to exist­ing utterances, forcing ourselves to bear in mind that the divine mean­ings [al-ma'dm l-ilahiyyah] we express by means of these utterances are of a more venerable species and are other than we imagine and conceptualize.[220]

A similar point of view is expressed in the emanationist treatises:

It is difficult and hard for us to apprehend It [the First Cause] and to rep­resent It to ourselves, because of the weakness of our intellectual facul­ties, mixed as they are with matter and non-being [al-maddah wa-l- ‘adam]: we are too weak to think It as It really is.[221]

And:

The pleasure which the First enjoys is a pleasure whose character we do not understand and whose intensity we fail to apprehend, except by anal­ogy [bi-l-qiyas] and by relating it to the amount of pleasure which we feel.[222]

In a similar vein al-Fârâbï explains in Müstqâ:

And the method that the theorist who cannot discern these harmonic beings [i.e., some musical notes] will use to represent them is the method through which he conceives things that cannot be perceived by the senses, such as the soul, the intellect, prime matter, and all of the separate existents. Indeed, those things cannot be used or studied that cannot be imagined at all; since their imagining is not possible through the senses, another method was devised in order to imagine them, and this is what is called the method of comparison [muqayasah] and the method of analogy [munâsabah].[223]

Two important points are reflected in these passages. First, they show al-Fârâbï’s awareness of the limits of metaphysical knowledge, or at least his awareness of the difficulty humans experience in acquiring this type of knowledge. The passage from Müsïqâ in particular high­lights the fact that the direct apprehension of the immaterial existents— including the separate intellects and the First Cause—is not possible and requires the mediation of analogical techniques. This skeptical fea­ture of al-Fârâbï’s epistemology has already been noted by some schol­ars, who have compared it to the via negativa of Christian theology or the aporetic ontology of Neoplatonism.[224] Second, these excerpts describe analogical reasoning as a privileged method for acquiring insight into the intelligible world. In Müsïqâ, again, al-Fârâbï advises the aspiring musical theorist to rely, like the metaphysician, on com­parison and analogy in order to acquire some knowledge of the intel­ligible things that lie beyond the realm of sense perception. Analogy is described as a bridge linking the physical and metaphysical worlds and as the only means available to humans to catch a glimpse of the realm of the intelligible.

One question worth asking is whether al-Fârâbï’s skepticism about the knowability of the intelligible beings extends to the celestial bodies as well. Maimonides’ statement in Guide (2.25.54b) seems to deny humans substantial, if not partial, astronomical and cosmological knowledge.[225] Al-Fârâbï does not openly admit that such knowledge is impossible, but the previously quoted excerpts could point to such a view. Yet there are several reasons to believe that this was not the case. The aforementioned passages mention immaterial beings, especially the First, but the celestial bodies are corporeal and as such can be per­ceived and studied by the senses, as al-Fârâbï explains in Tahstl.[226] In addition, al-Fârâbï highly values the empirical and observational approach in astronomy, a fact that did not escape Ibn Rushd, who stresses the importance al-Fârâbï placed on sense perception in his cos­mological method.[227] In Burhân al-Fârâbï explains that the particular sciences such as astronomy and physics can benefit the metaphysical inquiry by providing some kind of knowledge of the heavens and even of the immaterial beings that govern them, since the number of unmoved movers partly depends on the study of celestial motions. Finally, in Falsafat Aristü ta Its, the transition between the study of motion and the hypothesis of a first unmoved mover responsible for the beginning of motion is brought out in his discussion of Physics.[228] True, al-Fârâbï is here describing Aristotle’s methodology, but M. Rashed has shown that he adopted a similar analytical approach to prove the eternity of the world in his lost work Al-mawjüdât al-mutaghayyirah.[229]

These points show clearly that al-Fârâbï considered knowledge of celestial phenomena and of the orbs and planets possible, although his attitude toward the metaphysical beings and especially the First remains ambiguous. But more attention should be given to al-Fârâbï’s com­ments on analogy, which he praises as a philosophical tool in various passages of his works. How is analogy to be employed and how does it fit in his epistemological scheme? More specifically, what is the cosmo­logical relevance of analogy? In spite of the fact that texts such as Müstqâ clearly stress the value of analogical reasoning, they offer virtu­ally no indication as to how this method should be utilized. In order to shed light on this problem, it is necessary to examine in more detail al-Fârâbï’s conception of analogical techniques and particularly the method of transference.

3.3.    Transferred Terms (asma manqülah) and Transference (naqlah)

During the ninth and tenth centuries, Arabic philosophical terminol­ogy was slowly crystallizing as a result of the translation movement from Greek to Arabic and the intense intellectual activity that devel­oped in urban centers such as Baghdad. Al-Fârâbï appeared on the scene during this period, and his contribution to the formation of a distinctive Arabic philosophical vocabulary was significant, as modern studies have shown.[230] Al-Fârâbï also developed a quite nuanced theory of the evolution of language, which can be found in his works on logic and Hurüf More specifically, al-Fârâbï’s conception of how specialized philosophical terminology is shaped has a direct bearing on the study of his cosmology and may help to explain some points of method proper to the emanationist works.

On the one hand, al-Fârâbï believes that the specialized terminolo­gies of the sciences are elaborated gradually over a protracted period of time. He is aware that some terms are transmitted from one culture to another and subsequently undergo a process of assimilation in their new cultural environment. As a philosopher, al-Fârâbï derived much of his technical vocabulary from the Arabic translations of the Greek works he read. For his cosmology and natural philosophy, for example, he had access to a set of technical terms transliterated or translated from works such as On the Heavens, On Generation and Corruption, Meteorology, and Physics. To give a few examples, the Arabic surah cor­responds to the Greek pop^q, hayula and maddah to nXq, mawdu to nnoKeipevov, and tabïah to ^finiç. Likewise, falak renders the Greek c^aipa or kùkæoç, while kawkab is, like the Greek àorqp, a generic term that can refer to the stars, the planets, and the sun.[231] Hence, the basic conceptual and terminological framework that al-Fârâbï utilizes in his description of the cosmos is indebted to the ancient and late antique philosophical and astronomical traditions. These examples illustrate the terminological and conceptual continuity between ancient Greek and early Arabic cosmology and natural philosophy.

On the other hand, al-Fârâbï is aware that many other terms enter the philosophical discipline as a result of developments within a given culture. It is often the case that terms used in a popular context acquire a specialized meaning over time. Jawhar, for example, which for the masses designates a precious stone, acquired the technical meaning of ‘substance’ as a result of the development of philosophy.[232] [233] Jawhar is an example of what al-Fârâbï calls a “transferred term” (al-ism al-manqül). Al-Fârâbï describes this linguistic phenomenon in detail in some of his logical works, as in K. al-‘ibarah or his commentary on Aristotle’s On Interpretation and in the appending treatise on the same subject enti­tled Short Treatise on Aristotle’s De interpretatione.113 In the latter work, al-Fârâbï defines “transferred terms” (al-asma l-manqülah) as follows:

A term is transferred if a word generally known to have been the signi­fier of a certain thing ever since it was first introduced is later taken and used to signify a certain other thing, but remains the common name of the first and the second. This situation arises when discoveries are made by developing disciplines. ... The discoverer then transfers to them the names of similar things generally known; for every new thing he introduces the name of the known thing he thinks is most closely akin to it.[234]

Shortly thereafter (sec. 53), al-Fârâbï again mentions jawhar as an example to explain the relation between transference and homonymy: “Transferred terms are often used homonymously in the fields to which they have been transferred, like the term jawhar, which is transferred to the theoretical sciences and used homonymously there.” This quota­tion is important insofar as it shows that for al-Fârâbï at least some transferred terms possess an intrinsic homonymous quality.[235]

A passage in Ihsa ’ provides a relevant case study of how certain terms come to be transferred and enter the methodology of the philosophers:

Indeed, shape, form, and design [al-sïghah wa-l-sürah wa-l-khalqah] are almost synonymous [mutaradifah] terms that the masses [jumhür] use to indicate the shapes of animals and artificial bodies. But by way of similar­ity [or analogy] [‘ala tarlq al-tashbih], they were transferred [nuqilat] and were made into nouns that refer to the faculties [al-quwa] and things whose status in the natural bodies is that of shapes, forms, and designs in artificial bodies.

And al-Fârâbï adds, “this is because it is customary in the arts [or sci­ences, sanat] to transfer by means of similarity to the objects they con­tain [i.e., study] the names which have been established by the masses.”[236] Here we notice that al-Fârâbï establishes a connection between the process of transference and the concept of similarity (tashbth). Hence, although the two previous passages indicate that some transferred terms are homonymous, they may also point to similar characteristics in the various subjects they qualify. One may argue that it is precisely this similarity between the two things compared that enables transfer­ence to occur, in which case transference could be seen as a kind of analogical reasoning.

From the foregoing comments, we may infer that al-Fârâbï would have considered the technical terms he uses in his physics and cosmol­ogy to fall in the category of transferred terms. After all, jism, sürah, mawdü, and nafs, to give only a few examples, have a popular meaning that harks back to the invention of language, and it is only at a specific point in time that they acquired a technical and more specific philo­sophical meaning. These terms had prior significations before they were applied to cosmology or physics: sürah may refer to the shape or contour of a thing, while mawdü is a grammatical term meaning ‘sub­ject.’ It is only as a result of a gradual process that they were transferred from a popular usage to a more specialized semantic sphere. That these transferred terms end up constituting the nomenclature of philoso­phers is confirmed when al-Fârâbï writes that “transferred terms are used in sciences and other disciplines for things whose knowledge is peculiar to specialists.”[237]

Although transferred terms are in themselves important to under­stand al-Fârâbï’s perception of the evolution of philosophy, they go hand in hand with an important analogical method called naqlah, which al-Fârâbï appears to be using in his works. Indeed, the praise of analogy that one finds in Müsïqa is implemented in Âra and Siyasah, as well as in other works such as Fïl-aql. In these works, al-Fârâbï relies consistently on similarity and analogy to describe metaphysical, cos­mological, and psychological beings or concepts.[238] In Âra, for instance, al-Fârâbï explains that terms such as “living” (hayy) and “wise” (hakïm) can only be predicated of God by analogy with things in this world. God, indeed, is living and wise, but not in the same way that sublunary existents are, since God is immortal and eternal and has the “most per­fect existence,” while the latter are mortal and perishable.[239] By analogy with things already known to humans, one can get insight into God’s essence, although it will necessarily be a limited form of knowledge. This type of analogy relies on the notion of common or homonymous names (al-asma l-mushtarakah), which express the perfections that pertain to God in an absolute sense, and which common objects have in a relative and derived sense.[240]

In these same works, al-Fârâbï further explains that this analogical method is made possible by transferring terms from one realm to another, that is, from the human realm of sense perception to the intel­ligible realm of the divine. More specifically, the common names used in everyday speech to describe things can be transferred (nuqila) to other metaphysical beings and even to the First Cause itself. “When names like these are transferred [nuqilat] and applied to the First,” al-Fârâbï writes, “we have in mind to denote by them the relation the First has to other things by virtue of the existence which has been ema­nating from it.”[241] And in Siyasah, he writes that

these terms are applied to the First in the most prior and true manner and to anything else only by posteriority, but it is not unacceptable if our application of these terms to the First came after our application of them to something else—for clearly our application of many of them to the First is only by way of transferring them [‘ala jihat al-naql] from some­thing else to It and after we had applied them to something else for a time.[242]

The terms “transferred” to the metaphysical realm thus have a prior usage and meaning in the world of sense perception. Chronologically speaking, they are applied first to sublunary bodies and only then and by extension to the immaterial beings. This view coheres with al-Fârâbï’s understanding of the development of philosophical language as previ­ously discussed. Moreover, we can see from these quotations that the homonymous and transferred terms that al-Fârâbï defines in his works on logic, such as K. al-‘ibarah, are actually implemented and used in Ára and Siyasah in his philosophical discussions about the First and the other metaphysical beings. This points to the close connection between al-Fârâbï’s logical treatises and his cosmological works.

Given the importance these transferred terms play in al-Fârâbï’s descriptions of the First Cause, it is not surprising that he uses the same technique to describe the celestial bodies. In Árü’ and Siyasah, he compares the forms and substrates of the celestial bodies to those of sublunary bodies. The heavenly substrates “resemble” (tushbihu) the sublunary material substrates, while the souls of the heavenly bodies “resemble” (tushbihu) or are “like” (ka) the sublunary forms.[243] Al-Fârâbï uses analogical language to compare the celestial bodies to the hylo- morphic bodies of the sublunary world without establishing an identity between the two. Hence, terms belonging to sublunary physics are “transferred” to the heavens. This practice is described in K. al-qiyas, which contains an entire section on the epistemological status of infer­ence and more precisely on a technique al-Fârâbï calls naqlah, transfer­ence.[244] According to him, this technique is also what the theologians call “inference from the evident to the absent.”[245] In the passage under discussion, al-Fârâbï provides an analysis of this type of inference, of its aim, of the conditions necessary for its conclusions to be valid, and he also explains how it may be put into syllogistic form. As he himself puts it, the aim of this section of the treatise is to “discuss the ‘transfer’ from a judgment by [immediate] sensation in some matter [amr], or [direct] knowledge about it by some other approach, to another matter outside the realm of [immediate] sensation.”[246] In essence, naqlah consists in ascribing a certain quality to a thing that is not known to us on the basis of other things that are known to us to possess this quality. Naturally, the two objects compared must present a valid commonality for transference to be effective. More specifically, this is how al-Fârâbï defines the technique of transference:

The manner of this “transfer” is: that it is known by sensation that a cer­tain “matter” [amr] is in a certain condition, and that a certain “thing” is present in a certain “matter”; and so the intellect consequently transfers this condition or thing from this [known] matter to some other [unknown] matter similar to it, and thus judges with respect to it [i.e., the other, unknown, “matter”] upon this [known] basis.[247]

Al-Fârâbï then goes on to explain that there are two modes of transfer­ence, analysis (tahltl) and synthesis (tarktb). If correctly conducted, these can be put into first figure syllogisms. Analysis begins with the thing that is sought, whereas synthesis begins with what is already known. In other words, analysis entails moving backward from the conclusion to the premises, whereas synthesis proceeds from the premises to the conclusion.[248]

The relation between transferred terms and the technique of trans­ference should appear clearly at this point. Al-Fârâbï’s discussion of naqlah in K. al-qiyas represents the logical formulation of and the pen­dant to the linguistic treatment of transferred terms (asma manqülah) that appears for instance in K. al-ibarah and that is implemented in Ára and Siyasah. According to al-Fârâbï, there is a natural progression from the phenomenon of transferred terms to the analogical technique of transference (naqlah). Conversely, one may view the appearance of transferred terms as the result of the practice of transference.

One could object at this point that the technique of naqlah, at least as it is described in K. al-qiyas, is to be attributed to the theologians and is not endorsed by al-Fârâbï himself. But this view is nevertheless unlikely. Al-Fârâbï merely remarks that the mutakallimün call this technique by another name (al-isdidlal bi-l-shahid ’ala l-ghaib) from the one he himself uses (naqlah), and he does not in any way confine its use to the theological camp. Al-Fârâbï’s comments in the introduction and conclusion of this treatise reveal that he viewed its contents as gen­uinely Aristotelian, although he explicitly says that its examples were chosen for a contemporary audience.

Of particular relevance in this respect is the fact that al-Fârâbï provides a cosmological example to illustrate the use of naqlah. He writes:

This [transference] occurs [for example] when one knows by sensation that some corporeal substances, like the animals and similar things, are created, and consequently the intellect transfers the createdness from the animals or plants, and thus judges about the sky and stars that they are [also] created.[249]

What is important for the present purpose is not the conclusion reached concerning the createdness of the celestial bodies, since al-Fârâbï informs the reader at the beginning of the treatise that his examples are chosen on the basis of their intelligibility and familiarity to a contem­porary audience. For this reason it would appear that it is not possible to ascribe to al-Fârâbï the philosophical positions that are reflected in the conclusions of these examples.[250] Rather, what is significant is the fact that al-Fârâbï chose a cosmological example to illustrate the use of transference, which implies the applicability of naqlah to cosmology. And so it is not surprising to find that al-Fârâbï often compares the celestial and sublunary bodies in his cosmological works, with the assumption that these beings possess similar principles simply by vir­tue of being bodies.[251] Some of these principles, such as form, matter, and soul, as well as the proposition of the perishability of bodies given in the example above, can be identified from experience and through the physical investigation of sublunary bodies, and then “transferred” to other remote substances, such as the stars and planets. Hence, noth­ing in K. al-qiyas suggests that the Second Teacher perceived naqlah as an invalid technique and one that was restricted to the theologi­cal camp. On the contrary, al-Fârâbï’s methodological comments on analogy in his logical works seem to have been implemented to some extent in his own metaphysical works, and one finds in all of these treatises an identical language of similarity or analogy based on the root sh-b-h.[252]

This may explain why, as K. Gyekye has remarked, al-Fârâbï argues for a greater tolerance (musamahah) toward the use of these analogi­cal techniques. And as N. Rescher notes, al-Fârâbï may have been responsible for developing the concept of transference to a considera­ble degree, since it is not to be found in such an elaborate form in Aristotle or other Greek authors.[253] This hypothesis also agrees with G. Freudenthal’s study of al-Fârâbï’s commentary on the first book of Euclid’s Elements, which deals with some of the conceptual prob­lems related to mathematical entities. There is a striking parallel in al-Fârâbï’s method and approach to these subjects, namely, that induc­tion and sense perception represent a starting point for the acquisition of knowledge. Al-Fârâbï’s cosmological example in the section on naqlah and his analogical language in the emanationist treatises illus­trate how it is possible to ascribe certain properties to the heavens on the basis of our experience of sublunary bodies. Likewise, in his commentary on geometry he advises the student to begin with bodies and progressively move to more abstract entities such as lines and points. Hence, in geometry, analysis implies a shift from physical three­dimensional bodies to abstract mathematical entities, and in cosmol­ogy, transference enables one to progress from the sublunary bodies and their principles (form, matter, and substrate) to more remote enti­ties such as the celestial bodies. Regardless of the disciplinary differ­ence between these two texts, their theories are grounded in similar epistemological and didactic assumptions: sense perception and our direct apprehension of reality are a foundation for further knowledge. Accordingly, one’s inquiry should begin from sensible objects and gradually progress toward entities that are more abstract or remote from the human ken.[254] Al-Fârâbï himself stresses the didactic quality of this type of method in Hurüf, when he writes that

these aspects of similarity [shabah] have a certain utility when the stu­dent is taught an art due to the speed with which he grasps these notions [ma‘am] when their explanation is made with words that resemble those that express notions known by him before receiving this art.[255]

Hence, whether it is analysis in geometry or transference in cosmology, al-Fârâbï displays a highly sensitive awareness toward the didactic potential of these techniques.

The foregoing analysis enables us to understand why al-Fârâbï relies so ostensibly on analogical language and transfer to describe the celes­tial bodies in his emanationist treatises, and why he also relies on these techniques in his description of Aristotelian philosophy.[256] The con­cepts of asma’ manqülah and naqlah are central to al-Fârâbï’s percep­tion of how philosophy is formed, since he regards the process of transfer as one of the essential corollaries of the empirical development of the sciences. His remarks on transfer and analogy should therefore be read in conjunction with his account of the development of philoso­phy and logic in Fï zuhür al-falsafah and Hurüf.24 If we recall that Ára and Siyasah may have been transmitted orally by the Second Teacher or written expressly for didactic purposes, then the role of analogy in these works acquires additional significance. Analogy, especially the method of transference discussed above, possesses undeniable didactic qualities according to al-Fârâbï, for it begins with things closest to human experience, i.e., the bodies apprehended by sense perception, and gradually leads the student to an understanding of the entities remote from the senses.

In this regard, one can establish a link between al-Fârâbï’s emphasis on observation and experience, his conception of the empirical evolu­tion of language, and the value he places on analogical methods such as transference, which take physical reality as a starting point. All of these features testify to a remarkable ‘empirical’ concern in al-Fârâbï’s episte­mology and approach to philosophy, and they also show how conscien­tiously al-Fârâbï followed Aristotle’s directive in Physics 1.1.184a.16-17 to “start from the things more knowable and obvious to us and proceed towards those which are clearer and more knowable by nature.”[257] [258] On the other hand, if al-Fârâbï operated within a fundamentally Aristotelian framework, he departed from this philosophical model by developing concepts that are either briefly mentioned or ignored by the Stagirite.

One question that remains to be answered is whether analogy is able to produce new knowledge or simply represents a didactic method for teaching things that have been ascertained through other types of dis­courses or through demonstration. Al-Fârâbï’s inclusion of transfer­ence in K. al-qiyas and the possibility of shaping analogical reasoning into syllogistic form do not prove analogy’s capacity to produce true knowledge. Rhetorical arguments, for instance, can be turned into syl­logisms whose conclusions are untrue. Although the extensive use al-Fârâbï makes of analogy in his metaphysics and cosmology suggests that it may be conducive to knowledge in its own right, additional com­ments are required to elucidate this point.

One angle from which to address this problem is to compare trans­ference to other modes of analogical reasoning used by al-Fârâbï. Al-Fârâbï uses a whole gamut of analogical techniques, many of which hinge on the notion of imitation. It is already known that this concept of imitation (muhakat) occupies a central place in al-Fârâbï’s political theories. Unlike transference, however, imitation relies primarily on the imagination and is merely a translation into symbols and images of concepts whose real nature may remain unknown to those who use it. This is attested by al-Fârâbï in Falsafat Aristii ta lis when he writes that

image-making and imitation [muhakat] by means of similitudes [mithalat] is one way to instruct the multitude and the vulgar in a large number of difficult theoretical things so as to produce in their souls the impressions of these things by way of their similitudes. The vulgar need not conceive and comprehend these things as they are. It is enough if they com­prehend and intellect them by means of what corresponds to them.[259]

In a similar vein, Ara states that

the faculty of representation [or imagination, al-quwwah al-mutakhayyi- lah] ... also imitates [tuhaki] the rational faculty by imitating those intel­ligibles which are present in it with things suitable for imitating them. It thus imitates the intelligibles of utmost perfection, like the First Cause, the immaterial things and the heavens.[260]

In these passages, the connection between imagination and imitation is stressed, as is the main purpose of imitation, which is to produce like­nesses of higher cosmological and metaphysical entities. Al-Fârâbï believes that imitation and imagination are characteristic of the poetic art, since it is the very essence of poetry to express concepts through symbols, images, and mimetic language in general.[261]

These various points contrast markedly with the analogical tech­nique of transference described by al-Fârâbï in his logical treatises. Whereas imitation merely represents or symbolizes a higher order of being, transference is a logical mode of reasoning that has its starting point in the investigation of the physical world. Whereas imitation rests on imagination, transfer involves an act or judgment of the intellect. Finally, while imitation is associated chiefly with the poetic art and plays a key role in al-Fârâbï’s prophetology and political theo­ries, transfer is a technique described in logic and implemented in physics and metaphysics. This indicates that al-Fârâbï’s cosmological method does not rely on imitation (muh akat), which is the product of the imaginative faculty (takhayyul) in humans, but rather on analogical transference (naqlah), which is a logical tool that builds on empirical knowledge and experience and involves an operation of the intellect.

To conclude, it appears that al-Fârâbï considered some forms of analogy, in addition to experience and observation, as important phil­osophical tools liable to produce new knowledge. These techniques should consequently be carefully distinguished from the mimetic kind of analogy and the theory of imitation described by al-Fârâbï in a polit­ical context.[262] Al-Fârâbï’s theorization of transfer is rooted in the Aristotelian tradition, but it is elaborated and finds a new use in his works. At the same time, however, one may hypothesize that al-Fârâbï’s emphasis on techniques such as transference is symptomatic of a cer­tain skeptical outlook toward the possibility of obtaining direct and unmediated knowledge of cosmological and metaphysical things. In other words, it is perhaps because al-Fârâbï was aware of the difficulty of reaching this kind of knowledge that he emphasized the didactic potential of techniques such as experience and transference.

4. Conclusion

The previous analysis has identified and discussed some of the main features of al-Fârâbï’s epistemology and approach to the study of cos­mology. While dependent on various Greek and Arabic philosophical and astronomical sources, he did not hesitate to develop his own method and to depart from his models on many key points. I argued that al-Fârâbï’s method is characterized primarily by the notions of the interrelatedness and cooperation of the sciences. In al-Fârâbï’s view, there is no opposition or interference between the various philosophi­cal disciplines involved in the study of the cosmos. Astronomy, physics, and metaphysics are all meant to operate in harmony and toward a common goal, namely, knowledge of the heavenly world. This coopera­tion of the sciences leads to a synthetic cosmological picture, in which the mathematical, physical, and metaphysical methods are integrated in a single overarching endeavour.

Al-Fârâbï’s scheme of the sciences is nevertheless hierarchical and subordinates some disciplines to others: astronomy relies on physics and geometry for some of its principles, while metaphysics qua univer­sal science also provides some of the foundational principles used in physics and astronomy. On the other hand, physics and metaphysics can benefit from the results of astronomy, a science which occupies a central place in the study of the cosmos. Hence, al-Fârâbï’s interdisci­plinary method in cosmology is also shaped by his belief in the subor­dination of the sciences, that is, the idea that they are hierarchically organized and dependent on one another, while at the same time col­laborating toward a common end. This position, which partly stems from some of Aristotle’s comments in Posterior Analytics, was broadly adopted by the Peripatetic circle that flourished in tenth-century Baghdad, as well as by al-Fârâbï.[263] Unlike al-Kindl’s methodology, which stresses the “epistemic gap” between sensation and intellect, and thus between physics and metaphysics, al-Fârâbï’s methodology shows “no radical disjunct between the sciences.”[264]

Another salient trait of al-Fârâbl’s epistemology is the emphasis on observation and experience, particularly with respect to his discussion of the astronomical method. In this regard, he departs significantly from the late antique Neoplatonists and was receptive to some of the important developments in scientific methodology that were crystal­lizing in the Islamic world, partly as a result of the intensive scrutiniz­ing of the heavens that was taking place in astronomical circles. In addition, the analysis underscored the place of analogy and espe­cially the technique of transfer in al-Fârâbï’s works, which takes its starting point in physical reality and proceeds upward to investigate the more remote or abstract entities. While it may have been triggered


COSMOLOGy, THE SCIENCES, AND THE SCIENTIFIC METHOD 113 by complex epistemological factors, this technique shows al-Fârâbï’s interest in the didactic aspect of cosmology and should be construed in parallel to his keen remarks on philosophical terminology and the development of language. With regard to all the points outlined above, al-Fârâbï’s approach to cosmology and his scientific method mark an important turn in early falsafah and also contributed to establishing an influential methodological framework that was used and refined by later thinkers such as Ibn Sïnâ and al-Tu sï.


CHAPTER TWO

THE ARCHITECTURE OF THE HEAVENS:
INTELLECTS, SOULS, AND ORBS

Al-Fârâbï’s cosmos is a complex one, which consists of various different levels of existents organized hierarchically according to the noble­ness of their substance. This chapter aims to deconstruct the various layers of his cosmology in order to explain the activity and relation of the various entities that constitute it, as well as to compare his model to the ancient cosmological trends and identify some of the sources that informed it. The following analysis is based primarily on the emana- tionist works, Ára and Siyasah, which provide the clearest picture of the Second Teacher’s cosmology, although I will refer to other texts as well. The relationship between this cosmological model and the one articulated in Jam’ and Jawâbât will be addressed in detail in chapter 3.

1. The Celestial Bodies

1.1. Orbs, Spheres, Planets, and Stars

The celestial bodies represent one of the main classes of superlunary existents and consist of the orbs, planets, and stars that make up the visible heavens. Although al-Fârâbï uses the same Arabic expression to refer to all of these entities, namely, ajsam samüwiyyah, it should be noted that it appears in a wide variety of contexts and is therefore ambiguous. It can refer to the orbs alone, which are transparent and invisible to humans, to the orbs together with their planets, or to the planets or stars alone. For example, al-Fârâbï states in Árü’ that “the celestial bodies [al-ajsüm al-samüwiyyah] are nine altogether.”[265] The implication here is that the terms “celestial bodies” refer to the nine main orbs or systems together with the planets or stars they contain. In another instance, however, al-Fârâbï writes that the second main orb or system (the orb of the fixed stars) “is one body, which contains a number of bodies [the fixed stars] which have a common motion.”[266] In this passage, the term jism is used equivocally to refer to the orb of the fixed stars and to the fixed stars themselves. Hence, although the Second Teacher distinguishes conceptually between the orbs, planets, and stars, this distinction is not always reflected terminologically in his works, and the various kinds of celestial entities are often sub­sumed under the generic term jism samawï. But al-Fârâbï occasionally employs a more specific terminology: the term kawkab (pl. kawakib) refers exclusively to the planets, including the sun and the moon, as well as to the fixed stars, while falak (pl. aflak) and kurah (pl. kurat or ukar) designate the orbs.[267] Al-Fârâbï’s choice of terms (kawkab, falak, kurah, and jism samawï) overlaps with the terminology of Arabic astronomers and natural philosophers, thereby indicating that his cos­mology is grounded primarily in these two sciences.

Al-Fârâbï describes the celestial bodies as a particular genus of bod­ies, the highest in a group of six genera, the others being in a decreasing order of nobleness the “rational animals, non-rational animals, plants, minerals, and the four elements.”[268] The celestial bodies are thus distinct from the other genera, all of which reside in the lower world of genera­tion and corruption. Furthermore, each celestial body is the unique individual of its species.[269] It is notable that for al-Fârâbï each orb is a “spherical body” (jism kuri), despite the fact that it is imperceptible to the senses.[270] As bodies, the orbs and planets may be defined primarily by their corporeal qualities: they have shapes (ashkal), volumes (azam), and sizes or measures (maqddtr).[271] But since they represent a special class of bodies, al-Fârâbï believes that they have only the noblest corpo­real qualities (spherical shape, luminosity, and circular motion)[272] and possess only the “most excellent categories.”[273] In addition, he, like most Peripatetics, holds that the orbs and planets do not possess any of the qualities attached to sublunary bodies, such as coldness, heat, dryness and moisture. While it is clear that the heavens have the purest visible and kinematic qualities, al-Fârâbï does not specify what tactile quali­ties they possess, i.e., whether the orbs are solid or liquid, an important cosmological question in the Medieval Latin tradition.

The most conspicuous qualities of the heavenly bodies from the viewpoint of an observer situated on earth is, first, their luminosity, and second, their regular and harmonious circular motion. These phe­nomena highlight their noble nature and set them apart from other types of corporeal beings characterized by rectilinear motion. With regard to the former, the Second Teacher believes that the celestial bodies emit light, which is in turn responsible for generating heat in the sublunary world. It is this light and heat caused by the celestial bod­ies that enable the generation of plants and animals to take place. In one of his treatises on astrology, al-Fârâbï mentions two different views on the luminosity of the heavens that he attributes to the ancients (al-qudama). The first holds that the sun alone emits light. According to the second, all the fixed stars are luminous in themselves, while the other wandering planets reflect the light of the sun. In this text, al-Fârâbï seems hesitant as to which interpretation to follow and does not take sides.[274]

Ára provides additional information on this issue. Al-Fârâbï explains that only “some parts” (ajza) of the heavens produce light, namely, al-kawakib, while other parts—presumably the orbs—are transparent and both produce their own light and receive light from al-kawakib. This statement is ambiguous, to say the least. First, it seems to imply that the orbs (which are the only transparent celestial bodies) not only receive light, but also emit a light of their own. This is a rather strange idea, since this light is not perceptible from a human viewpoint on earth. Second, it is unclear whether the term al-kawakib here refers to the fixed stars or the planets (or both). This passage is thus of little help, but it would seem that, according to al-Fârâbï, both the orbs and plan­ets or stars emit their own light.

Turning to the other main visible quality of the heavenly bodies, al-Fârâbï holds that the celestial orbs perform eternal and harmonious rotations around the earth.[275] This eternal circular motion is the result of their uninterrupted contemplation of the higher principles, whose perfection they strive to attain. It reflects the desire of the heavenly bodies to acquire the last degree of perfection necessary to complete their substance. But since they are embedded in a material substrate, they can never attain this perfection, and can only express it through circular motion, the circle being the most perfect shape. Furthermore, heavenly motion fulfills an important role in al-Fârâbï’s physics. The various celestial motions act as accidental causes on the sublunary world and are responsible for governing the processes of generation and corruption. More specifically, through their various movements, the orbs prepare sublunary matter for the reception of form and par­ticipate in the mixture of the elements that constitute the hylomorphic bodies. Finally, it should be noted that al-Fârâbï rejects the claim of the Pythagoreans that the orbs produce a celestial harmony as a result of their motions.[276]

Like all other bodies, the orbs, planets, and stars are composite sub­stances. However, unlike sublunary bodies, which are composed of form and matter, al-Fârâbï tells us that they are composed of the two principles of soul (nafs) and substrate (mawdu). Soul and substrate can be compared to sublunary form and matter, the soul acting like the form and the substrate acting like the matter, but they are not strictly speaking hylomorphic beings in the sense that, say, a bed is composed of form (its shape) and matter (its wood). Al-Fârâbï’s comparison between soul-substrate and form-matter should thus be construed as a didactic aid to drive home the point that the celestial bodies are not perfectly simple substances and to clarify how the celestial souls relate to the celestial bodies. The duality of soul and substrate that character­izes the orbs and planets makes them the first composite beings and places them below the immaterial and intellectual beings in the onto­logical hierarchy. As al-Fârâbï writes,

the substances of the celestial bodies are divided, inasmuch as they are substances, into many things. They are in the first rank of the ranks of beings that are deficient, due to the fact that the thing by virtue of which they are actually substances [i.e., their soul] requires a certain subject. Thus, they resemble the substances that are composed of matter and form.[277]

It is noteworthy that in stressing the compositeness of the celestial bodies, al-Fârâbï departs from Aristotle and many of his followers, who had emphasized the simple nature of the orbs and defined aether as a perfectly homogeneous substance pervading the entire heavens. Al-Fârâbï, in contrast, stresses the composite nature of the heavens and omits any reference to a simple celestial matter.

1.2. Al-Fârâbï and Ptolemy on the Planetary Models

Al-Fârâbï’s descriptions of the spatial arrangement of the celestial bod­ies are very brief and tantalizing, and there are many points he leaves unsettled. We depend primarily on one section of Ara to solve these issues. Nevertheless, by gathering the various hints dealing with this subject throughout his corpus, it is possible to reconstruct an adequate picture of the cosmos as he conceived it. At a basic level, al-Fârâbï fully endorsed the geocentric cosmological model that was prevalent in antiquity, which posits an immobile earth lying at the center of the uni­verse and various celestial orbs arranged in concentric layers around it. This scheme was outlined both in Aristotle’s physical works and in the Greek astronomical texts transmitted to the Arabic world, which, it should be noted, often drew on Aristotelian physical principles.

However, when it comes to the arrangement of the orbs and planets, it is Ptolemy’s works that were the main source of inspiration for the Second Teacher. According to al-Fârâbï, the heavens are divided into what he calls “groups” (sing. jumlah, pl. jumal),[278] a term which, to my knowledge, does not have an astronomical or philosophical pedigree. Al-Fârâbï establishes a hierarchy among the various cosmic groups, and the orbs are organized in ranks (maratib) in a descending order of excellence.[279] There are in total nine jumal, which correspond to the nine main celestial orbs inherited from Ptolemaic astronomy. The far­thest, outermost orb, also called ‘the first heaven’ (al-sama l-üla) and ‘the first body’ (al-jism al-awwal), is a starless and planetless orb, which is nobler in rank than the other orbs, due to its essential proximity to the first separate intellect. This first orb surrounds all the other orbs and causes the daily rotation of the heavens from east to west.[280] Below it is ‘the orb of the fixed stars’ (kurat al-kawakib al-thabitah), which is characterized by its dual motion—one being the motion of the outer­most orb, the other a retrograde motion from west to east called precession—and by the fact that the stars are ‘fixed’ in their orb and hence do not change position vis-à-vis one another. Next are the orbs of the seven planets, whose descending order according to al-Fârâbï is as follows: Saturn, Jupiter, Mars, the sun, Venus, Mercury, and the moon. The orb of the moon is thus the last orb, which is closest to the earth, and whose concave surface marks the separation between

the sublunary world and the heavens proper. Below the orb of the moon, one finds the various regions of the elements in their pure form, starting with fire, then air, water, and earth. This order was the one recommended by Ptolemy, and it was subsequently adopted by most Arabic astronomers.[281] In brief, seven of the nine orbs contain a planet (including the sun and the moon), one the stars, and one is starless and planetless (see Figure 3).

 

Figure 3. The main orbs and the arrangement of the planets

When taken as a whole, these various orbs and what they contain form the physical and corporeal world, outside of which nothing exists, not even void. This raises the question of the place (makan) of the heavens, an issue about which al-Fârâbï is silent in his extant works. Nevertheless, al-Fârâbï’s view on this old cosmological problem can be partly reconstructed from some disparate comments in the works of Ibn Bâjjah and Ibn Rushd. When discussing physical problems, these two authors often refer to the works of the Second Teacher, especially his commentary on Physics and his treatise On Changing Beings. Apparently, al-Fârâbï believed that the heavens possess an essential place defined by the relation of the two bodies that are the heavens and the earth. More specifically, the position of the heavens is determined by the convex surface of the body around which they rotate and which they surround, i.e., the earth and the regions of the elements.[282]

Another issue that is difficult to settle due to the sparse evidence concerns the spatial relation of the orbs and whether these are in contact or not. This problem was to become a controversial issue in Medieval Latin cosmology, but it does not seem to have interested early Arabic philosophers much. With regard to al-Fârâbï, the only hint appears in Falsafat Arista ta lis, where he explains (on behalf of Aristotle) that the orb of fire has “one of its two surfaces contiguous to the con­cave of the celestial bodies [i.e., to the surface of the orb of the moon] [yujawiru ahad sathayhi muqa’ar al-ajsam al-samawiyyah][283] The cos­mos is therefore a plenum consisting of contiguous orbs, which does not allow for the existence of void or gaps between the various bodies that occupy it. Although al-Fârâbï is merely reporting the opinion of Aristotle, it is likely that he would have adhered to this view as well.

Yet another ambiguous point is whether the nine celestial “groups” (jumal) mentioned by al-Fârâbï each consist of one or several orbs, that is, whether they consist only of a planet-bearing orb or of a planet­bearing orb together with other secondary or subordinate orbs respon­sible for the planet’s motion.[284] This issue, which is of crucial importance to understand al-Fârâbï’s theories of celestial motion and to define his place in the history of medieval cosmology, is closely related to the question of whether his cosmological model is homocentric, like Aristotle’s, or includes the Ptolemaic theories of the eccentric and epi­cycle. One should not assume that al-Fârâbï automatically adopted these theories as a result of his acquaintance with the Ptolemaic works. The number of post-Ptolemaic thinkers who either neglected or openly rejected the Ptolemaic planetary models is by no means insignificant and includes Alexander of Aphrodisias, Themistius, and Proclus in the Greek tradition, as well as Ibn Rushd, al-Bitrûjï, and several other Arabic thinkers of al-Andalus in Islam. The evidence for al-Fârâbï’s adherence to the Ptolemaic planetary models must therefore be dis­cussed and established and should not be taken for granted. One should also address the corollary question of whether al-Fârâbï defined the spheres in a purely geometrical way or as concrete entities embedded in the physical cosmos.

It is frequently alleged in the secondary literature that al-Fârâbï’s cosmos consists of only nine celestial orbs.[285] Indeed, in his account of the superlunary beings in Ára, he refers only to the nine orbs that are caused to exist by the separate intellects. But in this passage, it is likely that al-Fârâbï is exposing a simplified cosmological model for the sake of clarity. There are many hints suggesting that he endorsed a more complex system that included smaller, subordinate orbs and spheres. To begin with, we know that al-Fârâbï wrote a commentary on Almagest, which must have discussed at length the function of these models in planetary motion. Although some Arabic authors criticized Ptolemy, especially from Ibn al-Haytham’s time onward, it is unlikely that al-Fârâbï’s commentary would have amounted to a wholesale rejection of the Ptolemaic system, and it is much more plausible that he endorsed its main features. Considering that al-Kindï before him and Ibn Sïnâ after him followed Ptolemy’s astronomy, it would be all the more sur­prising if al-Fârâbï had rejected it.

With respect to the textual evidence supporting this hypothesis, al-Fârâbï writes in Árü’ that “the third group to the ninth group [i.e., the main planetary orbs, including those of the sun and the moon] each contain bodies [ajsam] whose motions are several and different.”[286] The plural noun ajsam in this sentence must refer to subordinate orbs and spheres—presumably the eccentrics and epicycles—in addition to the planets, since the main orbs only contain one planet, the sun, or the moon, and therefore the reference to several bodies (ajsam) and several motions would not be justified if al-Fârâbï was referring to the planet alone.

This interpretation of the Ára excerpt is strengthened by other pas­sages in the Fârâbïan corpus, although it must be said that these are sparse and often obscure. In Müstqâ, the Second Teacher explicitly refers to the Ptolemaic theories of eccentrics and epicycles in the course of an argument designed to show that the astronomer must rely on physical principles in order to explain the causes of the planets’ motions. Al-Fârâbï states that the astronomer “can only explain these causes, such as the eccentrics and epicycles, if he posits that these planetary motions are in themselves regular.”[287] This passage shows beyond doubt that al-Fârâbï was aware of the existence of these astronomical devices. Accordingly, and returning to Árü’, al-Fârâbï describes one kind of celestial body as “a sphere or a corporeal circle” (kurah aw dairah mujassamah).[288] Shortly thereafter, he again mentions other “corporeal circles” apart from the main orb: “Each of the spheres and the corpo­real circles [dawair mujassamah] in them has an independent motion of its own.”[289] There is little doubt that the formula dawair mujassamah refers to the eccentrics and epicycles contained in the main orbs and which are responsible for the particular motions of each planet. Dairah is the Arabic counterpart of the Greek kùkàoç, which in general does not convey a sense of corporeality. But by specifying that these are “corporeal” (mujassamah) circles, and by locating them “within” the main orbs (flha), al-Fârâbï clearly defends, first, the existence of the eccentrics and epicycles in addition to the main orbs, and second, the physical nature of these planetary devices.[290]

Finally, and to lend additional weight to this view, in the same sec­tion of Ara al-Fârâbï discusses the shifting positions of the celestial bodies, mentioning the fact that they “sometimes come together [tajtamtu] and sometimes separate [taftariqu] ... sometimes come near [taqrubu] some bodies on the lower level and sometimes recede [tabudu] from them.”[291] These comments are echoed in Siyasah, where the celestial bodies are said to alternate between opposition and con­junction and to have varying distances vis-à-vis the earth.[292] It is clear that these remarks cannot apply to a system of homocentric orbs, in which the relation between the planets and stars and the earth remains virtually the same. It is much more likely that they refer instead to a Ptolemaic model whereby the planets conjoin and separate as a result of the motion of the epicycles and eccentrics which carry them along. Indeed, the eccentrics and epicycles could account much more effec­tively than the concentric orbs for the varying motions and distances of the stars and planets that could be perceived from earth. This helps to understand why they gradually became the favoured models of astron­omers and why the concentric system lost its popularity.

Apart from these brief comments, al-Fârâbï says little about the organization of the orbs, and he does not elaborate detailed planetary models using epicycles and eccentrics in his philosophical works.[293] In spite of this, the evidence adduced above, combined with the fact that al-Fârâbï commented on Almagest, is sufficient to conclude that his cosmology relied on the theories of the epicycles and eccentrics and is therefore closer to Ptolemy’s astronomical model as depicted in Almagest and Planetary Hypotheses than to Aristotle’s homocentric system.[294] In adopting the Ptolemaic planetary devices, al-Farabi fol­lows the example of his illustrious predecessor al-Kindi, who often mentions the eccentrics and epicycles in his treatises, as in On the Proximate Efficient Cause.[295]

One point deserves further comment. The evidence discussed above indicates that al-Farabi regarded the eccentrics and epicycles as physical entities embedded within the main orbs of each system. According to al-Farabi, all the celestial orbs, including the subordinate orbs and spheres, are spherical bodies (sing. jism kuri)[296] This explains why he states in Ára that there are several bodies (ajsam) within each main orb and that these bodies have several different motions, since he is referring in this instance not only to the planets, but also to the eccentrics and epicycles necessary to explain these planets’ particular motions. In turn, we may conclude that the term “group” (jumlah), which al-Farabi uses to describe the main spherical layers of the cos­mos, refers to the entire planetary system, i.e., the planet, the main orb, and the smaller subordinate orbs and spheres it contains, all of which possess a corporeal existence.[297]

These results are significant insofar as they shed light on al-Farabi’s position vis-à-vis the much debated problem of the conceptual versus extramental existence of the planetary devices. Indeed, the relation between the mathematical models posited by astronomy and the physical proposition of the materiality of the orbs represents a con­troversial issue both for ancient and modern scholars.[298] In the case of al-Fârâbï, in conceiving the eccentrics and epicycles as solid, corpo­real entities, he definitively sides with the realist camp, and he openly acknowledges that the mathematical planetary models he inherited from Ptolemy are representations of bodies that exist objectively in the heavens. This in turn explains why there is a visible attempt in al-Fârâbï’s works to integrate astronomical elements in a physical and metaphysical framework, as can be seen clearly in Ára, for instance. It should be noted that in upholding this view, al-Fârâbï agrees not only with most other falasifah, such as Ibn Sïnâ and al-Tusï, but also with many ancient Greek thinkers and with Ptolemy himself in Planetary Hypotheses.[299]

To summarize, then, al-Fârâbï endorsed various key features of Ptolemaic astronomy: the arrangement of the planets as advocated by Ptolemy; the existence of a ninth, starless orb responsible for the diurnal motion of all the orbs; and the planetary devices of the eccen­trics and epicycles, here interpreted as concrete entities. This suggests that al-Fârâbï deliberately embraced a harmonizing approach to phys­ics and astronomy and that he desired to some extent to reconcile his philosophical ideas with the most up-to-date astronomical knowl­edge. Like Aristotle, who had drawn on the astronomical theories of Eudoxus and Callipus, and Ibn Sïnâ, who was himself a practicing astronomer and devoted part of his Shifa to commenting on Almagest,[300] al-Fârâbï was genuinely interested in astronomy and assimilated its findings to other aspects of his philosophy. In this respect, it is not surprising that the Second Teacher chose Ptolemy’s Almagest as a model. While al-Fârâbï considered Aristotle’s corpus to be the pinna­cle of philosophy, there is no doubt that he and the falasifah in general regarded Ptolemy as the main authority in astronomical matters. It would therefore have seemed natural to al-Fârâbï to discard the out­dated astronomical model elaborated by the Stagirite and to favour the more recent astronomical theories and findings of his contempo­raries, who were elaborating on the Ptolemaic legacy. Finally, it is noteworthy that al-Fârâbï’s strategy to harmonize astronomy, physics, and metaphysics is apparent both in his scientific method, as was shown in the previous chapter, as well as in the general structure of his cosmology.

1.3. The Celestial Souls

The celestial bodies are by no means the only existents of the heavens. Above them in rank and nobleness are various other principles that will be discussed in the rest of this chapter. One of the remarkable fea­tures of al-Farabi’s cosmology is the consistent distinction that is made between two sets of celestial intellects: the rational souls that inhere in the celestial bodies on the one hand, and the separate intellects on the other. The present concern is with the former. Al-Farabi does not use a specific technical term to refer to these souls and simply calls them anfus al-ajsam al-samawiyyah (“the souls of the heavenly bodies”). Although the ensoulment of the heavens represents a ubiquitous and quasi-universal religious and mythological tenet, this doctrine had a long and variegated history in Ancient Greek philosophy. Suffice it to say here that Plato (or rather the characters of his dialogues) discusses the ensoulment of the heavens in several of his works, such as Timaeus (36E-39A) and Laws (896B-897C and 967D-E), a view reproduced by the author of the Epinomis (981E, 983A-C). The evidence in Aristotle is somewhat more ambiguous, but several passages in his works seem to defend a similar view.[301] At any rate, the later commentators took it for granted that Aristotle upheld the ensoulment of the heavens.[302] This doctrine was then conveyed to the Islamic milieu by some philosophi­cal texts translated into Arabic, such as Theology of Aristotle and the treatise Mabadi attributed to Alexander. Al-Kindi’s works also attest that this theory was endorsed by some thinkers during the early centu­ries of Islam.[303]

Al-Farabi describes the celestial soul as a principle that constitutes part of the substance of the celestial body, the other being substrate (mawdü ‘). Unlike the separate intellects, which are immaterial, the celestial souls do not exist separately from the orbs, but rather as part of them. They are compared to forms (su war), with the implication that they inhere in the celestial substrate in the way that sublunary forms inhere in matter. The identification of soul with form has a long history in ancient Greek thought, which begins with Aristotle’s asser­tion in On the Soul 2.1 that “the soul must be a substance in the sense of the form of a natural body having life potentially within it.”[304] Most of the Peripatetic and Neoplatonic philosophers who flourished after the Stagirite accepted this equation, while striving at the same time to address some of the problems it raised and to integrate the concept of soul in a new cosmological framework.[305]

Al-Fârâbï was obviously aware of the main propositions of On the Soul, such as the one cited above, and of Aristotle’s definition of the human soul as form.[306] But the origin of al-Fârâbï’s comparison between the celestial soul and form should probably be sought elsewhere, since Aristotle himself does not to my knowledge make this connection in a cosmological context. Indeed, On the Soul and its commentaries are primarily interested in the human soul and intellect. For this reason, the description of celestial souls as forms most likely represents a later cosmological development triggered by the commentatorial tradition. As C. Genequand has shown, it is most likely in Alexander’s Mabadi that al-Fârâbï found a precedent for this view, which is repeated on numerous occasions in this work.[307]

In spite of their proximity to the heavenly bodies, al-Fârâbï conceives of the celestial souls essentially as intellects. In his human psychology, al-Fârâbï makes an ontological and epistemological distinction between soul (nafs) and intellect (‘aql). When it comes to the celestial bodies, however, both concepts overlap and are used synonymously: the orbs have rational souls that contemplate intelligibles, and this activity makes them intellects. This appears clearly in Ára and Siyasah, where al-Fârâbï explains that the heavenly substrates “do not prevent their forms [i.e., the celestial souls] from thinking and from being intellects [uqülan] in their essences”;[308] that “despite the fact that the soul that is in each of them [the celestial bodies] is something existing in a sub­strate, it is ... an actual intellect.”;[309] and that “the celestial souls have neither sensory perception nor imagination; rather, they have only the soul that intellects.”[310]

Al-Fârâbï repeatedly mentions the fact that the celestial bodies “intellect” or “contemplate” (aqala) the higher principles.[311] In spite of their intellectual nature, however, the celestial souls are more complex than the separate intellects, due to their varied objects of thought. Moreover, they inhere in a substrate (mawdü ‘), to which they are closely connected and which makes the substance of the celestial bodies com­posite. These defects affect the nature of the celestial souls and prevent them from being pure intellects. This is why one reads in Ithbat that the heavenly bodies do not possess a “pure intellect” (‘aql si rf).[312]

Unlike al-Kindi, his philosophical predecessor, al-Farabi does not endow the heavenly bodies with the senses of sight and hearing. The usual argument for justifying sensation at the celestial level, and the one that appears in al-Kindi’s works, is that if the celestial bodies are the best and noblest of bodies, they must possess the most excellent senses (sight and hearing), or else the perishable animals of the sublu­nary world could be said to be nobler on this ground.[313] Although al-Farabi does not explain why he rejects this argument and the theory of celestial sensation, he might have found it superfluous to ascribe sensation to the celestial bodies in addition to intellection. Alternatively, one may explain the discrepancy in the two thinkers’ cosmologies by arguing that al-Kindi and al-Farabi might have consulted different sources and thus reached different conclusions on this topic. However, we know that both had access to a common Aristotelian and Neoplatonic body of works that occasionally ascribed sensation to the heavenly bodies. Al-Farabi would surely have come across this doctrine in some of the texts issuing from this corpus, such as Theology of Aristotle.[314] Rather, it seems more likely that he rejected celestial sensation as a result of the emphasis he places on the intellectual and rational nature of the orbs, through which he addresses more fundamental cosmologi­cal issues such as substance, existence, and motion. For al-Farabi, the special kind of intellection the celestial souls possess is the key differ­ence that sets them apart from other living beings.

Another salient feature of al-Farabi’s description of the celestial souls is his rejection of imagination (takhayyul) or the imaginative faculty (al-quwwah al-mutakhayyilah). Unlike al-Kindi and Ibn Sina, al-Farabi limits the activity of the celestial souls to intellection alone and deprives them of the imaginative faculty. But in this case as well, he does not adduce arguments to defend his position. This is all the more surpris­ing, when one realizes the important role that imagination plays in al-Fârâbï’s political and psychological theories. One reason could lie in his belief that imagination replaces reason in the non-rational ani­mals.[315] Since the planets are rational beings, they do not need imagina­tion to reach their state of perfection.

In brief, the celestial souls possess the rational faculty only and have neither sensation nor imagination, which are confined to the sublu­nary animals. But what al-Fârâbï has to say concerning the rationality of the celestial souls is relatively limited. Indeed, he says virtually noth­ing about will (iradah), choice (ikhtiyar), and desire (shawq, tashaw- wuq), concepts that are often associated with the rational activity of the orbs, and which furthermore played a key role in medieval Arabic accounts of heavenly motion inspired by Aristotelian cosmology. According to this theory, the celestial souls seek the perfections of the immaterial movers out of will and desire, and as a result produce the circular motion of the heavens. Al-Kindï, al-Sijistânï, and later on Ibn Sïnâ, for instance, endow the celestial bodies with will (iradah) and make it a cornerstone of their cosmology.[316] This concept was also adopted by al-Bitr üjï and Ibn Rushd in the Western Islamic lands and seems to have been prevalent in the Arabic Peripatetic tradition. It is therefore surprising to realize that al-Fârâbï omits to mention it in his works.[317] A possible explanation is that he considered will proper to the human soul and unnecessary to explicate heavenly motion.[318] One may nonetheless assume that the celestial bodies possess will by virtue of their very rationality. Since they have reason, they must possess choice (ikhtiyar) and will (iradah) as well. This point should be borne in mind when analyzing the Second Teacher’s theory of celestial motion, which will be taken up in chapter 4.

The foregoing comments underscore al-Fârâbï’s belief in the exclu­sively intellectual nature of the celestial souls: they possess rational thought alone and are deprived of sensation and imagination. It is, however, regrettable that he does not provide more detailed informa­tion about these celestial souls and that he leaves several questions unanswered. Are both the orbs and planets ensouled or are the planets or orbs alone ensouled? How many souls does each planetary system or group possess? Although al-Fârâbï does not address these issues in any depth in his extant works, it may be argued on the basis of certain pas­sages that he held both the orbs and planets to be ensouled. First, this may be inferred from the fact that the outermost orb, in spite of being starless and planetless, is placed in the same category of ensouled celes­tial bodies as the planetary orbs.[319] Second, since all the heavenly bodies have a form that inheres in a substrate, and since al-Fârâbï equates their form with their soul, it would seem that all of them must therefore have a soul. Yet the issue of the ensoulment of the orbs and planets creates certain tensions when it is connected with al-Fârâbï’s views on celestial kinematics, as will be shown in chapter 4.

1.3.1.    Celestial Soul and Nature

Al-Fârâbï’s views on the celestial soul and its co-existence with the celestial body also raise the question of how these principles relate to the concept of nature, an important and much debated question in late antique cosmology. Two issues worth investigating in this connection are what kind of nature (tabt ah) the heavens possess and how this celestial nature fits in the broader concept of nature in al-Fârâbï’s phi­losophy. The Second Teacher was aware of the fact that Aristotle had reflected on this cosmological question, as he writes that the Stagirite “had to investigate also whether the substances of the heavenly bodies consist of a nature [tabtah] or a soul or an intellect.”[320] The Peripatetic tradition that developed subsequent to Aristotle weaved a rich and diverse body of answers to the question of heavenly nature, thus pro­ducing its own elaborations and accretions on the Stagirite’s ideas.[321] Some of the interpretive strategies adopted in the late antique com- mentatorial tradition included equating nature with the celestial souls or, conversely, with the special material constitution of the heavens. Since Aristotle had defined nature as an internal source of motion in a body,[322] the challenge was to explain whether this source was psycho­logical or merely material and how this definition could be meaning­fully applied to the celestial entities, which appeared to be different from other bodies in many respects, including their circular motion.

In addition, it was unclear how this natural celestial motion could simultaneously be caused by other, non-physical principles such as the unmoved movers. As a result of the apparent contradictions in the Aristotelian corpus on this issue,[323] and depending on the exegete, the concept of celestial nature was interpreted in connection with the spe­cial celestial element (aether or a refined kind of fire), the celestial soul, or an inclination in the celestial bodies. An example of this kind of exegetical enterprise can be found in Simplicius’ commentary on Physics, which defines celestial nature in light of the special material constitution of the orbs and their inclination for celestial motion. At the same time, he clearly distinguishes nature from soul and criticizes Alexander for conflating the two concepts.[324]

It is against this exegetical background that al-Fârâbï’s views on the celestial nature should be examined. He follows Aristotle closely in his general definition of nature, particularly Physics 2.1 and Metaphysics 5.4. Like Aristotle, he holds the view that “the term nature applies to both matter and form,” although “form is more appropriately called by this name.”[325] In Falsafat Aristü ta lis, he explains that nature refers primarily to the essence of a composite being, thus reformulating Metaphysics 5.4.1014b35-37.[326] In addition, al-Fârâbï also refers to the Aristotelian definition of nature as a “principle of motion and rest.”[327] Finally, natural bodies are described in Ihsa ’ as bodies produced nei­ther by art nor human volition and thus in a sense primary. “The simple natural bodies,” al-Fârâbï writes “are those the existence of which does not result from bodies other than themselves,”[328] and he specifically mentions the heavens (sama') as an example of a natural body.[329] If we follow al-Fârâbï on this question, then bodies can be said to be ‘natural’ in several ways: a) because they are endowed with a prin­ciple of motion and rest; b) because they have form; c) because they have matter; d) because they are compound substances made of form and matter; e) because they are primary entities not produced by arti­ficial or artistic means. All of these definitions apply somewhat to the celestial bodies. Indeed, al-Fârâbï regards them as composite (they are made of substrate and soul-form), they are endowed with a principle of motion (albeit not of rest), and they are not artificial, in the sense that they are not produced by art or human volition. By their very virtue of being bodies (ajsam), they necessarily form part of the realm of nature or what al-Fârâbï calls “the world” (al-‘alam).[330] Broadly speaking, then, al-Fârâbï defines the realm of nature as encompassing both the sublu­nary world and the physical heavens.

Although the above taxonomy is useful to understand in what sense the heavens are ‘a part of nature,’ it sheds little light on the possible existence of a special heavenly nature. This difficulty is further com­pounded by the fact that al-Fârâbï mentions the term ‘nature’ only a few times in a heavenly context: once in Siyasah, where he explains that it is in the nature (tabtah) of the celestial bodies to act on the sublunary world; and twice in Ára in connection with celestial motion, where al-Fârâbï explains that the heavenly bodies move “by nature” (bi-tabtatiha) and through a “common nature” (tabïah mush- tarakah).[331] These statements can be globally interpreted in light of Physics 2.1.192b35 ff. as meaning that the heavens possess certain qualities, especially luminosity and circular motion,[332] “by nature” or “according to nature,” in the sense that these qualities do not come about through compulsion or are opposed to the celestial inclination and substance.

With respect to the first occurrence, however, it may be worthwhile comparing al-Fârâbï’s idea of a celestial nature acting on the sublunary world to Alexander’s cosmology. Alexander not only conceived of the entire heaven as having a nature, but he also described the powers it produced and transmitted to the world of generation and corruption as an extension of the heavenly nature.[333] Al-Fârâbï, probably following Alexander, also presents the celestial bodies as transmitting powers to the sublunary world as a result of their special nature. In the passage of Siyasah mentioned above, he argues that the heavenly bodies possess powers (quwan) that act on the sublunary world, in a manner which recalls Alexander’s own theory of celestial powers, and he even makes the celestial nature responsible for the generation of prime matter: “The substance, nature [tabtah], and activity of the celestial body is such that there immediately follows from it the existence of prime matter.”[334] In that sense, al-Fârâbï follows Alexander in establishing a connection between the heavenly nature and power and the sublunary processes of generation and corruption.

But to which cosmological principle should this special celestial nature be connected? Alexander and al-Fârâbï both elevate the heav­enly bodies to a high status in their ontology, the former describ­ing them as “divine” (probably following Aristotle in Metaphysics 12.8.1074b ff. and On the Heavens 1.3.270b ff.), the latter connecting them with the causality of the separate intellects and equating each one of them with an angel.[335] These views in turn rest on the premise of the ensoulment of the heavens, which is fundamental in these two phi­losophers’ cosmologies. In the case of Alexander, the celestial ‘nature’ can be directly connected with the celestial soul, which is responsible for causing the motions that in turn produce the powers emanating on the world of generation and corruption. Indeed, we know from Simplicius’ account in On the Heavens and from his commentary on Physics[336] that Alexander equated the celestial soul with the celestial nature. In Mabâdï, it is stated explicitly that “the nature of these things [i.e., the celestial bodies] is the soul.”[337] It is perhaps partly as a result of the influence of the Alexander arabus that al-Fârâbï chose to define the celestial substance primarily in light of the soul and its psychological faculties in his cosmological treatises, Ára and Siyasah. In these works, al-Fârâbï never equates celestial nature with matter—even a special kind of celestial matter—as Aristotle does in On the Heavens 1.2, but rather presents soul as the main principle of the celestial substance. Like Alexander, then, al-Fârâbï probably considered the celestial nature to be psychological and in fact reducible to soul. The dual ideas of the ensoulment of the heavens and of a heavenly nature that acts directly on the sublunary world appear side by side in their works. These paral­lels suggest a link between the two thinkers with regard to the concep­tualization of celestial soul and nature.[338]

1.3.2.    The Contemplation and Knowledge of the Celestial Souls

As mentioned previously, the celestial souls are characterized primarily by their rationality and abstract thinking. But their contemplation is by no means a perfectly simple act, since it is oriented toward various dif­ferent objects. According to al-Fârâbï, the souls of the heavenly bodies focus on three objects of thought, two of which are exterior to their essence. First and foremost, they reflect upon God as the ultimate prin­ciple of the universe and as the most perfect being. Second, each one of them contemplates the separate intellect responsible for its existence, which is its proximate efficient and final cause. Finally, each heavenly soul contemplates its own essence (dhâtahâ).[339]

This threefold mode of intellection introduces a notion of multiplic­ity (kathrah) in the heavenly souls and prevents them from being com­pletely simple substances. Al-Fârâbï, following Aristotle, equates thought and the object of thought in the divine essence.[340] In the case of the celestial bodies, however, the relation between the intellect and the intelligible is different for two reasons. First, because the heavenly bod­ies are not thinking one object, but three different objects simultane­ously. Second, because they contemplate objects that are exterior to and separate from their own essence, namely, the First Cause and the separate intellects.

Al-Fârâbï’s theory of the threefold intellection of the heavenly souls represents an interesting and idiosyncratic feature of his cosmology. It plays a key role in explaining not only the motion of the orbs and their impact on sublunary phenomena, but also the status of the heav­enly bodies as intermediate beings between the more perfect separate intellects and the sublunary world. But how did al-Fârâbï come up with this theory? In what follows I will argue that it represents an original elaboration on al-Fârâbï’s part, which was nevertheless inspired by his reading of the Proclus arabus texts.

To begin with, one finds in Proclus the idea that the souls and intel­lects are intimately connected, that is, that the celestial souls derive from the intellects, and thus that in a certain way these souls partici­pate in the nature of intellect. This view is articulated, for instance, in Propositions 174, 193, 207, and 208 of Elements. The parallel is further strengthened by the fact that in Elements some of these souls are meant to inhere in corporeal bodies, by which Proclus means the planets. As Proposition 196 states, “every participated soul makes use of a first body which is perpetual.”[341] Moreover, Proposition 201 of Elements explains that each soul is characterized by a “threefold activity” (rpinÀâç évepyeiaç), which reflects its intermediary status between the intelligible and corporeal worlds. This threefold activity of the souls is due to their godlike nature, to their intellectual nature, and to their having self-motion. Al-Fârâbï does not reproduce this exact scheme in his treatises, but it is likely that he derived the idea of the three-fold intellection of the celestial souls from an Arabic adaptation of this passage.

A likely vehicle of transmission for this last theory is Mahd al-khayr. In Proposition 3 of this work, the Arabic adaptor discusses the nature of soul and says: “Every noble soul possesses three actions [or opera­tions] [afail]: a spiritual or psychological [nafsânt] action, an intellec­tual [‘aqlt] action, and a divine [ilahi] action.”[342] The adaptor goes on to explain that these actions are made possible by powers [quwan] invested in the Soul by the First Cause and the Intellect. It is through these pow­ers that the Soul can act on the world of nature and acquire knowledge. At the end of this proposition, the author provides a similar statement about the threefold power in the soul: “soul has three actions [afafl] because it has three powers [quwan]: a divine power, an intellectual power, and an essential power [quwwah dhatiyyah] ”[343] [344] What is of inter­est in addition to quwwah—a key concept of classical falsafah, but which is to be understood in this case in the sense of ‘power,’ not ‘poten­tiality’ or ‘possibility’—is the idea that soul is divided into three aspects, one connected with the First Cause (ildht), one with Intellect (‘aqlt), and one with its own essence (nafsaniyyah or dhatiyyah). Mahd al- khayrs division of the soul into these three different aspects corre­sponds in al-Fârâbï’s cosmology to the souls’ three objects of thought: the First, the separate intellects, and their own essence. This passage shows such striking resemblance to al-Fârâbï’s theory that there can be little doubt that it represents its point of origin.

Due to their intellectual nature, the celestial souls are characterized first and foremost by their having knowledge (’ilm) and by being in a perpetual state of reflection. But is their knowledge restricted to the higher principles or does it include the particulars of the sublunary world as well? Put differently, can these souls know what lies beneath them, either as a result of knowing their own essence or in their capac­ity as causes of these things? And is their intellection discursive or non- discursive? Al-Fârâbï describes the celestial souls as being in a state of continuous intellectual activity or contemplation. They are “always contemplating what they contemplate,” and the “objects of their intel­lects are present in them from the very beginning.” This means that these souls are always in a state of actuality. This idea is emphasized when he writes that the heavenly souls are “never potential” (wa-dhalika annaha lam takun bi-l-quwwah aslan) and “always [or eternally] actual” (bal hiya bi-l-fil daiman)8 The intelligibles in them are continuously actualized and have been so “from the very start” (min awwal al-amr). This equation between intellection and actuality harkens back to Aristotle’s account of God as nous and pure actuality in Book Lambda 7 and 9, and it is clear that al-Fârâbï is following a well-established tra­dition. But what is notable here is that al-Fârâbï applies this principle to the heavenly souls, thereby underlining their intellectual nature in spite of their defects as substances.

Al-Fârâbï also compares the heavenly and human souls. Unlike the former, the latter “are at first in potentiality and then later in actual­ity.”[345] [346] [347] In the case of human intellection, which is discursive and moves from one object to another, it is clear that the intellect apprehends only one particular object at any given time, because it cannot think many objects simultaneously. However, the celestial souls in contrast con­template several objects simultaneously, and these objects, namely, God and the separate intellects, are themselves eternal and unchang­ing. Clearly, then, for al-Fârâbï, the intellection of the celestial souls is continuous, simultaneous, and non-discursive.

As for the question of the heavenly souls’ knowledge of particulars, it was occasionally broached in late antique works and is intricately linked to the theme of divine providence (indyah). A salient example of this type of cosmological discussion is the Arabic translation of Alexander’s De providentia, which examines the questions of celestial knowledge and providence at length. This trend continued in the early Arabic context, partly as a result of the influence of the Alexander ara­bus, as can be seen in the works of al-Kindl as well as those of early Arabic astrologers such as Abû Ma‘shar.82 Al-Fârâbï, in comparison, says little about this issue, but what he does say seems to exclude the possibility of the souls’ knowledge of particulars. Most of the relevant information can be found in a short section of SiyasahA There one reads that “the celestial souls definitely do not contemplate the major­ity of the intelligibles that humans contemplate from things in matter, because they are far too high in rank by virtue of their substance to contemplate the intelligibles that are below them.” This statement seems to limit the intelligibles of the celestial souls to eternal, immaterial principles, a view that agrees fully with al-Fârâbl’s belief that the souls are always in actuality “due to the fact that the objects of their intellect are present in them from the very beginning [min awwal al- amr]” Indeed, if the heavenly souls knew particulars, their thought would be discursive and constantly changing from one object to another. Alternatively, the heavenly bodies could know particulars in a universal way, but al-Fârâbï says nothing that could be used in support of this view.[348]

The previous comparison between the Proclus arabus and al-Fârâbï’s writings convincingly shows that the Second Teacher adapted Neopla­tonic theories on soul and intellect and reconciled them with other aspects of his cosmology. Regardless of the recension in which al-Fârâbï read the Proclus arabus, this corpus, especially Proposition 3 of Mahd al-khayr and the Arabic version of Proposition 201 of Elements, repre­sents one of the key sources underlying his theories of celestial psychology.

Before concluding this section, I wish to highlight certain tensions in al-Fârâbï’s account of the celestial souls. The first one is al-Fârâbï’s claim that the celestial souls are essentially intellects, since they have neither sense perception nor imagination, but only the rational faculty. But if this is the case, it becomes difficult to understand how they may be said to inhere in any kind of substrate, since what is intellectual is by definition immaterial and does not need a substrate to exist. Yet these soul-intellects are said to inhere in celestial substrates, which are even compared to the material substrates of sublunary beings. A second ten­sion concerns the celestial souls’ self-contemplation and their knowl­edge of “their own essence,” as al-Fârâbï puts it. Al-Fârâbï does not elaborate at all on this point, which leaves the reader quite perplexed about what exactly is meant by “their own essence.” Did he intend to refer only to the rational part of the celestial essence, in which case the self-reflexivity of the souls would focus on their very act of thinking? But this could lead to a circular argument, as their thinking about their own essence could be reducible to their thinking about the higher prin­ciples. Or did al-Fârâbï intend to say that the celestial souls think of themselves not only qua thinking subjects, but rather as composite and caused entities, a definition which would include their substrate as well, as is suggested in one passage of Arü’?[349] According to this inter­pretation, the celestial souls would apprehend their essence as being composite and causally derivative in a manner comparable to Ibn Sïnâ’s notion of the ‘possible of existence.’

Finally, there is the question of what distinguishes the soul’s contem­plation of the First and of the specific separate intellect that caused it to exist, since both objects are immaterial and intellectual and therefore cannot be individualized by resorting to the concept of matter. These tensions, which can definitely be seen as shortcomings in al-Fârâbï’s account, insofar as he does not explain them adequately, most likely arose out of his practice of adapting particular theories from Proclus arabus. While these theories acquired a new meaning and function in the context of his cosmology, they were at the same time fraught with theoretical difficulties, which had puzzled the Greek Neoplatonists for centuries, and which al-Fârâbï’s highly synthetic approach could not address in detail.

2. The Separate Intellects

2.1. The Origin of al-Fârâbï’s Ennadic Scheme

Distinct from and above the souls in the ontological hierarchy is a sec­ond class of intellects, which al-Fârâbï calls the “separate intellects” (al-‘uqül al-mufâriqah, or simply al-mufâriqah) to express the fact that, unlike the celestial souls, they do not inhere in any substrate and are immaterial beings. These separate intellects constitute a vertical line of existents that act as an intermediary between the First and the corpo­real world consisting of the heavens and the sublunary realm. They are ten in number and possess a common immaterial and intellectual nature. This means that they can be apprehended neither in relation to matter nor to time, which they transcend. Rather, their conceptual organization or hierarchy is defined in terms of essential priority and posteriority.[350] In spite of their identical intellectual nature, these entities may in turn be divided into two categories. Al-Fârâbï calls the first nine separate intellects al-thawant, while the last and tenth separate intellect is described as the Agent Intellect (al-aql al-fa“al).S7 In most cases, al-Fârâbï maintains a terminological and conceptual distinction between these intellects and discusses them in separate parts of his works. This distinction has not been sufficiently emphasized in the modern literature, and the general tendency has been to treat the thawant and the Agent Intellect as belonging to a single group of existents. Yet as we shall see, they present different characteristics and fulfill different functions.

The term thawant itself is interesting and deserves some attention. It may refer to the intermediate position that these intellects occupy between God and the corporeal world. They are, literally, the “second” in rank after God, called the First. But their name also refers to the fact that they are secondary causes of existence, since they produce the celestial bodies as a result of their own intellection. Ultimately, God is the primary agent and First Cause responsible for the causation of the entire world, and the thawant are the proximate efficient causes of the heavens. Finally, the term thawant may also refer to the twofold intel­lection and causation of the separate intellects (i.e., their contemplation of the First and of their own essence, which results in the causation of another intellect and an orb together with its soul). It is intriguing that the term al-thawant appears in Mahd al-khayr, the Arabic adaptation of Proclus’ Elements, where, as in al-Fârâbï’s works, it refers to celestial [351] intellects (‘uqül)8 This terminological parallel is not sufficient to prove that al-Fârâbï consulted this source, but the many other similarities existing between Mahd al-khayr and al-Fârâbï’s theories of celestial intellection support this hypothesis. In any case, these separate intel­lects form a distinct set of immaterial existents in the ontological chain that begins with the First and ends with prime matter, “the lowest of the possibly existing things.”[352] [353] Finally, it should be noted that in his extant works, al-Fârâbï, unlike Ibn Sïnâ, does not offer any proof concerning the existence of the separate intellects or any justification concerning their number.[354]

In total, then, there are nine thawânt, which correspond to the nine main celestial orbs of al-Fârâbï’s cosmology, as well as one Agent Intellect, which does not correspond to a celestial orb, but whose task is to govern the sublunary world. Although al-Fârâbï’s cosmology has been called “decadic” (due to the existence of ten separate intellects after the First),[355] it would be more precise to call it an ‘ennadic’ system, because there are nine main celestial orbs and nine thawânt, and because this symmetry breaks down with the Agent Intellect. The idea of an ennadic system is also reinforced by the differences that distin­guish the thawânt from the Agent Intellect.

This multiplicity of souls and intellects at the superlunary level reminds one of the metaphysical models of some Neoplatonic thinkers such as Proclus, while al-Fârâbï’s hierarchy of the First, separate intel­lects, and celestial souls corresponds essentially (although not numeri­cally) to the triad of One, Intellect, and Soul that can be found in the metaphysics of Plotinus (d. 270 CE). These Neoplatonic metaphysical features can be found in the Neoplatonica arabica, including the Arabic corpus that emerged from Proclus’ Elements, i.e., Mahd al-khayr. In spite of these obvious Neoplatonic parallels, however, al-Fârâbï’s dis­tinction between the separate intellects and celestial souls and his con­ception of how these entities relate to the celestial bodies likely stems from a particular interpretation of Aristotle’s Metaphysics Book Lambda 7 and 8. This work posits a first entity at the very top of the celestial hierarchy (the First Unmoved Mover), other lower unmoved movers, and the celestial bodies, which are presumably ensouled. This hypoth­esis seems reasonable, especially given al-Fârâbï’s thorough knowledge of Book Lambda, and in spite of the fact that the distinction in Metaphysics between the separate movers, the orbs, and the celestial souls is not clear and has puzzled ancient, medieval, and modern schol­ars alike.[356]

The key question at this point is how al-Fârâbï interpreted the cosmology of Metaphysics Book Lambda, especially with regard to Aristotle’s doctrine of the unmoved movers. More specifically, how did al-Fârâbï understand the issues of whether these movers are separate from the orbs, of their number, and of their activity? What are the features of his cosmological theory that can be traced to the Arabic versions of Book Lambda, and what are those which in contrast may have derived from other sources or were elaborated by al-Fârâbï himself?[357]

Perhaps the most pressing question in this respect pertains to the philosophical sources underlying al-Fârâbï’s division of the cosmos into nine major orbs, to which correspond nine separate intellects, since this doctrine is not found in this form in Aristotle’s works. Because the structure of al-Fârâbï’s cosmology conforms to the nine­tiered universe of Ptolemy and most Arabic astronomers, it is reason­able to think, as R. Walzer and D. De Smet have, that al-Fârâbï took purely astronomical considerations into account when elaborating his system.[358] But even if this assumption is true, one still has to explain how al-Fârâbï managed to reconcile Aristotle’s unmoved movers with this new astronomical model. Moreover, it does not account for the special nature and activity that characterize the separate intellects, which depart from Aristotle and bear no apparent connection with the Greek and Arabic astronomical traditions. Finally, this assumption runs into a problem related to celestial motion that has not been hith­erto fully addressed and which will be discussed in detail later on.

In the following section, I will examine these questions with the aim of illuminating al-Fârâbï’s doctrine of the nine separate intellects. Special attention will be devoted to the Arabic versions of Book Lambda and some late antique commentaries on this work. This analysis seems highly desirable, because al-Fârâbï’s theory of the separate intellects appears at first glance to be without precedents in the Arabic tradition. Indeed, he is the first Arabic thinker to clearly posit an intermediate level of intellectual beings between God and the material heavens.[359] What is more, the number of intellects he adopts also seems unprece­dented in Greek philosophy, which otherwise provides the closest par­allels to his model. Although several valuable contributions have already discussed some of the sources that influenced al-Fârâbï, no sys­tematic and comparative analysis of these texts, especially in their Arabic translations and adaptations, has been conducted, which would enable a thorough reconstruction of the Second Teacher’s interpreta­tion of ancient Greek cosmology.[360]

2.1.1.    Al-Farabi and the Arabic Versions of Book Lambda on the Unmoved Movers

An obvious place to begin the inquiry is in Aristotle’s Book Lambda, which would have been known to al-Fârâbï in at least two different Arabic translations. The most important questions in this respect are the following: to what extent is al-Fârâbï’s hierarchy of the First, the separate intellects, and the celestial souls, to which correspond the nine main celestial orbs, derived from Book Lambda and its commentaries? Alternatively, what role did late antique Peripatetic and Neoplatonic texts play in shaping his interpretation of this foundational work? Both hypotheses present difficulties. In the case of Book Lambda, one must show that al-Fârâbï construed it in a way that resembles his own cosmological scheme.[361] In positing other, Neoplatonic sources, a new problem arises: these primarily discuss Intellect and Soul as hypo­static or universal ontological entities, not as particular souls and intel­lects inhering in the heavenly orbs, so that the transition from this Neoplatonic framework to al-Fârâbï’s cosmology is neither logical nor obvious and has to be accounted for.

Thanks notably to the recent works of P Thillet and A. Bertolacci, we have a much clearer picture today of the reception of Aristotle’s Metaphysics in the Arabic world.[362] The results of their research show that thinkers active during al-Fârâbï’s time had access to several trans­lations of Book Lambda: one by Ustâth, one by Mattâ ibn Yûnus, which also contained an incomplete commentary by Alexander of Aphrodisias, and one (possibly) by Ishâq ibn Hunayn. Only parts of the first two translations have survived. According to Bertolacci, a terminological comparison between the Arabic translations and al-Fârâbï’s corpus suggests that he probably used Ustâth’s version of Book Lambda, which is the oldest one.[363] Fortunately, this early translation is still partly extant in Ibn Rushd’s Tafsir on Book Lambda of Metaphysics together with a section of Mattâ ibn Yûnus’ translation.[364] In addition, al-Fârâbï may have consulted another version, which was edited by A. Badawi and which has often been called a ‘Neoplatonizing adaptation,’ because it inserts various elements not found in the original Greek and shows some similarity with Theology of Aristotle.[365]

An examination of Ustath’s and Matta ibn Yûnus’ translations shows that although they introduce numerous small and not so small depar­tures from the original Greek text, they convey a relatively accurate picture of Aristotle’s cosmology as it appears in Book Lambda. For example, in textus 42, 43, and 44 of Ibn Rushd’s Tafstr, which contain Ustath’s translation, one finds a discussion of the number of unmoved movers, which in textus 45, 46, and 47 are said to correspond to the number of celestial orbs and whose number is established at 47 or 55. A few passages in particular explicitly assert the Aristotelian theory of a plurality of unmoved movers: “then it is necessary that each one of these motions should be caused by something immovable by essence and an eternal substance”[366]; “It is clear that there must be as many substances as there are motions, that they are naturally eternal and immovable in themselves”[367]; “It must be considered, then, that the unmovable, and also the perceptible, principles, are this many [55 or 47].”[368] In addition, in textus 36 the question of the cause of celestial motion is addressed, and the theory that the Unmoved Mover acts as the first object of desire and thought is presented in a manner that mirrors Lambda 7. Finally, textus 51 defines the First Unmoved Mover as an intellect thinking itself. In spite of the linguistic gap and the haz­ards of textual transmission, then, Arabic thinkers had access through this translation to some of the most important features of Aristotle’s cosmology.

In comparison to Ustath’s version, the Arabic translation edited by A. Badawi differs quite significantly from the Greek original. Some of the essential features of Aristotle’s doctrine in Book Lambda 7 and 8 nevertheless come through in the translation: the Unmoved Mover is said to move the orbs only by way of being an object of desire and an object of thought (wa-tahrtkuhü innama huwa ‘alâ tartq annahü mashüq wa-ma‘qül).[369] The heavenly motions are 47 or 55, as are the “unmoved principles” responsible for the orbs’ motions.[370] It is note­worthy, however, that the reference to the unmoved movers, described as “unmoved principles” (mabadi ghayr al-mutaharrikah) in this trans­lation, is much more fleeting and obscure than in the Ustâth transla­tion. In any case, both translations do mention “unmoved principles” or “unmoved movers.”

This overview enables us to clarify an important point. If al-Fârâbï had access to Ustath’s translation—and the version given in Ibn Rushd’s Tafstr is the closest we can get to the text that al-Fârâbï may have used— then he would certainly have concluded that Aristotle posited a series of unmoved movers, since this theory is explicitly asserted in this trans­lation. Moreover, al-Fârâbï could very well have regarded these movers as being separate from the orbs.[371] That he did in fact construe them as separate substances is confirmed a posteriori by the fact that he defines the separate intellects as movers (sing. muharrik) in his Ft l-aql.[372] But this view is also implicitly conveyed in the Ustâth translation. At textus 41, one reads that “there is a substance which is eternal, immovable and separate [mufariq] from sensible things [i.e., the First Unmoved Mover] .”[373] Shortly afterwards, in textus 42, the Arabic Aristotle raises the question of whether “we should posit one such substance or more,” the separability of these substances being assumed, and con­cludes that there are 47 or 55 movers.[374] Hence, in addition to the pos­tulate of the existence of several unmoved movers, al-Fârâbï may have naturally concluded from the Arabic Book Lambda that these movers are separate from the orbs.

However, contrasting evidence from al-Fârâbï’s works may be adduced against this hypothesis. In some of his other works on Aristotle, al-Fârâbï only mentions one unmoved mover. For example, in Falsafat Aristütalïs, al-Fârâbï writes that

he [Aristotle] investigated whether or not the principles that move the bodies moving in a circular motion by nature are themselves bodies or whether they are nonbodily essences that are, however, in a material and a body. When he had investigated the case closely, it became obvious to him that that which gives circular motion to the bodies at the limits is a certain being [mawjüd ma min al-mawjüdat] that cannot be a nature or a natural thing, or a body or in a body, or ever in a material at all.[375]

And a few pages later, al-Fârâbï mentions only a single mover: “the thing [al-shay] that supplies the heavenly bodies with perpetual circu­lar motion.”[376] In his summary of Aristotle’s philosophy, then, al-Fârâbï focuses on the First Unmoved Mover to the exclusion of the other unmoved movers.

But undue weight should not be placed on these passages, for they appear in the context of al-Fârâbï’s discussion of natural philosophy and more specifically of Aristotle’s Physics. Since al-Fârâbï probably had Physics 8 in mind in this passage, then it is normal that he would only allude to one unmoved mover. Furthermore, in Aghrad, al-Fârâbï provides a very brief yet highly significant summary of the aims of Book Lambda, in which he says that “[Book Lambda also deals with] the separate existents [al-mawjüdat al-mufariqah] that come after [the First Principle] and how their existence is ordered from [the First Principle] ”[377] This statement concerning the aim of Book Lambda goes hand in hand with the reference to the same work that appears at the very end of Fï l-‘aql and which is used to confirm the status of God as First Intellect in a series of separate intellects: “This [i.e., God] is the intellect that Aristotle discusses in Book Lambda of Metaphysics. While each one of the other [separate principles] is also an intellect, this [God] is the First Intellect.”[378] These two passages from Aghrad and Ft l-‘aql convincingly indicate that al-Fârâbï construed Book Lambda as posit­ing several separate unmoved movers. Judging from his own works, it appears that he made this principle one of the cornerstones of his cos­mological model. In holding that there are several separate intellects moving the orbs, al-Fârâbï thereby consciously aligned himself with what he believed was the true Peripatetic tradition.

This point is clear enough. But there are other complications. Al-Fârâbï posits only one mover per celestial group (jumlah) and not, as Aristotle, one mover per orb and motion. If al-Fârâbï had read the Arabic translations of Aristotle carefully (which he surely did), he could not have failed to grasp this point, which is conveyed very lucidly by the Ustâth translation: “It is clear that there must be as many substances as there are motions.” And the text logically concludes that there are 47 or 55 orbs, motion, and separate principles. But unlike the Greek and Arabic versions of Book Lambda, al-Fârâbï rejects these numbers in favour of a system of only nine separate movers. Be it only for this rea­son, his model shows a marked departure from Aristotle’s cosmology. As a corollary, Book Lambda should be regarded as only one of the sources to have informed al-Fârâbï’s cosmology, and one whose con­tents were transformed as a result of other influences. But what were the other sources that shaped al-Fârâbï’s interpretation? Examining how Book Lambda was interpreted by the Greek commentators can shed light on this question.

2.1.2.    Al-Fârâbt and the Greek Commentators on the Unmoved Movers

2.1.2.1. Alexander and Themistius

Recent attempts have been made to delineate with greater precision the late antique Greek sources underlying al-Fârâbï’s cosmology. In an arti­cle published in 1995, M. Maróth argued that Alexander’s Mabadi and Themistius’ Paraphrase of Aristotle’s Book Lambda exercised a decisive influence on al-Fârâbï’s cosmology. Maróth contends that Alexander’s theories of the celestial souls and intellects and Themistius’ model of a nine-orb heaven are key antecedents to understand the cosmology of Arabic philosophers such as al-Fârâbï and Ibn Sïnâ. Accordingly, these two texts, when added to the Aristotelian and Ptolemaic legacies, can account for what Maróth calls al-Fârâbï’s “decadic” cosmologi­cal scheme.[379] In the introduction to his translation of Mabâdi’, C. Genequand also stresses the relevance of Alexander’s work for studying al-Fârâbï’s cosmology, although the common features he discusses are not the same as those highlighted by Maróth.[380]

Maróth’s article sheds valuable light on the relation between al-Fârâbï and the works of the Peripatetic and Neoplatonic commentators, espe­cially Alexander. It is undeniable that Alexander’s Mabâdi’ foreshadows some of the basic ideas of al-Fârâbï’s cosmology, such as the influence of the heavenly bodies on the sublunary world, the parallel made between the cosmic order and the social order, and the emphasis on the ensoulment of the orbs. More specifically, Maróth is right, in my opin­ion, to trace al-Fârâbï’s equation between the souls and the forms of the celestial bodies to Alexander,[381] [382] a doctrine which he may have known not only through Mabâdi’, but also through other fragments derived from Quaestiones.[383]

With regard to the number of the unmoved movers and orbs in the works of Alexander and Themistius, however, the problem is more complex. Maróth’s discussion of this point in Mabâdi’ is marred by the fact that he refers to Alexander’s commentary on Books Lambda and Nu of Metaphysics for support, which have been shown to be inauthen­tic.119 On the basis of these texts, Maróth argues that Alexander posits 47 or 55 cosmic intellects, which correspond to an equivalent number of orbs and celestial motions.[384] But this is likely to be a misinterpreta­tion caused by Maróth’s reliance on the spurious sections of the Meta­physics commentary. In Mabâdi’, Alexander does not mention these numbers, and the passages dealing with the unmoved movers in this work are ambiguous to the extent that it is difficult in the final analysis to establish whether he posits one or several separate unmoved movers.

The text contains conflicting evidence that can be used to support either view. In several passages, Alexander argues that since the motion of the heavens as a whole is regular and continuous, there can only be one unmoved mover, which he identifies with God. In contrast, in another passage, he seems to be alluding to several separate unmoved movers.[385] This being said, the balance seems to tilt in favour of there being only one unmoved mover identified with God, a conclusion reached by both C. Genequand and G. Endress in their studies of the Arabic version of the text.[386]

The question of the number of orbs in Alexander’s cosmology is equally difficult to settle. As Genequand notes, Mabadi seems to put forth a system of eight main celestial orbs.[387] This is confirmed explic­itly by Quaestiones, which mentions eight orbs, and implicitly by some passages in Simplicius’ commentary on On the Heavens in which Alexander refers to the “orb of Saturn” and the “orb of Venus,” thus betraying a simplified cosmology that takes into account only the main orb of each planet.[388] In this connection, Bodnár has shown convinc­ingly that Alexander often represents the cosmos as consisting of eight principal orbs, which nonetheless probably comprise several other minor orbs and spheres.[389] Hence, one cannot conclude from the evi­dence of Mabadi alone that Alexander followed Aristotle’s astronomi­cal model of 47 or 55 orbs.

Maróth’s statements concerning the influence of Themistius’ Paraphrase on al-Fârâbï are equally problematic, as he was appar­ently not aware of the existence of the extant Arabic excerpts of this paraphrase.[390] According to Maróth, Themistius only posits nine celes­tial orbs and thus nine celestial movers, and he suggests that this inno­vation was responsible for al-Fârâbï’s cosmological model.[391] But to my knowledge, no passage in the Hebrew and Arabic texts articulates this view, and Themistius plainly develops in chapter 8 of his commentary a model based on the theories of Aristotle (and indirectly Callipus and Eudoxus), which posits a total of 47 or 55 orbs. In addition, Themistius explicitly states that the number of motions, orbs, and movers must be the same and that therefore the number of movers also amounts to 47 or 55.[392] Finally, although Themistius lived after Ptolemy, he does not mention the Ptolemaic theories of eccentrics and epicycles and most probably adhered to the homocentric astronomical model which he describes in his commentary.[393]

The picture that emerges from the foregoing analysis is as follows. There are only very few similarities between al-Fârâbï and Themistius. Perhaps the main point worth noting is that Themistius posits a plural­ity of movers. But whereas he mentions 47 or 55 movers, al-Fârâbï only speaks of nine celestial movers; and Themistius says nothing as to whether these movers are separate or inhere in the orbs. There are, on the other hand, more significant parallels between Alexander and al-Fârâbï. First, Alexander appears to have reduced Aristotle’s system of 47 or 55 orbs to a simpler system of eight main orbs, and second, his Mabâdi may also be construed as positing several separate movers. Alexander therefore effected a simplification of the Aristotelian model that resulted in something closer to al-Fârâbï’s own solution to the problem.

But more should be said about the latter two points. According to Bodnár, Alexander’s scheme of eight orbs and his attribution of one main orb to each planet was common practice by his time, and other thinkers, such as Adrastus of Aphrodisias and the Platonist Alcinous (who both flourished in the second century CE), had done the same.[394] This way of representing the cosmos, which was made possible by Ptolemy’s work, and which may have arisen out of a reaction vis-à-vis the problems inherent in the Aristotelian kinematic model, was trans­mitted to the Islamic world. It corresponds to al-Fârâbï’s and Ibn Sïnâ’s cosmologies in Ára and Shifa respectively, although the two thinkers added an additional orb, the outermost starless orb. This affiliation with the Greek tradition emphasizes the continuity between Alexander and al-Fârâbï and enables us to better grasp the historical origin of the Second Teacher’s ennadic cosmology. However, this simplified way of representing the cosmos should not obscure the fact that for all of these thinkers the number of orbs that actually exists is much higher. This is because the main orbs each contain several other minor orbs and spheres whose existence is necessary to explain the particular motions of the planets. The main parallel between Alexander and al-Fârâbï, then, rests primarily on their describing a simplified cosmological sys­tem in their philosophical treatises, although they adhered to a more complicated astronomical model.

Second, with respect to the issue of the number of movers in Mabadi, there is some evidence that Arabic thinkers such as al-Fârâbï and Ibn Sïnâ interpreted this text as positing several separate movers in addi­tion to the First Unmoved Mover. There is one particular passage in Mabadi that lends itself to this interpretation:

Let us posit that the noblest of these things and the most deserving to be the first is the mover of the sphere of the fixed stars [al-muharrik li-kurat falak al-kawakib al-thabitah] [i.e., Aristotle’s First Unmoved Mover]; through the latter it also moves the things moved by it; the following is the mover of the second sphere [al-muharrik li-l-kurat al-thaniyyah], and after it the mover of the third sphere, and so on with all the other things.[395]

In this passage Alexander may be interpreted as positing a separate unmoved mover for each main orb of his system, although he does not specify whether the other movers after the First are separate from or inhere in the celestial bodies. But here one may cite a crucial passage from Ibn Sinas Metaphysics of Shifa that seems to vindicate this read­ing of Mabadi. When addressing the thorny question of the unmoved movers in Aristotle’s philosophy, Ibn Sina writes:

It is impossible that the first mover of the whole of heaven should be more than one, even though there is for each of the celestial orbs a proxi­mate mover proper to it, and an object of desire and love proper to it, as the First Teacher and those Peripatetic scholars of attainment after him see it. For they deny multiplicity only [in] the mover of all [things] and affirm multiplicity in the movers, both [those] separated [from matter] [li-l- muharrikat al-mufariqah] and [those] not separated, that specifically belong to each one of the celestial orbs. They thus make the first of the spe­cific separated [entities] the mover of the first orb. [This,] for those who preceded Ptolemy, is the orb of the fixed stars; and, for those who learned the sciences that became manifest to Ptolemy, [it] is an orb outside the [former] which surrounds it and is without stars. After this, [they made] the [second of the separated entities] the mover of the orb that follows the first in accordance with the difference of the two views, and so on.[396]

Ibn Sina in this passage intimates that not only Aristotle, but also the Peripatetic commentators who flourished after him, posited several separate unmoved movers (muharrikat mufariqah) to explain celestial motion. He then goes on to add:

One of his [Aristotle’s] followers, who is more sound than [other follow­ers] in what he says, declares and states in his treatise on the Principles of the Whole [fl risalatihl allatl fl mabadï l-kull] that the mover of the entire heaven is one, it being impossible for it to be numerically many, even though for each of the orbs there is a mover and an object of desire spe­cifically its own.[397]

Immediately after this passage, Ibn Sina describes the view of another Aristotelian follower, probably Themistius. This thinker posits “the existence of a principle of motion belonging specifically to [each celes­tial orb] as being an object of love separated [from matter],” and he concludes that “these two are the closest among the disciples of the First Teacher to being on the right path”[398] Ibn Sina is here providing examples of specific thinkers who, according to him, followed Aristotle in upholding several separate unmoved movers in their cosmology, something which he praises highly. Now, there can be little doubt that the first follower described by Ibn Sïnâ is Alexander, since he mentions Alexander’s treatise by its title (ft risalatiht allait ft mabadi’ l-kull). If this is the case, then this excerpt represents solid evidence that accord­ing to Ibn Sïnâ, Alexander defended the theory of multiple separate unmoved movers. Although Ibn Sïnâ does not specify that these unmoved movers are separate [mufariqah] in the sentence that deals expressly with Alexander, the general context in which his statement appears convincingly indicates that this (on Ibn Sïnâ’s view) is how Alexander construed them.

On the basis of the foregoing analysis, it appears that al-Fârâbï could have anticipated Ibn Sïnâ in interpreting Mabadt as positing several separate movers. When this point is connected with the simplified sys­tem of orbs exposed in Mabadt, we reach a cosmic picture of eight main orbs and several separate unmoved movers (possibly eight). This model would correspond closely to that of al-Fârâbï, who nevertheless added an extra orb and an extra mover as a result of the theory of the ninth, outermost orb upheld by Ptolemy and adopted by most Arabic astronomers. I would argue, then, that in spite of its ambiguity, Mabadt contains some of the key features of al-Fârâbï’s cosmology and signifi­cantly shaped his interpretation of Aristotle’s theory of the unmoved movers.[399]

2.I.2.2. Simplicius

Simplicius’ commentary on On the Heavens appears to be an equally promising source for understanding the philosophical roots of al- Fârâbï’s cosmology. Although this work was apparently not translated in Arabic either in full or in part, the evidence for Simplicius’ influence on Arabic philosophy is slowly increasing, as more and more parallels between his ideas and those of Arabic thinkers are emerging.[400] The present inquiry is a case in point. Like Alexander, Simplicius appears to have drastically altered Aristotle’s complex astronomical model. At one point in his On the Heavens commentary, Simplicius writes the following:

It has not been shown that it [i.e., the heavens] is one orb (since he [Aristotle] knows that the planetary is different from the fixed and he knows the division of the planetary into several <orbs>), but that there is one cosmos with a system of eight orbs and not several heavens which fill out more than one cosmos.[401]

Although in this chapter of his commentary Simplicius is discussing the impossibility of there being several worlds, he gives a vital piece of information concerning his conception of the heavens: these can be reduced to eight main orbs, to a “system of eight orbs.” Hence, like Alexander, Simplicius, following what seems to have been a fairly com­mon trend in late Greek cosmology, presents a simplified astronomical model consisting of eight main orbs, which, one assumes, contains sev­eral other components, such as planets, stars, and perhaps smaller counteracting orbs or epicycles, depending on the nature of his plane­tary models.[402]

There is another passage in Simplicius’ commentary indicating that he may have accepted a ninth starless orb. Simplicius writes:

When I was present in Alexandria, our master Ammonius observed Arcturus using an armillary sphere and found that it had moved forward so much with respect to its position at the time of Ptolemy as to require that it had one degree of contrary motion in one hundred years. So per­haps it would be truer to say that the starless orb which contains <all the orbs>, of which it seems there was no knowledge at the time of Aristotle, carries around all the other <orbs> with its single simple motion from the east.[403]

In this passage, Simplicius refers to a starless orb that would be located beyond the orb of the fixed stars. Although he is not consistent in upholding the existence of this ninth orb, it would seem that he and perhaps his master Ammonius (son of Hermeias, d. ca. 520 CE) devised a system of nine main celestial orbs identical to the one later adopted by al-Fârâbï and Ibn Sïnâ. Furthermore, Simplicius discusses in several parts of his commentary the way in which the Ptolemaic theories of the eccentrics and epicycles, as well as other aspects of Ptolemaic astron­omy, can be integrated in what is otherwise an Aristotelian cosmologi­cal framework.[404] This harmonizing attempt may be explained by the fact that Simplicius thought highly of Ptolemy’s achievement, as is clear when he calls Ptolemy “the best of the astronomers.”[405] Hence, both Simplicius’ cosmology and his attempt to reconcile some aspects of Ptolemaic astronomy with Aristotelian cosmology anticipated the efforts of al-Fârâbï and other Arabic falasifah.

Finally, Simplicius posits several unmoved movers, and he criticizes Alexander for interpreting Aristotle as positing only one mover. In one passage of his commentary, for example, he writes, pace Alexander, that “Aristotle does not say that the mover of the revolving body is single, but rather that while the single movement of the fixed [orb] is caused by the first substance, each of the wandering spheres is moved by an unmoved, eternal substance.”[406] Although he does not say so explicitly, Simplicius probably regarded these movers as being sepa­rate from the celestial bodies, since he criticizes Alexander expressly for his belief in one separate mover, i.e., for recognizing the existence of the First Unmoved Mover only. In spite of the fact that Simplicius does not specify the number of unmoved movers in his commentary, it is possible to connect this text with the other excerpts discussed above and to hypothesize that he may have ascribed one separate mover to each main orb, i.e., eight or nine movers excluding God. His claim in the above citation that “each of the wandering spheres” (t®v 8è nÀavrnqévrnv c^aipmv eKampv) is moved by an unmoved mover is ambiguous, since Simplicius could be referring in this pas­sage either to the main orbs alone or to all the orbs and spheres associ­ated with a planet, in which case the number of movers would be much higher.

Regardless of this ambiguity, Simplicius’ work should be seen as a potential precedent for al-Fârâbï’s model, together with Alexander’s Mabâdi’. These texts share several germane ideas with al-Fârâbï’s ema- nationist treatises. To begin with, they describe a simplified cosmologi­cal model consisting of eight or nine main orbs, while at the same time implicitly upholding the existence of other minor orbs and spheres. Moreover, these thinkers likely interpreted Aristotle’s unmoved movers as separate substances, and it is even possible that they equated the total number of movers with the number of main orbs, i.e., eight or nine. The similarities are reinforced by the fact that Simplicius, following his master Ammonius, conceives of God not only as a final cause, but also as an efficient cause of creation, a doctrine which occupies a central place in the thought of the falasifah.[407] God is responsible for the world’s (beginningless) causation and sustenance, and He stands also as the highest end that all beings aspire to attain in a movement of reversion toward the One. This is exactly the view developed by al-Fârâbï in his later emanationist treatises.

The astronomical and metaphysical parallels outlined above strongly suggest the possibility that al-Fârâbï was acquainted with the works of thinkers from the Ammonian school, especially with Simplicius, who was one of its outstanding members. But there is one important differ­ence in these thinkers’ cosmologies: while al-Fârâbï makes each sepa­rate intellect an efficient cause for the existence and sustenance of its corresponding orb, Ammonius and Simplicius seem to reserve efficient causality to God and do not explicitly connect the existence of each main orb or ‘system’ with a separate principle. It is difficult to pinpoint when and how this cosmological elaboration occurred in the late antique Greek and early Arabic philosophical contexts, and whether al-Fârâbï was its sole author. One may nevertheless hypothesize that al-Fârâbï’s theory is a generalization of the Neoplatonic tendency of construing the Aristotelian First Unmoved Mover as an efficient cause. Al-Fârâbï applies to each unmoved mover/separate intellect of his cos­mology the causative activity that Ammonius, Simplicius, and others had ascribed to the Aristotelian divinity. However, a more convincing interpretation that will be discussed later on is that al-Fârâbï was influ­enced by some of Proclus’ metaphysical theories, which ascribe causa­tive and demiurgic powers to a plethora of intellectual entities.

In any case, in maintaining a level of intellectual beings between the First and the celestial bodies, al-Fârâbï’s cosmology departs radically from that of previous Arabic thinkers, such as al-Kindï and Abû Ma'shar. According to these thinkers, the celestial bodies are interme­diaries between God and the sublunary world, and in this capacity they carry out God’s providence through their continuous influence on the realm of generation and corruption. For al-Fârâbï, in contrast, between God and the celestial bodies lies the realm of the immaterial intellects, or thawânt, with the immediate result that the role of the heavenly bod­ies as intermediaries between God and the sublunary world is drasti­cally modified. In theory, these intellects should stand as a new kind of intermediaries between the First and the corporeal world of the heav­ens, but they in fact possess a high degree of autonomy and causative powers of their own.

This structural difference between the cosmologies of al-Fârâbï and previous Arabic thinkers such as al-Kindï and Abû Ma'shar should not be underestimated. From an epistemological point of view, this privi­leged intermediary status assigned to the heavens meant that the astro­logical investigation was justified and could yield knowledge about divine providence and even about some aspects of the divine nature itself. This explains why both al-Kindï and Abû Ma'shar held astrology in such high esteem. It also partly explains why al-Fârâbï did not share their faith in astrology—in addition to the purely methodological qualms he had with this science—and why he does not perceive the celestial bodies as transmitters of divine providence in the way envis­aged by these earlier thinkers. In addition, and more significantly from a metaphysical perspective, the disjunction he introduces between the First and the celestial bodies enables al-Fârâbï to articulate a completely different account of creation and causality, since God becomes only one cause among a multiplicity of eternal efficient causes responsible for causing the existence of the material universe (ch. 3, 2.6.). Hence, al-Fârâbï’s articulation of the Aristotelian theory of the unmoved movers announced a new way of framing and conceiving causality in the superlunary world, one which dispensed with the creationist and astrological model of al-Kindi, and which relied instead on a subtle conceptualization of efficient and final causality distributed on several levels. In that sense, al-Farabi’s theories must be regarded as an impor­tant development in the early history of Arabic metaphysics and cosmology.

2.2. A New Problem

In the foregoing discussion, I argued that the structure of al-Farabi’s cosmology, especially with regard to the separate intellects, is based on a particular interpretation of Metaphysics, Book Lambda, which was informed by some late antique works expounding on this seminal text. It was shown that Alexander’s and Simplicius’ views anticipated some important aspects of the ennadic system developed by al-Farabi. What is striking about these works is that they combine the cosmological theories of Book Lambda with a revised astronomical model, thus anticipating a salient trait of al-Farabi’s method. At a structural level, then, al-Farabi’s cosmology was shaped considerably by some of the philosophical and astronomical developments that occurred in late antiquity.

Yet despite these important clarifications, there remains a crucial problem, which is not fully accounted for by the sources and which the foregoing interpretation does not adequately explain. Why is there no correlation in al-Farabi’s system between the number of separate intel­lects and the number of planetary motions and orbs? It is worth recall­ing here that al-Farabi upheld the materiality of the various celestial entities, including the eccentrics and epicycles. Since each main orb contains various other minor orbs and spheres in addition to the planet—each entity (with the possible exception of the planet) possess­ing its own motion—it would be necessary, for al-Farabi’s ‘Aristotelian’ system to be functional, that each orb and sphere contemplate its own separate intellect, which is defined as a mover (muharrik) in Fil-‘aql.[408] If he were truly following the model developed in Book Lambda 7 and 8, then he would, like Aristotle and some of the later commenta­tors, have posited as many movers as there are celestial orbs and motions. Themistius in his Paraphrase, for instance, follows Aristotle in arguing that there are 47 or 55 orbs, and then states that “it is neces­sary that the number of motions be equal to the number of orbs that move, and that the number of motive causes be equal to the number of motions.”[409] Why does al-Fârâbï depart from the Stagirite and his com­mentator Themistius on this point and limit the number of movers to nine (excluding the First Cause and the Agent Intellect)?

There are, I believe, two plausible solutions to this problem. The first one is that al-Fârâbï conceived of the separate intellects primarily as causes of being and only secondarily as causes of motion. Each intellect is responsible for producing a main orb, which may include, as we have seen, stars or a planet as well as other minor orbs and spheres embed­ded within it. In other words, each intellect produces a celestial “sys­tem” (jumlah) to use al-Fârâbï’s terminology. Unlike the cosmology of Aristotle and other Greek thinkers where the relation between the orbs and the separate intellect(s) is limited to motion, al-Fârâbï also defines it in terms of efficient causality, arguing that each separate intellect is the efficient cause of its corresponding celestial system. This is why he begins his account in Ára by explaining how the orbs are caused, and only afterwards addresses the question of their motion.[410] This also explains why in Fï l-aql, al-Fârâbï describes the separate intellects as “movers,” but instead of proceeding to a discussion of motion (as one would expect), he focuses solely on the question of the existence and causation of the orbs.[411]

It is this very emphasis on the efficient activity of the separate intel­lects that may explain why al-Fârâbï only posits nine intellects, a number which obviously does not correspond to the number of plan­etary motions and celestial bodies. By definition, the separate intellects have a dual intellection, and as a result of this dual intellection, they can only produce two distinct effects: one is the existence of another intellect, and the other is the existence of a main orb together with its soul, i.e., a planetary ‘system.’ This also implies that the same cause is made to account for a diversity of corporeal components within a celes­tial ‘system.’ Now, if al-Fârâbï had wanted to assign a specific efficient cause to each corporeal component in the heavens (i.e., to all the main orbs, minor orbs and spheres, planets, and stars), he would have had to introduce a plethora of intellects, which would have significantly complexified his account and altered its simple elegance. According to this interpretation, then, al-Fârâbï’s priority in devising his cosmo­logical system was not the question of celestial motion, but rather to provide an explanation of the existence of the heavens that relies on as few causes as possible. His main consideration was of an ontological order and focused on the concept of efficient causality, not on celestial kinematics. If this is true, it would underline the gap between the cos­mological projects of Aristotle in Book Lambda 7 and 8 and of the Greek commentators on the one hand and the aim of al-Fârâbï on the other.

The historical process by virtue of which this interpretation may have occurred cannot be discussed in detail here, as it deals with efficient causation and creation and will accordingly be treated in chapter 3 of this book. Suffice it to say that it is likely in my view that al-Fârâbï may have construed the Aristotelian movers as efficient causes or beings endowed with demiurgic powers by following some of the Athenian Neoplatonists, such as Proclus and his master Syrianus. As the extant parts of Syrianus’ Metaphysics commentary testify, these late antique Greek thinkers had already transformed the Aristotelian unmoved movers in light of Neoplatonic elaborations on causality, intellection, and demiurgy. In this respect, they anticipated al-Fârâbï’s own metaphysical system in emphasizing the role of these beings as cosmic principles of existence and unity.[412]

A second line of interpretation—briefly intimated, but not devel­oped at any length by Walzer—focuses instead on the question of celes­tial motion.[413] A convenient starting point for discussing it is a passage that appears in the Metaphysics section of Ibn Sïnâ’s Shifa. Ibn Sïnâ begins by stating the following:

In sum, it is inevitable that each [of the orbs] that moves for a rational end should have an intellectual principle that intellectually apprehends the First Good and that the essence [of this intellectual principle] is sepa­rated [from matter].[414]

Having associated one separate intellect or mover per orb, Ibn Sïnâ then goes on to discuss whether a separate intellect should be ascribed only to the main orbs or to each individual orb, including the subordi­nate ones:

Thus, the number of the separate intellects after the First Principle would be the same as the number of movements. If, in the case of the orbs of the wanderers [li-aflak al-mutahayyirah], the principle of the movement of the spheres[415] of each planet therein is a power emanating from the plan­ets [quwwah tafidu min al-kawakib], then it would not be unlikely that the separate [intellects] would have the same number as the number of these [planets]—not the spheres—and their number would be ten, after the First. Of these, the first would be the unmoved mover that moves the orb of the outermost body, then the one similar to it [that moves] the orb of the fixed stars, then the one that is like it [that moves] the orb of Saturn, and so on, terminating in the intellect that emanates on us—namely, the intellect of the terrestrial world, which we call the active intellect. If, how­ever, this is not the case, but each moving orb has a rule governing its own motion and every star, then these separate [intellects] would be of a greater number. It would follow, according to the doctrine of the First Teacher, that there would be something close to fifty and over, the last being the active intellect. But you have known, from what we have said in the Mathematics, what we have attained in ascertaining their number.[416]

This passage is of primary importance for several reasons. First, it shows that Ibn Sïnâ was conscious of the basic tension under discus­sion, which he probably inherited alongside al-Fârâbï’s cosmology. In this passage, Ibn Sïnâ envisages the possibility of two systems of celes­tial motion. In the first one, only one separate intellect per main orb (or system) is posited, and the motion of the other subordinate orbs and spheres is explained in terms of a power (quwwah) that emanates from (taftdu min) the planet. In the second model, all the orbs, both the main ones and the subordinate ones, are moved by an unmoved mover, as in Aristotle’s model, which attributes a mover per motion and per orb.[417] Ibn Sïnâ’s account enables us to confirm not only that the coexistence of these various kinematic models was seen as a genuine problem by medieval Arabic cosmologists, but also that each one of them repre­sented a valid explanation of celestial motion. It is likely that Ibn Sïnâ’s awareness of this problem was shared by his predecessor al-Fârâbï, although no comparable passage can be found in the Second Teacher’s works.

Second, the Shifa passage vindicates the reading that was proposed earlier concerning the various kinds of orbs in al-Fârâbï’s system. It indicates that besides the main planetary orbs, Arabic thinkers pos­ited smaller, subordinate orbs and spheres, which altogether combined to form a single unit governed by a separate intellect. Finally, this pas­sage helps to understand why someone like al-Fârâbï may have reduced the number of movers and posited only one separate intellect per sys­tem, and not per orb and motion: he may have developed a particular theory of celestial motion that did not require the 47 or 55 movers mentioned by Aristotle, and which in contrast involved the existence of powers emanating from the planet embedded in each system.[418] This hypothesis, which will be discussed at length in chapter 4, indicates that al-Fârâbï may have devised a kinematic model akin to the first one described by Ibn Sïnâ in this passage of Shifa’.

The two interpretations proposed above, which, it should be noted, are not mutually exclusive, can account satisfactorily for the fact that al-Fârâbï departs from Book Lambda and does not posit a separate principle per heavenly motion and per celestial orb, but simply one separate intellect per main orb or ‘planetary group,’ to use al-Fârâbï’s terminology. By making each intellect the efficient and final cause of the various elements of a celestial system, al-Fârâbï is displaying a great economy of intelligible principles, a kind of Ockham’s razor adapted to his cosmology. Unlike Proclus, who posits a plethora of immaterial, intelligible principles, al-Fârâbï, I believe, aims to establish a balance between the deductive and the inductive, between experience and observation on the one hand and deduction and synthesis on the other, and both are to meet midway methodologically in his cosmology. Understandably, al-Fârâbï does not want to posit more principles than are necessary to explain the world of nature and the existence of the heavens. He achieves a much more unified synthesis between the perceptible and the immaterial, between induction and deduction than does Proclus, for example, whose innumerable deities and other intelligible principles do not have an exact corporeal counterpart.

Indeed, the economy of principles underlying al-Fârâbï’s system sug­gests a careful and well-thought-out theorizing of these cosmological problems in his philosophy.[419]

We may conclude that al-Fârâbï’s theory of the nine separate intel­lects and of how these fit in a new astronomical model derived from Ptolemy developed out of a sustained exegetical effort and a process of adaptation of the ancient sources. The simplified cosmological struc­ture of nine main orbs, the theory of the ensoulment of the heavens, the existence of a plurality of separate intellects responsible for causing their motion, and the attempt to reconcile Ptolemaic kinematic theo­ries with physical and metaphysical ideas, are features that can be traced back partially to the works of Alexander and Simplicius. Hence, it is clear that al-Fârâbï’s interpretation of Book Lambda was mediated and shaped by several layers of philosophical exegesis, a hypothesis which will be further substantiated with regard to his theories of celes­tial matter and causation in the next chapter. In spite of these parallels, however, it should be noted that no single Greek source contains all the features adopted by the Second Teacher and harmoniously synthesized in his works. This should stand as a reminder that, while profoundly engaged in the study of the late antique literature, al-Fârâbï displayed critical insight and creativity in his approach to these sources, espe­cially with regard to his theory of the nine separate intellects. The latter should be considered as an important cosmological development in Arabic philosophy and as an original interpretation of the Aristotelian theory of the unmoved movers.

2.3. The Nature, Activity, and Knowledge of the Separate Intellects

The separate intellects or thawdnt, like the First (Itself an intellect) and the celestial souls, have intellection (taaqqul) as their principal activity. However, unlike the First, which contemplates only Its essence, and the celestial souls, which apprehend three intelligibles, the intellection of each separate intellect (with the exception of the Agent Intellect) focuses on two objects: the First, and its own essence. This model is developed in some detail in Ára and Siyasah, and it also appears briefly in Fl l-aql. One passage of the latter treatise conveniently encapsulates these various points: “Now, since the mover of the first heaven is nei­ther matter nor in matter, it necessarily follows that it is an intellect in its substance, in which case it contemplates itself and the very thing that is the principle of its existence [i.e., the First].”[420] Due to their hav­ing two objects of thought, the intellects are not completely simple beings and are affected by multiplicity or complexity (kathrah), which is nevertheless not as great as that of the celestial souls.[421] According to Neoplatonic metaphysics, which al-Fârâbï follows on this point, the higher one progresses on the ontological hierarchy, the more perfectly the concepts of unity and simplicity are expressed, until one reaches the First, which is absolutely one and simple. Conversely, as one descends this ontological ladder, one encounters an increasing degree of multiplicity. Al-Fârâbï’s theories of celestial intellection should be construed in light of this hierarchical ontological framework.

As in the previous discussion on the celestial souls, one notices strik­ing parallels between al-Fârâbï’s theory of the intellects and the doc­trines of the Proclus arabus. The first entity to emerge from the First Cause is conceived of in similar terms by al-Fârâbï and the Arabic adaptors of Proclus, namely, as a separate intellect. On this point, they depart from the historical Proclus, for whom the One first emanates Being, then Life, then Intellect. The elimination of these intermediary entities between the One and Intellect is, together with the equation of God and Pure Being, the most notable and radical transformation undergone by the Greek Proclus in the Arabic context.[422] This being said, the Arabic adaptors and al-Fârâbï follow Proclus quite closely in their conception of the intellect’s substance, activity, and knowledge.[423] In Elements, Proclus argues that the Primal Intellect is not completely simple, because it is composed of the duality of Finitude-Infinity. He then goes on to show that every intellectual being subsequent to the Primal Intellect possesses a certain plurality in its essence due to its thinking its own essence as well as its causes and effects. Hence, while the Primal Intellect derives its multiplicity from its being composed of Finitude and Infinity, the subsequent intellects are affected by multi­plicity as a result of their various objects of thought. As Proclus writes in Proposition 167, “each subsequent intelligence knows simultane­ously itself and its priors, so that its object is in part itself, but in part its source.”[424]

These ideas reappear in the works forming the Proclus arabus corpus. In Proposition 4 of Mahd al-khayr, it is said that the first originated being (i.e., Intellect) “receives multiplicity,” because it is “composed of finitude and infinitude.”[425] In Liber de causis II, the intel­lect is “multiple [kathtr] because of the virtues it receives from the First Cause.”[426] More important for our purposes is the link between intel­lection and complexity in the other intellectual beings. In one of the propositions of the Proclus arabus edited by G. Endress, the author dis­cusses the intellection of the intellectual beings and concludes: “It has been established by now that there exists a knowledge that knows its essence and knows what is above it, without the knower and the known being like one thing.”[427] This theory also has a pendant in Mahd al- khayr, where one finds the assertion that the intellects know what is above them and what is below them through their own substance.[428] In a way, this does not mean that a real complexity affects the intellects, since the knowledge of each intellect is nothing else than the knowl­edge of its own essence. In other words, the various kinds of knowledge of the intellects can be reduced to the knowledge they have of them­selves. Accordingly, the adaptor of Mahd al-khayr concludes that “the intellect and the intelligible things ... are one.”[429] On the other hand, however, intellect is not completely simple in the way that the First Cause is simple. The very fact that it possesses a cause suggests that it cannot be completely simple and that it contains multiplicity in its essence. Hence, the adaptors of Mahd al-khayr and of Liber II seem to oscillate in their descriptions of the intellect, which is not simple when compared to the One, but whose various kinds of knowledge can nev­ertheless be subsumed under the knowledge it has of its essence.

The idea that the essence of intellect is characterized by multiplicity or complexity is found in al-Fârâbï’s metaphysics as well, although it is derived not from the Finitude-Infinity dichotomy that characterizes the Primal Intellect, but rather from the multiple objects of intellection of the subsequent intellectual beings. In al-Fârâbï’s cosmology, each separate intellect reflects on God and its own essence and therefore has a dual intellection. This duality prevents the intellects from being absolutely simple. As al-Fârâbï says, “there is a multiplicity in the very being of each of them [the separate intellects], since anything that intellects some other given thing does itself, in a certain manner, become that other thing while simultaneously being its own proper self”[430] The intellects therefore initiate the process of variety and multi­plicity in the metaphysical world, and this in spite of their immaterial­ity. They are below the First Cause in the ontological hierarchy and are the first kinds of beings to possess some degree of multiplicity or com­plexity. Hence, with regard to the intellection and nature of the sepa­rate intellects, al-Fârâbï is relying directly on some propositions of Proclus arabus.

But the parallels do not end here. A common feature in the Greek Proclus and the Neoplatonica arabica is the relation established between knowledge of the cause and of the self. This is a crucial concept for Proclus and many Neoplatonists, because it creates a noetical and causal link between the various metaphysical entities and implements the fundamental rule that the effect should be in a sense like the cause and the cause like the effect. In Proposition 167 of Elements, for instance, Proclus explains that each intellect knows itself and its prior cause, and that by knowing its prior cause, it knows its own essence.

The gist of this idea appears to have been conveyed by the Arabic adaptors and translators of Proclus. In Proposition 167 of Proclus arabus, one reads in respect to the intellectual beings: “if it knows what is above it, it also knows its own essence.”[431] Risalah fi l-‘ilm al-ilahi, a text derived from the Plotinus arabus, contains a similar passage, where the author argues that since the intellect knows God, Who is its cause, it must necessarily know itself as well. He writes: “If we concede to you that the intellect knows and desires God, may He be exalted, we concede also that when it knows Him it knows itself [‘alima dhatahü]” And he adds shortly after: “If ... we concede that the intellect knows God Almighty, then it knows His powers too. And if the intellect knows His powers, it knows itself.”[432] Mahd al- khayr makes a similar point with regard to the knowledge of the intel­lectual beings, but also extends this knowledge to the lower effects: “every intellect ... knows what is below it, because it is a cause of it, and knows what is above it, because it acquires the virtues from it.”[433] Finally, in an excerpt of Proclus arabus, the relation between knowledge of the self and of the effect is also clearly asserted: “As for the rest of the things endowed with knowledge [or science, ‘ilm], each one of them knows its essence and knows what is above it [for this is also knowable]. I say that it knows what is above it and knows those things that are below it.”[434]

The identity or connection between knowledge of the cause and of the essence is nowhere stated explicitly by al-Fârâbï, who appears to have maintained a sharp distinction between these two kinds of knowl­edge.[435] His aim in doing so was perhaps to strengthen the duality of the intellects’ contemplative activity, which not only distinguishes them from the perfectly unitary intellection of the First, but which is also used to explain how two different effects can proceed from these intel­lects. These distinctions would have been somewhat fuzzy if al-Fârâbï had collapsed both types of knowledge (of the First and of the essence) into one.

In spite of this, we cannot completely exclude the possibility that al-Fârâbï would have accepted the theory that by knowing their cause, i.e., God, the intellects know their essence, for nothing of what he says contradicts this view. Ibn Sïnâ adopted it later on, arguing that each separate intellect can know its essence either in itself (as ‘possible of existence’) or through its cause (as ‘necessary of existence’). But Ibn Sïnâ developed in this respect a threefold model of intellection, while al-Fârâbï adhered to a twofold model that does not hinge on the modal distinction between ‘possible’ and ‘necessary’ later made by Ibn Sïnâ.

It should be noted that in al-Fârâbï’s system, unlike in that of Ibn Sïnâ, each intellect does not contemplate the intellect located immedi­ately above it, but rather the First Cause. This is slightly surprising, because according to al-Fârâbï, each intellect is directly caused by the intellect above it, so that its proximate efficient cause is this prior intel­lect rather than the First Cause itself. Al-Fârâbï’s view could be explained by the propensity among monotheistic philosophers to emphasize the causal primacy of God to the detriment of the other metaphysical beings and to limit the causative role of these other beings. By making each intellect reflect on God rather than a higher intellect, al-Fârâbï would be emphasizing that God is indeed the First Cause of all beings, even the ones located at a distance from His immediate emanation. But this theory is hard to reconcile with other aspects of his metaphysics, especially with the emphasis he places on the causative autonomy of the separate intellects (ch. 3, 2.6).

Al-Fârâbï is more straightforward when it comes to knowledge of the essence and of the effect. Here one can be quite certain that he rejected any essential connection between the two. In Siyasah, for instance, he writes that

it is not part of their nature [the separate intellects’] to gain the splen­dour, beauty, and adornment of existence by contemplating anything existing below them, or anything that comes to be out of each of them, or anything that is consequential to the existence of each of the existing beings; none of that is associated with any one of them or inheres in any one of them.[436]

In Ara, al-Fârâbï also states somewhat mysteriously that “what it [the first separate intellect] thinks of its own essence is no more than its essence.”[437] The emphasis on the separate intellect’s essence may serve to indicate that it does not acquire cognition of lower beings or of any other intelligible apart from the First. The radical detachment of the separate intellects from what lies beneath them seems appropriate to the mode of their intellection, which focuses on the unchanging and eternal principles that are the First and their own essence. Al-Fârâbï’s restriction of the intellects’ cognition to a higher principle is hardly surprising, given that he also rejects the idea of celestial imagination and the theory that the celestial souls know what lies beneath them. While his view is aligned with the doctrine of ‘learned ignorance’ or of ‘an ignorance higher than knowledge’ that one finds in Theology of Aristotle with regard to the principle of intellect, it on the other hand departs from the passages of Proclus arabus cited above.[438]

So far I have emphasized mostly the parallels between the Neoplatonica arabica, especially Proclus arabus, and al-Farabi’s theories of the thawânt. However, with regard to how intellection relates to actuality and potency, the Second Teacher is in complete disagreement with the Arabic Neoplatonic texts. In Theology of Aristotle, the adaptor argues that the higher mode of thought, that is, the mode of thought applicable to the incorporeal and intellectual entities, is potency, not actuality. As he writes, potency (al-quwwah) is, “in the high intellectual substances, that which manifests and perfects activity [al-fi’l], whereas in the corporeal substances it is activity that perfects potency and brings it to the limit.”[439] Mahd al-khayr also articulates a similar idea, which can be traced back to several propositions of Elements, espe­cially Propositions 78, 91, and 92, as well as to Plotinus’ Enneads.[440] While the idea of a potency that surpasses actuality ultimately has its roots in these Greek works, the adaptors of Theology of Aristotle and Mahd al-khayr were obviously keen to elaborate on it. In the context of Neoplatonic philosophy, quwwah is not meant to express Aristotle’s concept of potentiality, but rather a power that transcends actuality and causes actuality in lower beings. For instance, the Intellect may be said to possess a potency or power that causes the actuality of the Soul.[441]

In contrast, al-Farabi categorically rejects the idea of a potency or power (quwwah) that would transcend actuality. He follows Aristotle in holding that everything above the orb of the moon is in a state of constant and perfect actuality, and he contrasts this eternal actuality to the potency (in the sense of potentiality) of the sublunary existents. God, to begin with, is “actual intellect” (aql bi-l-fif.'7 The souls of the heavenly bodies are, for their part, “in no way and at no time in poten­tiality. On the contrary, they are always in actuality.”[442] [443] Finally, although al-Fârâbï does not state this explicitly in his works, it is obvious that the separate intellects are in a state of complete actuality as well, since they are above the celestial souls in the hierarchy of being. In addition, like the First, they are immaterial and constantly actualized by their intel­lection. Their only deficiency derives from their having multiple objects of thought. Al-Fârâbï thus restricts potency to the corporeal world, especially to sublunary matter. On this particular issue he follows Aristotle and the Peripatetic tradition rather than the Neoplatonica arabica.

2.4.    The Special Case of the Agent Intellect

I shall not concern myself here with the Greek antecedents to the theory of the Agent Intellect, or with the unique role that this intel­lect plays in the processes of sublunary change and human intellec­tion. These topics have already been discussed quite extensively by H. A. Davidson and other scholars and could very well form the subject matter of a new monographic study.[444] Rather, I wish merely to high­light some of the most striking features of the Agent Intellect in the superlunary context, as well as the discrepancies between it and the other separate intellects, because these features have not been suffi­ciently emphasized in the modern literature.

To begin with, the Agent Intellect is distinguished by having a three­fold intellection, instead of a twofold intellection like the thawânt. As al-Fârâbï explains in Siyasah: “As for the Agent Intellect, it contemplates the First, all the thawânt, and its own essence.”[445] Hence, in terms of the structure of its intellection, the Agent Intellect is comparable to the celestial souls, whose contemplation encompasses three different kinds of intelligibles. There is, however, an important difference. Whereas each celestial soul contemplates only the separate intellect to which it owes its existence, the Agent Intellect apprehends all the prior intellects in one sweep (wa-l-thawant kullaha). The conclusion is that the Agent Intellect has a unique kind of intellection, which sets it apart from that of the other separate intellects and the celestial souls.

Al-Fârâbï does not explain why the Agent Intellect is unique, nor is there any particular reason that could immediately justify this fact. However, at least one hypothesis can be advanced. According to the Second Teacher, the separate intellects and heavenly bodies are organ­ized hierarchically with respect to their nobility, which itself depends on their causal proximity to the First. The Agent Intellect is the tenth separate intellect and lies below the nine thawant, although it is higher in rank than the celestial bodies. As a result of its lower rank and its remoteness from the First, it does not produce another separate intel­lect and an orb, but instead governs the sublunary world. This is the most conspicuous difference between the Agent Intellect and the thawant. Now, the separate intellects are alike in that they are all imma­terial and intellectual beings, so that the substance of the Agent Intellect is really the same as that of the thawant. Their only deficiency lies in their having various objects of intellection, which causes a certain mul­tiplicity to exist in them. Hence, it is at this level only that al-Fârâbï can establish a distinction between these intellects and justify the fact that the Agent Intellect is the last and lowest in the series. This he does by ascribing a threefold intellection to the Agent Intellect, thus setting it apart from the thawant, which only have a twofold intellection. This threefold intellection means that the Agent Intellect has a lower status than the thawant, because it possesses a higher degree of multiplicity. It is this greater degree of multiplicity attached to its threefold intellec­tion that can best account for its special status and for the fact that it cannot emanate another separate intellect.[446]

There is, however, another peculiar feature about the threefold intel­lection of the Agent Intellect. Not only does it mirror that of the celes­tial souls, but it can also be compared to the activity of the human intellect, which in al-Fârâbï’s noetics possesses three stages: potential, active, and acquired. The parallel between these three human noetical stages and the three objects of thought reflected upon by the Agent Intellect is strengthened by the fact that the Agent Intellect is responsi­ble for the actualization of the human intellect. It is thanks to the Agent Intellect that human beings can reach the state of the acquired intellect. In this connection, al-Fârâbï writes that the Agent Intellect “belongs to the same species as the acquired intellect” in humans (wa-l-‘aql al-fa“al huwa min naw’ al-'aql al-mustafad).133 This statement is at first glance surprising, because the celestial souls are said in another passage to belong to a different species from the human intellect, and so a fortiori the separate intellects should be even more different from the human intellect.[447] [448] [449] But in light of the role of the Agent Intellect in human cog­nition and in the actualization of human knowledge, it is understand­able that al-Fârâbï would want to stress the kinship between them. Hence, the unique status and mode of contemplation of the Agent Intellect can also be explained in terms of its function in actualizing the human rational soul, which both possess a tripartite structure. If the Agent Intellect were radically different from the human intellect, then our capacity to acquire knowledge would become difficult to explain.

This suggests that al-Fârâbï probably intended to model his cosmol­ogy closely on his psychology. He elaborates a celestial noetics that is in many respects symmetrical to his theories of human noetics. Thanks to the previous analysis, it is easier to understand why al-Fârâbï in Siyasah lists the Agent Intellect as a principle that is distinct from the other separate intellects (thawant).135 Although all of these beings share a common immaterial and intellectual essence, the Agent Intellect nev­ertheless fulfills a unique epistemological function in al-Fârâbï’s cos­mology, which is implied by the structural parallel between its mode of functioning and the human mind.

2.5.    Intellect and Form

One of the salient features of al-Fârâbï’s theory of the celestial souls is his claim that they can be identified with celestial forms (suwar). The heavenly bodies are “like” sublunary beings in that they have a sub­strate, and they are also “like” them in that they possess a form, which for al-Fârâbï is their soul (nafs).[450] Unlike sublunary substrates, how­ever, which can receive a variety of forms, the heavenly bodies only ever possess one single irreplaceable form. Yet the mention of form in a superlunary context is somewhat problematic, since according to al-Fârâbï’s physics, form always inheres in matter. This problem is com­pounded by his frequent claim that the celestial souls are essentially intellects, thus making this identification even more puzzling. To what extent should the equation between form and intellect be taken liter­ally? And can the concept of form be extended to the separate intellects as well? In order to answer these questions, it is necessary to examine al-Fârâbï’s views on the separability of form.

The passages in the Fârâbïan corpus dealing with the question of the separability of form display many tensions. On the one hand, al-Fârâbï is quite clear that form and matter are principles that pertain to the sublunary world alone, and thus one assumes that they have no place in the heavens. He explains that form cannot exist without matter and must inevitably inhere in a material substrate. In talking about the First Cause in Ára, for example, al-Fârâbï asserts that it does not have form, “because form can exist only in matter.”[451] In Siyasah, al-Fârâbï writes “that forms do not subsist by themselves, as they need a subject in order to exist, and their subject is matter.”[452] In another passage, al-Fârâbï distinguishes between the forms that inhere in the matter of concrete objects, which he calls su war, and the forms that enter the various fac­ulties of the human soul as a result of abstraction, which he calls “imprints” (rusüm). He then adds that although these imprints are “like forms in matters, they are definitely not called forms, except in an ana­logical manner [illa ‘ala sabil al-tashbth]” Also significant is al-Fârâbï’s statement that the imprints of the intelligibles are “most unlike forms” and that “in the case of the actual intellect’s becoming like the Agent Intellect, the intellect is not a form nor even like a form.” He concludes that it is only by homonymy (ishtirak) that one may call the human intellect a form in this case.[453] What this shows is that the human intel­lect and a fortiori the two classes of celestial intellects are not forms stricto sensu, but rather can be called forms in a homonymous manner. These passages from Siyasah argue clearly that form can only truly exist when it is embedded in material substrates.

On the other hand, Fi l-aql unambiguously posits the existence of immaterial forms. At one point, al-Fârâbï writes: “In the case of exist­ing things that are forms that neither are in matters nor were ever in matters.”[454] The possibility that forms can exist without an accompany­ing matter is also asserted in another passage: “What Aristotle calls the ‘Agent Intellect’ in Book 3 of On the Soul is a separate form [sürah mufariqah] that has never been and never will be in matter.”[455] Al-Fârâbï defends the existence of separate forms in some of his other works, as in Jam, whose authenticity, it should be stressed, is problematic. In this work he refers to the authority of Theology of Aristotle to argue that Aristotle agrees with Plato in positing spiritual forms (su war rühaniyyah) devoid of matter, although these are said to subsist in the divine essence.[456] In Falsafat Aristü ta lis, he also describes the Agent Intellect as “a separate form of man.”[457] Although he does not mention any Neoplatonic text by name, it is clear that material from the Neoplatonica arabica is lurking in the background, as the theory of separate forms is a salient trait of this corpus.[458] Hence, according to certain works by

al-Fârâbï, the Agent Intellect as well as the universals subsisting in God’s essence can be defined as immaterial forms. Just as form expresses essence in the sublunary world, it would seem that the essence of the superlunary intellects is also reducible to form. Interestingly, the over­lap between the two concepts of form and intellect is observable both in al-Fârâbï’s celestial and human noetics.[459]

How should one reconcile al-Fârâbï’s various statements on the separability of form? Did his views on this topic change over a period of time? This is a likely hypothesis, since the works in which al-Fârâbï clearly rejects the existence of separate forms, namely, Ára and Siyasah, were composed at the end of his life. In contrast, the works in which he endorses this theory, such as Jam’ and Falsafat Aristütâlts, are presumably earlier compositions. Moreover, the presence of a specific analogical terminology in the emanationist treatises with regard to how forms relate to the superlunary entities suggests a certain deve­lopment in al-Fârâbï’s reflection on this point. In these works, he com­pares the celestial soul to form, but nowhere does he establish a strict identity between the two. The celestial soul is “like” form and “resembles” form. This analogical language, or language of similarity, suggests that al-Fârâbï did not conceive of the celestial souls as forms stricto sensu and that he merely used this comparison to facilitate the reader’s grasp of the nature of the celestial beings. As for the separate intellects, nowhere are they identified with forms in the manner stated in Falsafat Aristii talis. Hence, this variegated evidence definitely raises the possibility of an evolution in al-Fârâbï’s concep­tion of how soul and intellect relate to the concept of form. This devel- opmentalist hypothesis will be further explored at a later stage, but for the time being I wish to complete the structural overview of al-Fârâbï’s cosmology by turning to the highest metaphysical entity, namely, God or the First.

3. The First (al-awwal)

The terms al-Fârâbï uses most frequently to describe God are ‘the First’ (al-awwal) and ‘the First Cause’ (al-sabab al-awwal). These two expres­sions refer to God’s essential priority in existence over all the other entities and to His causing the lower effects out of His own essence. It should be said from the outset, however, that the mode in which the First causes the universe to exist is an ambiguous topic in al-Fârâbï’s cosmology and has divided scholarly opinion for some time. To begin with, al-Fârâbï presents different accounts of creation in his works. In some treatises attributed to him, notably Jam’ and Jawabat, he seems to adhere to a creationist position, according to which God created the whole world ex nihilo, all at once, and together with time and will destroy it at some point in the future. But in other works, and especially in his emanationist treatises, the First is said to act as an eternal cause of the world’s existence, the world itself having neither beginning nor end. Even his emanationist treatises are not devoid of ambiguity, as al-Fârâbï limits God’s causation to a single effect (the first separate intellect) and also endows the separate intellects (thawam) with the capacity to bring other beings into existence on their own and through their own powers. This raises the questions of how the First differs in its creative activity from the other separate intellects, and of whether creationism—in the sense of there being a unique Creator-God respon­sible for the world’s existence—has any relevance at all in al-Fârâbï’s philosophy (ch. 3, 2.6).

With regard to al-Fârâbï’s ‘theology’ or his views on God’s existence and essence, only few statements can unambiguously and positively be made.[460] The First is a substance (jawhar), which is eternal (azalt), autonomous, non-hylomorphic and of an intellectual nature, and in essence one and simple (wahid and bastt). An important feature stressed by al-Fârâbï is the identity between intellect and the divine essence. Since the First is immaterial, It must necessarily be an intellect (’aql), as al-Fârâbï considers all immaterial beings to be of an intellectual nature. More specifically, however, It is a perfect intellect that is not affected by any kind of deficiency (naqs) and plurality or complexity (kathrah), and which thus possesses a unitary and perfectly simple intellectual existence. It may be described as pure reason or as thought itself, and in that sense it is the originative source to which all rational beings seek to return.

The First is not only an intellect (‘aql), but in addition the highest intelligible (maqül), which means that It is both thought and object of thought at the same time. It is, first and foremost, an object of thought for Itself, which means that It is constantly engaged in the act of contemplating Its own essence. In the case of the First, however, this self-reflexivity does not lead to multiplicity, as thought and object of thought is one and the same thing. Not only is It the unique object of thought of its own contemplation, it also represents the highest and most universal intelligible for the other rational beings of al-Fârâbï’s cosmology, the thawânt, the celestial bodies, and, finally, human beings. In equating God and intellect or pure thought, al-Fârâbï is following a long Peripatetic tradition that has its starting point in Metaphysics 12.9.1074b.34-35. In this passage, Aristotle defines the First Unmoved Mover as “thought thinking thought,” a formula which the Second Teacher reproduces in Ára, thereby showing his adherence to this fun­damental Aristotelian tenet.[461]

In addition to being pure thought or intellect, the First is also described as the highest existent (mawjud) and as the cause of exist­ence (wujüd) in all the other beings. In conceiving of the highest divin­ity in such a way, al-Fârâbï departs from the Greek Neoplatonic tradition, which had placed the One above the concept of existence and all positive predication. On the other hand he seems to follow the Neoplatonica arabica, which describe the First as possessing existence (anniyyah) and as a cause of existence for the lower beings.[462] This would seem to imply that all the other entities, whether immaterial or material, and regardless of how far removed they are from the direct causation of the First, ultimately owe their own existence to It.

This picture, together with the notions of emanationism and the ‘commonality of being’ it implies, is nevertheless difficult to reconcile with other statements by al-Fârâbï. For unlike the Neoplatonica ara­bica, al-Fârâbï does not describe the First as ‘pure being’ (anniyyah faqat), but rather as a unique existent, “different in its substance from everything else,” whose special existence is not shared by any other entities.[463] In that sense, it should be stressed that the immaterial world of the intellectual entities is eternal and above time, which means that these entities have always existed and have always possessed their par­ticular and autonomous existence, even though they require a cause for their substance to be actualized and fully perfected. In addition, al-Fârâbï explains clearly that the First’s intellection gives rise to a sin­gle effect, and not to the entire universe, and that it is the other separate intellects that are responsible for causing the rest of the existents.

In view of this, al-Fârâbï’s occasional statements that the First is a cause of existence for all the other beings is highly ambiguous and may perhaps be construed as a concession to the religious creationist para­digm of his day. Alternatively, and more likely in my view, it represents a remnant of his early creationist phase, which was not fully reconciled with his mature theory of secondary causation. As a result, it stands awkwardly alongside his parallel account of the causation of the sepa­rate intellects, whose activity, together with the crucial issue of media­tion (tawassut), will be explored in depth in chapter 3.

At any rate, al-Fârâbï’s doctrine of the First appears to be grounded in, and a synthesis of, two main sources: Aristotle’s Metaphysics, Book Lambda 9, and the Neoplatonica arabica. It is the combination of these sources, which were in wide circulation in tenth-century Baghdad, which can best explain his particular view of the First as pure thought and as the highest existent and cause of existence. In the First, then, existence and thought is one and the same thing. Since It is nothing else but an immaterial intellect, its existence is identical to its thought, and it exists only in or through its thinking. This also helps to explain the particular way in which the First Cause induces existence in the first effect. Although al-Fârâbï is silent on this issue, one may conclude that its causation operates solely through its intellection. Since Its intel­lection is wholly unitary and simple, the First can only give rise to a single being, i.e., the first separate intellect.

Furthermore, al-Fârâbï insists repeatedly on the notions of divine oneness and unity (wahdah) and frequently asserts that God is one (wahid); in fact, God is the One (al-wahid). The underlying idea is that were the First Cause not a perfectly simple being, it would require a cause prior to it in existence to account for its compositeness and thus would not be the First. It is noteworthy that al-Fârâbï stresses two related yet distinct concepts with respect to God’s essence: first, God’s simplicity, that is, the idea that God’s essence is not in any way compos­ite, composed, or complex, but rather simple (basit); and second, God’s unicity and oneness, that is, the idea that another being as simple as God cannot exist alongside God.[464]

It is interesting to note that the conclusion regarding God’s oneness or unicity is deduced from the concept of divine simplicity. If, al-Fârâbï argues, another being is posited whose substance is like God’s, i.e., per­fectly simple, then both beings would be similar in one respect and different in another. As a result, a pre-existing cause would have to be posited to account for this differentia, which means that neither would be the First.[465] It is because God is the only being to have a perfectly simple essence that He does not require a cause and is prior to all other beings. As the only simple being, God is the First Cause of all things, whose substances are in contrast composite and thus deficient and derivative. The concepts of God’s simplicity and priority explain why, according to al-Fârâbï, there cannot be a definition of the First, since a definition requires a division of the subject’s substance.[466]

Intellection, existence, simplicity, and oneness are therefore the foundational concepts of al-Fârâbï’s theology. They are the most signif­icant positive and assertoric statements that can be made with regard to the First. In Ára and Siyasah, the Second Teacher enumerates many other qualities and attributes, such as justice, wisdom, knowledge, beauty, etc., which can be applied to God.[467] But al-Fârâbï is prompt to warn his readership that these terms do not refer to something distinct within, or apart from, the divine essence. While they apply to the First in a prior and primary way, they are inadequate to express Its true essence and can only be predicated of the First in a homonymous man­ner and in relation to things in this world.[468] Since some of these terms correspond to the divine attributes used in Islamic theology, there can be little doubt that al-Fârâbï is deliberately alluding to contemporary theological issues in these passages, and more specifically to the ques­tion of how God’s attributes relate to His essence. Indeed, this question had turned into a widespread debate by the time al-Fârâbï appeared on the scene, and it was one of the main causes of doctrinal division among the theologians of his time.[469]

Al-Fârâbï’s laconic style makes it particularly difficult to recon­struct his views regarding the question of God’s knowledge, which should nonetheless be addressed briefly. Again in this case, knowledge (’ilm) is not to be conceived of as something distinct from the First’s essence, but rather as being identical with Its thought and existence. But what is the First thinking about, and what does Its knowledge con­sist in? Unlike in the case of the celestial souls and intellects, al-Fârâbï does not elaborate on the objects of divine thought beyond the mere statement that the First thinks Its own essence and therefore that It is pure intellect (‘aql) and intelligible (maqül). Yet in Siyasah,he adds that

the First contemplates Itself, which, in a certain way, is all of the existents [al-mawjüdat kulluha]; for when It intellects Itself, It intellects, in a cer­tain way, all of the existents, because It is only out of Its existence that every other existent receives its existence.[470]

This tantalizing statement leaves ample room for speculation about al-Fârâbï’s position on this issue and raises more questions than it solves. To begin with, one wonders whether al-Fârâbï intended this statement literally, or whether it should not rather be construed as a concession made to the theologians and the traditionalists. Its tenor and phrasing at any rate could point in this direction. But assuming that al-Fârâbï sincerely intended this statement, other questions arise. Does the First apprehend universals only or also particular things? Are we to understand al-Fârâbï’s statement as referring to the presence of forms in the divine intellect, by which or through which the First knows all things? And how can the First be said to be absolutely simple, if It in a certain way comprises all things? Would not the very act of beholding different essences or particulars lead to multiplicity in the divine essence?

Needless to say, al-Fârâbï does not address these questions in detail in Siyasah or in his other extant works. But as ambiguous as it is, this statement could represent an important piece of evidence for his adher­ence to a particular doctrine of divine omniscience derived from the ancient commentatorial tradition. Indeed, some of the late antique phi­losophers had not only defined Aristotle’s God as pure thought, but also argued that the objects of His intellection consist of various intel­ligibles contained in the divine essence. One strategy was to apply to the Aristotelian God some of the (Neo-)Platonic doctrines on the forms and intellect, as exemplified by Ammonius, who seems to have located the forms in the divine intellect, a move which in turn helped him to argue in a treatise written to this effect that the Aristotelian God is also the efficient cause of the world.[471] Al-Farabi presumably knew at least excerpts from Ammonius’ treatise, as well as some of the late antique writings on Book Lambda 9, especially Themistius’ paraphrase and possibly Syrianus’ commentary, all of which were translated into Arabic. According to the remaining Arabic and Hebrew fragments of Themistius’ paraphrase, God contemplates the intelligibles contained in His essence and through them knows all things. As he writes: “And so it has become clear from the foregoing that God is the First Principle [al-mabda l-awwal] and that He knows His essence and all the things [jamt al-ashya] for which He is a cause.” And also: “The First Intellect [God] contemplates all the intelligibles together [jamt al-maqulat ma an] when It contemplates Its own essence.”[472] Hence, by existing as the First Cause of the entire universe and by encompassing all the forms of the things that come to be, the First would know all the effects that derive from Its essence, be they several times removed from It.[473]

It is possible that al-Farabi had Themistius’ paraphrase in mind when writing this passage of Siyasah and that he followed his Greek prede­cessor in including the universal intelligibles in the divine essence. Since its phrasing is ambiguous, one might even be tempted on the basis of this statement to extend the First’s knowledge to all the particu­lars of the sublunary world. Although Its knowledge of all effects is atemporal, since Its causality operates beyond time, the concatenation triggered by the First eventually enters the temporal realm and results in the historical events human beings are involved in. God would accordingly know the effects of past, present, and future events, which in contrast to the divine knowledge unfold linearly in historical time. This is the view articulated in some of al-Farabi’s other writings, such as Jam’ and K. al-‘ibarah, which describe explicitly God’s knowledge of particulars.[474] Alternatively, there is also the possibility that the First would know all the particulars “in a universal way” (‘ala nahw kullt), as Ibn Sïnâ would say.[475]

While possible, these readings of the Siyasah passage require an interpretive leap. Nowhere in his emanationist works does al-Fârâbï intimate that God’s knowledge of all effects qua First Cause includes knowledge of the transient, particular things of the sublunary world. Nor is there any support for the view that God knows particulars in a universal way, which seems idiosyncratic to Ibn Sïnâ. Moreover, one aphorism in Fusü l that addresses this question expressly seems to deci­sively reject the possibility of divine knowledge of particulars. In this passage, al-Fârâbï discusses three possible views concerning divine knowledge. The first one is that the First knows only Its essence (dhdtihi). This position obviously harks back to Aristotle’s comments in Metaphysics Book Lambda 9 on the self-reflexivity of divine thought. According to the second view, God knows “all universal intelligibles” (al-maqülat al-kulliyyah kullaha) instantly and through non-discur­sive thought (dafatan), a position indebted to Platonic and Neoplatonic theories on intellect and to the late antique commentatorial tradition on Book Lambda. Finally, the third view claims that God knows “all of the sense-perceptible particulars” (al-juziyyat al-mahsüsah kullaha).[476] Al-Fârâbï vehemently refutes this third option at the end of the apho­rism, which, although it is not stated, is clearly the one defended by most mutakallimün.

While this is straightforward, there are no other hints to help us decide which of the first two views al-Fârâbï adhered to. The second one can be compared to the key statement in Siyasah cited above, and it seems also to be the one implicitly upheld by Themistius in his paraphrase of Book Lambda 9. It could very well be, then, that al- Fârâbï believed that God’s knowledge encompasses the universal prin­ciples, such as the forms or mathematical axioms, which was the view defended by some Greek Neoplatonists in their attempt to provide a harmonizing account of Plato’s and Aristotle’s philosophies. However, even this restricted interpretation runs into difficulty, as al-Fârâbï does not make a cause’s knowledge of its effects a condition for the existence of these effects. For instance, he believes that neither the separate intel­lects nor the celestial souls are cognizant of the things that lie beneath them, although they are causes for the existence of these things. Hence, it would be surprising if the First was cognizant of what lies beneath It. Indeed, al-Fârâbï seems eager to remove the immaterial principles from any connection—be it purely cognitive—with their effects and with the beings situated below them in the cosmological hierarchy. Al-Fârâbï’s minimalist account of the intellection of the celestial souls and separate intellects seem to favour the first view exposed in Fusü l, i.e., that the First thinks only Its essence. This interpretation also seems supported by the fact that in his longest and most systematic account of the First, which can be found in Ara, al-Fârâbï says nothing concern­ing Its knowledge of other intelligibles apart from Itself, and he seems to faithfully follow Aristotle’s proposition of divine self-reflexivity.

But if this interpretation is correct, then it would raise a host of prob­lems, since al-Fârâbï, unlike Aristotle, clearly defines the First as an efficient cause. If the First’s thought is limited to Its own essence, and if It is supposed to cause the existence of other things through Its intel­lection and knowledge, then how can it cause something else to exist apart from Its own self? Although the problem of how multiplicity can arise from unity characterizes the entire Neoplatonic metaphysical program, it manifests itself in a particularly sharp form in al-Fârâbï’s philosophy, due to the purely intellectual nature of the First. It would seem that al-Fârâbï’s doctrine in this respect presents a real ambiguity, which may be encapsulated in the following dilemma: either a) the First knows all things, with the implication that whatever comes into exist­ence is an effect of Its contemplation and knowledge of that thing, or b) Its knowledge is restricted solely to Its own essence, in which case cau­sation of other existents would not be possible. Unfortunately, al-Fârâbï does not provide us with any satisfactory explanation of this problem. In the absence of further evidence, it seems unwise to put forth a defin­itive conclusion concerning al-Fârâbï’s views on divine knowledge.[477]

Putting this question aside, I wish to end this section with some remarks on how the First Cause fits in al-Fârâbï’s cosmological model, especially with regard to its relation to the orbs and its role in celestial motion. In Aristotle’s cosmology, the First Unmoved Mover is respon­sible for causing the motion of the outermost heaven, and in this respect it does not differ from the other unmoved movers whose task it is to move the lower orbs.[478] According to al-Fârâbï, in contrast, God is a universal mover and a final cause responsible for the motion of the entire heaven, while the outermost orb is moved directly by the first separate intellect. God moves the heavens as “the first object of love” (al-mahbüb al-awwal) and is the highest intelligible contemplated by the various celestial intellects.[479] In that sense, the First Cause is unlike the other intellects, which are each associated with one main orb and which act as a final cause for this orb specifically. The increased isola­tion of the First Cause and the introduction of an intermediary intel­lect between it and the first heaven are key features of al-Fârâbï’s cosmology. It marks a significant departure from Aristotle, and also argues in favour of a profound Neoplatonic influence on the Second Master. Indeed, the First Cause becomes more akin to the One of the Neoplatonists, especially since it causes a single, intellectual being in a way reminiscent of how the One causes the Intellectual Principle. Yet al-Fârâbï’s First also retains the kinematic function that Aristotle had ascribed to the unmoved movers, i.e., their capacity to move the heav­ens as final causes, thereby making his doctrine a subtle compromise between these two positions. All in all, then, al-Fârâbï’s theological doctrines regarding the essence, activity, and place of the First in his cosmology are similar to his other doctrines on soul and intellect in that they display a thorough and well-thought out combination of Aristotelian and Neoplatonic material, creatively reworked and recast in a new form.

4. Unity and Multiplicity

In the previous sections, I identified and analyzed the various corpo­real and incorporeal entities that make up al-Fârâbï’s cosmos. The First Cause, the separate intellects, and the celestial souls and bodies consti­tute the various classes of existents that constitute his superlunary ontology. This ontological continuum starts with the absolutely imma­terial and simple essence of the First and becomes increasingly affected by multiplicity and deficiency as one proceeds downward, until one reaches the celestial bodies and, below them, the realm of generating and corrupting bodies, the four basic elements, and, finally, prime mat­ter. What is more, the immaterial beings themselves are arranged in a hierarchical order depending on their relation vis-à-vis the First. The first separate intellect that inaugurates the series of thawdnt is purer and nobler than the other intellects due to its proximity to the First. It is the only being directly caused by the First and in that sense it occupies a special status in al-Fârâbï’s cosmology, although it does not possess for that matter any special function or activity that would be lacking in the other intellects. In turn, the celestial orbs are arranged hierarchically in a descending order depending on the nature of their cause and their degree of perfection, starting with the outermost orb and ending with the orb of the moon.

Approached from another angle, this ontological hierarchy can be reduced to three fundamental principles: intellect, soul, and matter or substrate. All existents according to al-Fârâbï consist of one or a com­bination of these principles. The immaterial realm is exclusively intel­lectual, and at this level existence can only be of an intellective or contemplative kind. The lower level of soul appears first with the celes­tial souls, although al-Fârâbï’s position in this regard is somewhat idi­osyncratic in that he defines these souls exclusively as intellects devoid of the other psychological faculties. Like the thawdnt, these celestial souls are also characterized by thought, albeit of a less unitary kind than the one existing in the immaterial realm. Finally, below intellect and soul lies matter, which participates in the substance of the sublu­nary beings. Al-Fârâbï neatly summarizes this three-fold cosmological structure when he states in Fusü l that “there are three worlds: spiritual, celestial, and material,” by which he means the world of intellect, of soul, and of body or matter.[480]

The subsumption of all immaterial and material existents on three basic levels, corresponding to the three principles of intellect, soul, and body or matter, vividly brings to mind the metaphysics of the late antique Neoplatonists. The Neoplatonists, like al-Fârâbï, also organized these principles in a hierarchical scheme, with intellect producing soul, and soul in turn producing nature and inaugurating the corporeal realm. There can be little doubt that al-Fârâbï was influenced by this tradition when he composed his mature philosophical works, such as Fusül, Ára, and Siyasah, which define intellect, soul, and matter as dis­tinct principles (mabâdï) organized in a hierarchical pattern.[481] The previous sections showed the ubiquitous influence of the Neoplatonica arabica on al-Fârâbï’s theories of celestial psychology, and so it is only natural to presume that he would have derived this tripartite division of the cosmos from this corpus as well.

It is likely that al-Fârâbï used this framework to construe Aristotle’s cosmology in Book Lambda, especially with respect to the celestial souls, which are not explicitly formulated in this Aristotelian work. Accordingly, the Neoplatonic theory of Intellect can be made to corre­spond to the unmoved movers, that of Soul to the celestial souls, and Nature to the realm of corporeality beginning with the orbs, but apply­ing primarily to the sublunary world. A hint that al-Fârâbï construed Aristotle’s cosmology in such a manner appears in Falsafat Aristii ta lïs, when he explains that the Stagirite had to inquire into the celestial sub­stance and decide whether it is a “nature, a soul, or an intellect.”[482] The phrasing of this statement not only betrays the tripartite division derived from Neoplatonism mentioned above, but in addition suggests that al-Fârâbï thought that Aristotle himself organized these very prin­ciples in this hierarchical fashion in his cosmology. The attribution of many texts from the Neoplatonica arabica to Aristotle in the Arabic tradition can help to explain why al-Fârâbï spontaneously interpreted the cosmology of the Stagirite through the tripartite division of intel­lect, soul, and matter articulated in these works.

Yet in spite of this apparent attempt at harmonization, al-Fârâbï’s basic metaphysical framework remains primarily indebted to the Sta­girite. This appears clearly in the fact that he, unlike most Neoplatonists, does not uphold a theory of a universal or hypostatic intellect and soul that subsequently becomes individuated in particular entities. This observation applies particularly to the concept of soul, which for the Neoplatonists is responsible for generating the world of nature or mat­ter. In contrast to the Neoplatonists, al-Fârâbï makes intellect the direct cause of the existence of the celestial bodies (al-ajsam al-samawiyyah), thus bypassing the role traditionally ascribed to soul in Neoplatonic cosmology. The idea to connect matter, whether heavenly or sublu­nary, directly with intellect is foreign to most Neoplatonic systems. In this case, it can best be explained by al-Fârâbï’s particular exegetical approach, which consisted in integrating Neoplatonic theories on intel­lection and demiurgy into a fundamentally Aristotelian cosmological framework, which establishes a direct relation between the unmoved movers and the celestial orbs. Fundamentally, then, al-Fârâbï engaged in the daunting task of harmonizing theories derived from two differ­ent metaphysical and cosmological systems, which he found in the Aristotelian texts and the Neoplatonica arabica. The idea of an inherent compatibility between these systems was surely suggested to him by some of the late antique commentaries and works that he read, but it adopted a particular form in his case, due to the central place occupied by Book Lambda in his cosmology.[483]

Al-Fârâbï closely follows the Neoplatonists on another important point, namely, the relation between causation, unity, and multiplicity. A detailed analysis of his terminology of superlunary causation will be given in chapter 3, but at this stage it seems worthwhile to sketch a basic picture of al-Fârâbï’s causative model and of how it underlies the hierarchical structure of his cosmology.[484] According to the Second Teacher, each entity—whether an intellect, a celestial soul, or an orb— is caused by a higher principle, except for the First, which does not have a prior cause and is completely autonomous. According to this theory, the celestial bodies and souls are caused by the separate intel­lects, while each separate intellect is itself caused either by another and prior separate intellect or by the First Itself in the case of the first sepa­rate intellect (i.e., the first of the thawânt). These causal relations are not to be conceived of as subsisting in a temporal sphere, since time only appears with the motion of the celestial bodies. Rather, causation in the immaterial realm rests on the essential priority of the cause over the effect, which also implies the greater unity and simplicity of the former over the latter.

Al-Fârâbï regards causality as an outcome of the intellective activity in which the souls and intellects are engaged. As we saw earlier, intel­lection or contemplation (taaqqul) is the main activity of the First Cause, the thawânt, and the celestial souls, and it is as a result of their particular mode of intellection that they cause the existence of other specific entities. More precisely, according to al-Fârâbï, causation can issue either from self-intellection or self-reflexivity, that is, from an entity’s contemplation of its own essence, or from the intellection of other, exterior, and higher principles. The celestial souls and separate intellects are characterized by this dual introspective and extrospective activity, and it is the multiplicity of their intelligibles that produces a multiplicity of effects. In contrast, in the case of the First, intellection is self-contained and self-reflexive, with a perfect identity of thinker and thought, which means that causation proceeds solely from the First’s contemplation of Itself and can result only in a single effect. Finally, and to complete this picture, there can be little doubt that al-Fârâbï con­ceived of this causality as an efficient one, responsible for the existence and sustenance of the various entities of his cosmology (see further ch. 3, 2.6.1-2.). In tying efficient causality to the intellective activity of the immaterial entities, and more specifically to their self-reflexivity, al-Fârâbï is following a well-established, yet highly diversified, Neoplatonic trend, which found its main formulations in Plotinus and later in Proclus.[485]

But what is the connection between causation, unity, and multiplic­ity? Since the degree of unity or multiplicity that is attached to the superlunary entities differs and corresponds to their variegated modes of contemplation, it is only normal that the nature of their effects would differ as well as a result of this. In other words, the kind of intellection that characterizes a cause also characterizes the number and nature of its effects. Thus, the perfectly unitary intellection of the First leads to a single effect, while the fragmentary intellection of the thawânt and celestial souls leads to a progressively greater degree of multiplicity in their respective effects.

This explains why, according to the causal hierarchy that underlies al-Fârâbï’s entire cosmology, causes are always simpler than their effects, or, put differently, effects are affected by a greater degree of mul­tiplicity than the source from which they proceed. If we invoke the tripartite structure discussed above and apply it to al-Fârâbï’s cosmol­ogy, then this implies that the separate intellects, which are the causes of the celestial souls and bodies, are simpler than these entities, while the celestial souls, which are causes for the phenomena occurring in the sublunary world, are themselves simpler than their sublunary effects. As for the First or God, according to this reasoning, It must be simpler than its single effect, the first separate intellect.[486] As we saw in the previous section, al-Fârâbï describes It as being absolutely one (wahid) and simple (basit) and stresses that It is not affected by multi­plicity in any way. Its perfectly simple essence thus stands in opposition to matter’s absolute potentiality to receive contrary forms. One of the corollaries of this theory is that every effect possesses some degree of multiplicity, regardless of its status in the hierarchy of being.

The notion of multiplicity, which al-Fârâbï expresses by means of the Arabic term kathrah, is, however, not to be construed in the same way when applied to these various effects. In the case of the intellectual beings, since they are immaterial, they cannot be composed of various parts or elements. Consequently, their multiplicity does not consist in any kind of composition or compositeness (tarklb), but rather in a kind of complexity in their essence. This is due to the special mode of their intellection, which is divided into two objects of thought, the First Cause and their own essence, and it is this duality that constitutes their kathrah.[487] In the case of the celestial bodies, in contrast, the notion of multiplicity can refer to composition and complexity, as they possess both a corporeal substance and a rational soul engaged in contempla­tion. First, the celestial bodies are “composed” (murakkab) of the two principles of soul (nafs) and substrate (mawdü‘).[488] Second, the celestial souls themselves are complex, due to their three-fold intellection, which apprehends the First, a higher intellect, and their own essence. Finally, the sublunary bodies are affected by multiplicity due to their basic hylomorphic composition, which in turn can be divided further into various elemental combinations constituted by the four elements of fire, air, water, and earth. Multiplicity in this case is associated with matter and thus with the potentiality inherent in material beings to acquire many contrary forms.

Hence, al-Fârâbï’s concept of multiplicity (kathrah) can be construed either in terms of composition (tarkib) in the case of bodies or in terms of complexity (also called kathrah) in the case of intellectual entities. In the former case, multiplicity is associated with matter or substrate, while in the latter case it has to do with an imperfect and not wholly unitary kind of intellection. Although al-Fârâbï uses the same term kathrah to express both concepts, it is clear that a distinction should be made between the two. Since he associates both kinds of multiplicity with division (inqisam) and deficiency (naqs),[489] this theory defines the First Cause as the only entity that is not in any way composed, com­plex, divisible, and deficient. In other words, the First does not suffer from any kind of multiplicity, either with respect to Its essence or Its intellection. But as one proceeds downward, one encounters an increas­ing degree of multiplicity and heterogeneity, until one reaches the sub­lunary world characterized by the absolute receptivity and potentiality of matter. In this manner a correlation is established between the degree of simplicity of a cause and the nature of its effect: a complex cause will necessarily emit an even more complex effect.[490]

In parallel to the relation between causality and multiplicity and the idea that all existents apart from the First are affected by multiplicity and deficiency, al-Fârâbï also holds that all existents are characterized by a certain unity or oneness (wahdah), which is a necessary property of their existence. For al-Fârâbï, existence and unity are applicable to all things, from the sublunary, material existents to the separate intellects and the First Cause. As al-Fârâbï writes, “one of the meanings of unity [al-wahdah] is the proper existence [al-wujüd al-khass] by which every existent is distinguished from another, and it is by virtue of this that every existent is called ‘one.’ ”[491] According to this statement, unity is essentially attached to existence, with the implication that every exist­ent also possesses a certain ‘unity of existence.’

But this concept manifests itself in various degrees in al-Fârâbï’s cos­mology. The higher one ascends the ontological ladder, the more per­fectly and authentically the concept of unity will be embodied, until one reaches the First Cause, in which pure existence and perfect unity are identical.[492] As al-Fârâbï explains in his work K. al-wahid wa-l- wahdah (On the one and oneness), unity can be predicated of the existents in various ways: according to species (naw‘) or genus (jins), to number (bi-l-‘adad), to what is composite (mutalif) and subject to division (inqisam), to essence (bi-mdhiyyatiht), etc. For instance, he explains that composite beings still possess a certain unity, in spite of their composition (ta’ltf), which is expressed by the totality formed by their various parts, and he gives the example of the ship (safmah) to illustrate this.[493] This remark applies to all composite and hylomorphic beings, but what about the immaterial beings, which do not suffer from composition? In their case, as al-Fârâbï explains, unity refers to their very essence (mdhiyyah).[494] But this concept is not restricted to the immaterial beings and can be applied to all entities, “whether divisible or indivisible, whether conceived of by the soul or lying outside the soul,” and it is moreover closely connected with the concept of exist­ence (wujüd).23 Hence, not only are there different degrees of oneness, but this concept also applies to things in various ways.

In spite of this, it is presumably this last type of essential oneness that al-Fârâbï has in mind when he asserts that the concept of unity, like that of existence, has its starting point in the divine essence.[495] [496] God is not only the First, al-awwal, that is, the existent that is essentially prior to all the other existents, but He is in addition one and unique, wdhid, meaning that no other being possesses His perfectly simple and uni­tary essence and existence. In Him, unity and existence can be found to their utmost degree. This point is conveyed clearly and elegantly when al-Fârâbï writes: “Its [i.e., the First’s] distinction from everything else is through a unity that is its being [or essence, bi-wahdatin hiya dhâtuhü][497] It should be noted that this concept of unity can be applied both to the divine existence and intellection, which is one and the same thing in God, although they represent alternative ways of describing His essence.

This conjunction of existence and unity also helps to explain the bond between all things, since each entity derives these qualities from its cause, and this cause from a previous cause, a series which ultimately originates with the First. This means that effects are similar to their causes in that, like them, they possess existence and unity, albeit to a different degree and in a different mode, which is appropriate to their status in the cosmic hierarchy. This idea of a genuine similarity between cause and effect can be further applied to al-Fârâbï’s metaphysics with respect to the concept of intellect. In causing the first separate intellect, the First also in a sense reproduces a likeness of itself, since both the cause and the effect are immaterial, intellectual, and possess a high, but not identical, degree of unity. Like the First, the thawdnt are engaged in self-intellection, and in that sense their activity imitates that of the First. Finally, the thawdnt cause the celestial souls and bodies through their self-reflexivity, thus echoing the causative act of the First. This in turn explains why the celestial souls are, according to al-Fârâbï, primarily defined by their intellectual nature, since they share to some degree in the essence of their cause. The intellectual principle is thus conveyed from the level of the First to the separate intellects, then fur­ther to the level of the celestial souls and finally to the human rational souls, although it decreases in purity with every level. In each case, the effect resembles its cause and participates to some extent in a similar nature, thus ensuring both the primacy of intellect in al-Farabi’s cos­mology and the essential similarity between each class of cosmic existents.[498]

So far, the discussion has focused on the connection between intel­lection and causation and what this implies in terms of the multiplicity of being; this is the procession or downward motion away from the First, expressed through the concept of efficient causality and the cor­ollary notion of deficiency (naqs). However, of equal importance is the reversion or upward motion back toward the First, which is also expressed through the concept of intellection, and which is connected this time with final causality. While intellection is the act that necessar­ily leads to the production of similar, albeit inferior, effects by a given entity, it is also what enables the cosmic existents to actualize their essence and to seek the attainment of their perfection by reverting toward the prior principles. This search for perfection can be explained by a desire for greater unity, a striving to increase one’s essential close­ness to one’s cause, although here as well it manifests itself differently depending on the class of beings examined. In the case of the orbs and planets, their souls inhere in a substrate that prevents them from acquiring the perfections of the immaterial existents and that can only be actualized through motion. Consequently, they possess according to al-Fârâbï the highest corporeal perfections, including circular motion, which in a sense reproduces at a corporeal level the circularity associ­ated with self-reflexivity. In the case of the thawânt, their contempla­tion of the First and their striving to imitate Its perfect existence and absolute unity is sufficient to actualize their substance to its utmost degree, although they too fall short of acquiring the absolute unity and perfection of the First.[499]

At this point, one clearly perceives the complementarity and partial overlap between efficient and final causality in al-Fârâbï’s cosmology. Both are grounded in the concept of intellection, and, more specifi­cally, in the contemplative act that accompanies the reversion toward the prior principles. According to al-Fârâbï, the causation of other beings by the intellects, i.e., their activity as efficient causes, necessarily occurs as a result of their turning backward toward their cause and inward toward their own essence, and in no sense can it be associated with a motion or intention directed downward toward the lower existents. As we have seen previously, al-Fârâbï denies that the separate intellects and celestial souls know what lies beneath them, which means that efficient causation is not defined in terms of the providence or care that the celestial beings have for their effects. Rather, the contem­plation of these entities is turned either toward itself, in an act of self­reflexivity, or toward the higher principles, on which they depend and which they strive to imitate. Hence, it is the very act of return or rever­sion of the souls and intellects toward their source that leads to their producing lower effects.

In that sense, efficient causation may be regarded as the corollary of the intellective act of reversion of the souls and intellects, as well as a by-product of it. For this reason, it is tempting to conclude that final causality enjoys primacy in al-Fârâbï’s cosmology, to the extent that the proposition was recently made to eliminate efficient causality entirely from his system.[500] At any rate, it seems more accurate to con­clude that in al-Fârâbï’s view, both types of causality are closely con­nected to one another as well as to the concepts of unity and multiplicity. The results of the foregoing discussion may be represented schemati­cally as follows:

 

Figure 4. Al-Fârâbï’s cosmological hierarchy

In conclusion, one observes that al-Fârâbï’s cosmology embodies to a high degree several fundamental Neoplatonic postulates. First, causa­tion and the production of lower existents are to be regarded as a logi­cal outcome of the (self-) intellection of the cosmic entities; intellection is thus intrinsically demiurgic (ch. 3, 2.6.2.). Second, the intellection of the intellects and souls results in a causality that is characterized by a dual orientation: a downward one (efficient causality), and an upward one (final causality), which is used to explain both the existence of the celestial entities and the perfectibility of their existence respectively. Third, causes are always simpler than their effects, a theory that gradu­ally leads from unity to multiplicity. Fourth, there is a similarity between causes and their effects, thus accounting for the diffusion of existence, unity, and the intellectual principle throughout the cosmos and rein­forcing the ontological continuum that has its point of origin in the First.

5. Conclusion

The structure of al-Fârâbï’s cosmology is original and unprecedented in the early Arabic philosophical tradition. It emerged out of a complex process of exegesis, assimilation, and transformation of the Greek sources. The previous analysis elaborated on past scholarly contribu­tions by examining some of the key works underlying al-Fârâbï’s theo­ries and by reconstructing his interpretation of specific cosmological questions addressed in these texts. In addition to confirming the impor­tance of Aristotle’s Metaphysics and Alexander’s Mabâdï, already stressed by Maróth and others, the study highlighted al-Fârâbï’s debt to the Proclus arabus and also introduced new sources into the discus­sion, such as Quaestiones attributed to Alexander, Ptolemy’s Planetary Hypotheses, and Simplicius’ commentary on On the Heavens. The anal­ysis showed that al-Fârâbï did not merely reproduce or slavishly copy the contents of these works, but critically selected and adapted their

causality represent two sides of the same coin, depending on whether the procession away from, or the reversion toward, the First is emphasized. This was the view adopted by many Neoplatonist commentators on Aristotle, and it seems to be al-Fârâbï’s posi­tion as well. For a general treatment of efficient and final causality and their interrela­tion in ancient philosophy, see Rosemann (1996, ch. 1 and 2, 33-103); and for a discussion of this subject in the works of Ibn Sïnâ, see Wisnovsky (2002 and 2003, 183-195).

theories to develop an original cosmological model. In doing so, he achieved a remarkable synthesis of various philosophical and astro­nomical theories, whose meaning and function in his cosmology are largely defined by the new structural relations that connect them.

Perhaps the most outstanding structural feature of al-Fârâbï’s cos­mology is the introduction of a level of separate intellects between the First and the corporeal world, which marks an important metaphysical shift in early Arabic philosophy and redefines the relation between the divine world and matter. Equally striking is the manner in which he describes the nature and function of these intellects. By focusing on the questions of the nature, number, and activity of the unmoved movers, the analysis showed that al-Fârâbï’s cosmological project consisted to a large extent in an original interpretation of Book Lambda in light of the Proclus arabus. It was argued that al-Fârâbï significantly elaborated on this Aristotelian tenet by relying on some of the late antique commen­taries and the Neoplatonica arabica, which enabled him to integrate Neoplatonic ideas on causation and intellection into a cosmological framework that combines Aristotelian physical and metaphysical theo­ries with Ptolemy’s planetary models.

In his treatment of the activity of the celestial souls and intellects, and in his theorizing of the key concepts underlying his metaphysical and cosmological thought—unity and multiplicity, intellection and causation, efficient and final causality—al-Fârâbï is inscribed in an ongoing intellectual tradition that has its roots in the late antique phil­osophical worldview. His cosmology may rightly be regarded as an extension of the philosophical project begun centuries earlier with the ‘Ammonian synthesis,’ which has been thoroughly described by R. Wisnovsky with respect to Ibn Sïnâ’s cosmology. The next chapter will largely confirm this view and will try in addition to open other perspectives for interpreting al-Fârâbï’s development as a philosopher.


CHAPTER THREE

MATTER AND CREATION: A SHIFT IN PARADIGMS?

The two previous chapters have shed light on al-Fârâbï’s method, on the structure of his cosmology, and on his interpretive approach to the ancient philosophical and astronomical texts. This chapter intends to examine the last point in more depth, by providing a case study of al-Fârâbï’s views on the nature and origin of celestial matter. Celestial matter was a central concept in ancient and medieval cosmology, espe­cially due to its significance in the debate concerning the creation or eternity of the world. Given al-Fârâbï’s place in the history of Arabic cosmology, his views on the subject deserve to be accurately examined. How did al-Fârâbï construe Aristotle’s theory of aether? What place does celestial matter occupy in his cosmology? What is the relation between al-Fârâbï’s theories of matter and his views on creation? Did his theories change over the course of his life, and, if so, for what rea­sons? These questions will inform the following discussion and provide a background for the subsequent analysis of al-Fârâbï’s views on crea­tion and causation.

1. The Nature of Celestial Matter

The purpose of this first section is to investigate al-Fârâbï’s views on the nature and composition of celestial matter, a key issue discussed at length by the ancient commentators. These discussions appear chiefly in works on natural philosophy, such as commentaries on Aristotle’s On the Heavens, but also occasionally in a metaphysical and astronom­ical context. The following analysis will attempt to reconstruct al-Fârâbï’s views on the subject by relying on the scattered evidence that can be collected from his corpus, as well as on the reports of later thinkers.

1.1.    Al-Fârâbïs Hylic Terminology

In various parts of his works al-Fârâbï emphasizes the difficulty of elaborating a philosophical terminology that would be devoid of ambi­guity and obscurity. Being aware of the long history of philosophy before Islam, and endorsing an empirical model for its development, he acknowledged the risks inherent in the project of transferring and translating philosophical terms and notions from one culture to another. Al-Farabi’s general outlook in this regard also applies to the hylic terminology he inherited from the Greek to Arabic translation movement. Indeed, he seems to have been particularly troubled by the proper translations and transliterations of the Greek terms referring to matter. In contrast, his predecessor al-Kindi was much less critical on this point. While he frequently relies on the transliterated term hayüla to render the Greek nXq, al-Kindi’s Risalah ft hudüd al-ashya includes entries for other hylic terms such as Unsur and ttnah, whose exact meaning is difficult to establish despite the definitions provided.[501]

In contrast to al-Kindi, al-Farabi shows a keen awareness of the semantic nuances of Arabic terms expressing matter. In Hurüf, he explains that ‘unsur may mean both ‘element’ and ‘matter’ and should therefore be avoided because of its ambiguity.[502] Al-Farabi’s omission of ‘unsur in his works is notable and can be explained—in addition to the perceived ambiguity of this term—by the fact that it became associated with the concept of intelligible matter in the Pseudo-Empedoclean tradition and in the early Arabic doxographies.[503]

Al-Farabi’s personal preference goes to the two terms hayülâ and maddah (pl. mawadd), although the latter term is by far the most com­mon in his works.[504] It is notable that the same word (maddah) is used by al-Fârâbï in some of his treatises to describe both sublunary matter and the special celestial matter.[505] This terminological overlap leads to the important observation that al-Fârâbï does not have a special word to refer to celestial matter exclusively. Indeed, the Second Teacher shuns the terms ‘aether’ (athir), ‘first substance’ (al-jawhar al-awwal), and ‘fifth nature’ (al-tabiah al-khamisah) that appear in early Arabic philo­sophical works. These terms had become associated with Aristotle’s doctrine of aether and with the Peripatetic tradition on On the Heavens.[506]

The complete omission of the traditional Peripatetic hylic terminol­ogy in al-Fârâbï’s corpus need not indicate that he rejected the theory of aether. However, it definitely raises the possibility that he substan­tially transformed Aristotle’s doctrine, especially when it is combined with independent doctrinal evidence drawn from his treatises.[507] If one approaches al-Fârâbï’s cosmology with the assumption that it is merely a replica of Aristotle’s, then this terminological omission proves diffi­cult to explain. Conversely, if one hypothesizes that al-Fârâbï creatively transformed the theories that reached him, then the omission of this terminology may point to a redefinition of celestial matter in al-Fârâbï’s cosmology. Keeping this in mind, I wish to turn to the evidence con­cerning al-Fârâbï’s views on celestial substance in his corpus.

1.2.    A Survey of Celestial Matter in al-Fârâbï’s Philosophy

1.2.1. The Fârâbïan Corpus

Ihsâ ’ « «

Al-Fârâbï states in Ihsâ ’ that the second part of the physical science studies simple substances, whether they exist, how many they are, and other such questions. According to al-Fârâbï, the term “simple bodies” (ajsâm basïtah) encompasses not only the four sublunary elements fire, air, water, and earth, but also the matter of the heavens, which in the Peripatetic tradition is considered a fifth element. As al-Fârâbï explains, physics studies “the heavens and its various parts as being made of a certain one matter [mâddah mâ fïhâ wâhidah]” The inclusion of the celestial substance in the physical inquiry is in line with the On the Heavens tradition of late antiquity, which al-Fârâbï here follows. In fact, he refers explicitly in this same passage to Book 1 of Aristotle’s work. The use of the term mâddah to signify celestial matter in this passage of Ihsâ’ is notable, because it is one of the very rare instances in the Fârâbïan corpus where it is applied to the superlunary world and where al-Fârâbï refers unambiguously to the heavens as being material. In this particular case, it can be explained by the fact that he is using Aristotle’s On the Heavens as a model for his discussion of celestial physics.

Falsafat Aristütâlïs

This work, which purports to provide an overview of Aristotle’s philosophy, contains information about al-Fârâbï’s understanding of Aristotle’s aether theory. Al-Fârâbï writes that

he [Aristotle] explained that there are five primary simple bodies [al-ajsâm al-basïtah al-uwal] that constitute the world. ... One of them is the outermost body that moves in a circular motion: the remaining four have common matter but are different in their forms: the fifth [aether] differs from these four in both its matter [mâddatihï] and its form [süratihï], and is the cause [sabab] of the existence of these four.[508] [509]

Although this might seem like a faithful exposition of Aristotle’s theory of the elements, there are a few notable points that particularize al-Fârâbï’s summary and signal a departure from Aristotle. First, al-Fârâbï attributes to Aristotle the view that the heavenly bodies are composite. According to this account, aether possesses a different “form” and a different “matter” from the ones constituting the sublu­nary elements. This is slightly surprising, since Aristotle does not spec­ify anywhere in his works that aether is a compound of form and matter, and he describes the fifth element as a simple and homogeneous body. Al-Fârâbï’s wording here can perhaps be explained in terms of the influence of the ancient commentators, who often debated about whether or not the heavenly bodies are simple substances. In any case, aether is defined in this passage as a hylomorphic substance. Second, the idea that aether is the “cause” (sabab) of the other sublunary ele­ments also appears as an addition to the original Aristotelian doctrine.[510] True, Aristotle in On Generation 2.10 explains that the sun plays an important role in causing the generation and corruption of sublunary bodies, but he does not explicitly make the heavens the cause for the existence of the sublunary elements and sublunary matter. Hence, this passage does not merely summarize Aristotle’s ideas but also betrays a subtle transformation of the Aristotelian doctrine.

Radd

This treatise offers interesting, but ambiguous information about al-Fârâbï’s interpretation of the aether theory. The context is a defense of Aristotle’s cosmology against Philoponus’ attack. Philoponus had criticized Aristotle’s aether theory in order to undermine his doctrine of the eternity of the world. Al-Fârâbï retorts in this treatise that Aristotle’s intention was not to prove the eternity of the world, but merely to explain the difference between aether and the other four ele­ments. At one point in the treatise al-Fârâbï writes:

Thus, by some of those statements, Aristotle explained that the form [surah] of that part of the world which is the body that moves with a circular movement is not the same as the form of any other part of the world. By others it becomes evident that not even its matter [maddah] is the same as the matter of [any other part of the world]. And by [still] oth­ers it becomes evident that its matter is not the same as the matter of anything at all of the bodies in general, whether parts of the world or a body whose position is outside of these.[511]

In this passage al-Fârâbï explicitly refers to some well-known Aristotelian theses: that the heavens are made of a unique element that is different from the sublunary elements, and that the heavens move in a circular motion. What is more surprising here is al-Fârâbï’s mention, as in Falsafat Aristu ta lis, of both the form (su rah) and matter (maddah) of the heavens, which implies their hylomorphic composition, and which would seem to go against the notion of the perfect simplicity of aether. But in spite of this minor doctrinal modification, one may safely conclude that al-Fârâbï is not only defending Aristotle’s cosmology against the attacks of the Christian philosopher-theologian, but that he himself adhered to the aether theory or a variant of it. Hence, Ihsa ’, Falsafat Aristü ta lis, and Radd ascribe matter (maddah) to the heavens and endorse Aristotle’s theory of aether as it is discussed in On the Heavens, sometimes mentioning this work by its title. In these three texts, al-Fârâbï exposes and, one assumes, endorses this vital feature of Aristotelian cosmology.

Ara’ and Siyasah

A very different theory of celestial matter is articulated in some of al-Fârâbï’s other treatises, especially Ara’ and Siyasah. In Ara’, al-Fârâbï writes that the celestial bodies possess a soul (nafs) that can be com­pared to form (surah), as well as a substrate (mawdu) in which this soul-form inheres. Although these celestial substrates can be compared to the material substrates of sublunary beings, they are not truly mate­rial, but rather resemble matter. As al-Fârâbï puts it, the celestial bodies “have substrates that resemble [tushbihu] the matters laid down to bear the forms [al-mawadd al-mawduah li-haml al-suwar]”[512] Unlike the sublunary material substrates, however, which can receive many con­trary forms, the celestial substrates can receive only one unique form and, hence, do not suffer from the contrariety associated with matter, i.e., change and corruption. This unique soul-form is different in each celestial body and is essentially an intellect (aql), in spite of the fact that it inheres in a substrate.[513]

One finds a similar but more pronounced trend in Siyasah. Having explained at the beginning of this treatise that form and matter are among the six principles of existents and that they are in bodies but are not themselves bodies,[514] one would expect al-Fârâbï to apply these principles to the orbs and planets, since these are after all bodies (ajsam). But as in Ára, al-Fârâbï employs analogical language or a lan­guage of similarity to argue that the heavenly bodies with their soul and substrate merely “resemble the substances composed of matter and form” (tushbihu l-jawahir al-murakkabah min maddah wa-min surah)}[515] However, al-Fârâbï plainly asserts that “their [heavenly] substrates are not material (or are not matters)” (ghayra anna mawduataha laysat mawadd) and that they are free from any aspect of deficiency that is in sublunary matter.[516] In addition, he also repeats the argument of Ára that the heavenly substrates can only receive one form and that this form is a soul.

The terms “matter” (maddah) and “substrate” (mawdu) are fre­quently encountered in al-Fârâbï’s physics and were part and parcel of the technical philosophical vocabulary of his day. Al-Fârâbï follows the Peripatetic tradition according to which sublunary beings are a com­pound of matter and form. Matter is defined as a substrate that receives form, each principle being unable to subsist without the other. In Ára al-Fârâbï explains these principles by citing the stock example of the wooden bed: matter is the wood of the bed, form its shape. He then writes: “Matter, then, serves as substratum for the subsistence of form,”[517] meaning that the form of the bed inheres in its matter. Both form and matter make up a compound and as such are distinguishable one from the other only conceptually.

In the case of the heavens, however, the relation between form and substrate is not the same as in sublunary physics. Al-Fârâbï does not explicitly ascribe matter to the celestial bodies and consistently uses the term mawdu instead of maddah. He resorts to analogical language to compare the celestial and sublunary substrates, noting that the celestial substrates “resemble” the sublunary matters (mawadd) in their capac­ity to receive form. But the analogy between heavenly and sublunary substrates ends here, for besides this capacity to receive form, the two types of substrates have nothing else in common. The sublunary sub­strates are material precisely by virtue of their capacity to receive differ­ent and contrary forms. As al-Fârâbï writes, “what has a contrary has a matter common to it and to its contrary”[518] Contrariety and potency affect sublunary substrates, but the celestial substrates are affected by neither. Because the heavenly bodies do not accept contrary forms, they cannot be made of the same potential matter that composes sublu­nary beings. Moreover, the form of the heavenly body is also essentially different from that of sublunary beings, since in the case of the former it is unique and is a rational soul, whereas in the case of the latter it may be replaced by other contrary forms.

Al-Fârâbï’s insistence on ascribing substrate, but not matter, to the celestial bodies becomes easier to understand when one realizes that he consistently distinguishes these two concepts in his philosophy. For example, when discussing the essence of God, al-Fârâbï explains that “[God’s] existence is devoid of every matter and every substrate [bal wujüduhü khalwun min kull maddah wa-min kull mawdu].”[519] Al-Fârâbï reiterates this distinction in another passage: the heavenly body “is distinct from the First and from the ten ‘separate’ intellects, which are free from matter and any substrate [yufariqu l-awwal wa-l- ‘asharah al-mutakhallisah min al-hayüla wa-min kull mawdü‘]”[520]° Even in the sublunary world, where substrate and matter are closely related and seem virtually interchangeable, the two concepts are not identi­cal. In Ft l-‘aql, al-Fârâbï states that substrates can be “either bodies [i.e., matter] or powers in bodies [wa-zahir anna l-mawdüat ... imma ajsam wa-imma quwanft ajsdm]”[521]

Hence, as these citations clearly show, al-Fârâbï distinguishes sub­strate from matter and considers the former to be conceptually broader than the latter: matter is always a substrate for other things, but not all substrates are material. This means that, although the Second Teacher is willing to ascribe substrate to the celestial bodies, it should not be inferred that this substrate is material in nature. While this idea is only

implicitly suggested in Ára, it is more clearly articulated in Siyasah, which emphasizes that the heavenly substrates are immaterial.[522] The two treatises conspicuously rely on analogical language to express this particular point. All in all, the style and ideas developed in these two works are strikingly close in spirit and suggest that they were written during the same period.

1.2.2.    Later Reports

Al-Ghazâlï’s Tahafut al-falasifah

It has often been noted that Tahafut is a valuable work not only for the arguments it contains, but also for the information it provides concerning the doctrines of the falasifah. Among other subjects, this work addresses cosmological issues, especially the question of the creation or eternity of the world. It is on this point in particular that al-Ghazâlï intends to refute what he considers to be the heretical and misinformed views of the philosophers. One passage is relevant to the subject under discussion. Al-Ghazâlï finds fault with the falâsifah’s belief that the heavenly orbs are hylomorphic and composed of form (surah) and matter (hayula), and that these are caused to exist by a single immaterial intellect. According to al-Ghazâlï, the falasifah fail to explain adequately how these principles can be caused by the separate intellects, which are by essence simple and thus cannot pro­vide multiple effects.[523] This point is one of many that are used to build an overarching argument against the falâsifah’s theory of eternal causality.

Now, al-Ghazâlï states at the beginning of the Tahafut that he will limit his refutation to the theories of al-Fârâbï and Ibn Sïnâ: “the most reliable transmitters and verifiers among the philosophers in Islam are al-Fârâbï Abû Nasr and Ibn Sïnâ. Let us then confine ourselves in refut­ing what these two have selected and deemed true of the doctrines of their leaders in error.”[524] Yet, we have seen that unlike Ibn Sïnâ, al-Fârâbï does not hold a standard hylomorphic view on the celestial substance, and he substitutes immaterial substrate for matter in his emanationist works. Moreover, al-Ghazâlï describes a threefold mode of intellection to explain the causation of the orbs, which was developed by Ibn Sina, not al-Farabi, who endows the separate intellects with twofold intellec­tion only. Hence, one may conclude that al-Ghazali’s depiction of al-Farabi’s theory of celestial substance and intellection is either delib­erately or accidentally inaccurate. Consequently, Tahafut seems to be primarily a refutation of Ibn Sinas cosmology. There is little if no effort on al-Ghazali’s part to distinguish between the theories of these two falasifah and to provide a nuanced account of their views, and for this reason the Tahafut is of little interest to our inquiry.[525]

Maimonides’ Guide of the Perplexed

Maimonides’ Guide, in contrast, provides valuable information in the form of an interesting, if somewhat tantalizing, quotation allegedly borrowed from al-Farabi’s commentary on Physics. In the context of a polemical argumentation against the eternalists, Maimonides refers to the authority of the Second Teacher to lend weight to his claim that, since the stars are immobile and the orbs are mobile, they must be made of different matter. He writes:

For the fact that a sphere is always in motion and a star is always fixed proves that the matter of the stars is not the matter of the spheres. In fact, Abu Nasr [al-Fârâbi] in his glosses on the “Akroasis,” [Physics] has made a statement of which the literal text is as follows. He said: There is a difference between a sphere and the stars, for a sphere is transparent whereas the stars are not transparent. The cause for this lies in the fact that there is a difference between the two matters [al-maddatayn] and the two forms. But this difference is small. This is literally the text of his statement.[526]

There are a few striking features about Maimonides’ citation that require clarification. First, although the mention of al-Farabi undoubt­edly strengthens the claim that Maimonides is trying to make, there is a discrepancy between the contexts of their arguments. Maimonides infers the need for various celestial matters from the contrast between mobile spheres and immobile stars. His is, thus, an argument based on motion. Al-Farabi, on the other hand, comes to the same conclusion on the basis of a distinction between transparent and non-transparent heavenly bodies. Maimonides acknowledges this when he further writes: “I, however, do not say “small,” but say that they [the two mat­ters] are very different. For I do not infer this from the fact of transpar­ency, but from the motions.”[527] Obviously, what is of interest and value to Maimonides is al-Fârâbï’s conclusion concerning the different grades of celestial matter, not the reasoning he develops to reach this conclu­sion. This disregard for the context from which arguments are bor­rowed is typical of polemical works.

Of much greater relevance to the present discussion, however, is the cosmological idea that Maimonides ascribes to the Second Teacher, according to which different kinds or grades of matter exist in the heav­ens. This idea not only fits awkwardly with the previous passage quoted from Ihsa ’, which refers to “a certain one matter,” but it also plainly contradicts al-Fârâbï’s other theories of celestial substrate in Ára and Siyasah. Maimonides’ quotation evokes various Greek theories of celes­tial matter, such as the one developed by Philoponus, who argued that the heavens are composed of various elements and do not form a homogenous whole. In the Arabic tradition, Abû l-Barakât al-Baghdâdï apparently held such a view as well.[528] But as far we know, al-Fârâbï never adhered to a Philoponian conception of celestial matter. This is clear from his refutation of the Grammarian’s cosmological theories in his treatise Radd—which focuses expressly on the elements and aether—as well as from the views he articulates in his own works. Alternatively, there is no evidence to conclude that al-Fârâbï ever adhered to the atomistic theory defended by the mutakallimün. How, then, are we to interpret this passage?

Since al-Fârâbï’s commentary on Physics has not survived, except for a few fragments in Latin translation, there is no way of verifying Maimonides’ report.[529] Although the latter’s exaggerated emphasis on the fact that he is quoting al-Fârâbï “literally” and the polemical use he makes of this quotation are a bit suspicious, one should not dismiss his testimony as wholly unsound. The more likely hypothesis is that al-Fârâbï may actually have upheld such a view in his Physics commen­tary and during a period of his life that coincided with his early philo­sophical formation. For the fact that Maimonides transmits al-Fârâbï’s view in the midst of arguments designed to prove the createdness of the world shows that this type of theory of celestial matter fitted well in a creationist context.[530] In this sense, it should be connected with al-Fârâbi’s possible endorsement of creationism—as evidenced by Jam’ and Jawabat—and with his study of Aristotle with Christian scholars. On the other hand, it is difficult to imagine how the view conveyed by Maimonides could be adjusted to an eternalist framework, since differ­ent grades of celestial matter would seem to undermine the notion of elemental simplicity usually associated with an eternal heaven. In any case, Maimonides’ testimony indicates that at one point in his life, and more precisely during the time he composed his commentary on Physics, al-Fârâbi upheld the view that the heavenly bodies consist of different grades or kinds of matter.

Ibn Rushd’s Middle Commentary on On the Heavens

A diametrically opposed testimony is presented by Ibn Rushd in his Middle Commentary on On the Heavens, one of three Averroistic commentaries devoted to this work to have survived. In his discussion of celestial hylomorphism, Ibn Rushd surveys the views of previous thinkers and states that

Alexander acknowledged that the heavenly body is simple and not com­posed of form and matter [basitghayr murakkab min maddah wa-sürah], as is clear from his commentary on Book Lambda. Know that there is no disagreement among the commentators [al-mufassirin] on this point, as is shown by Themistius’ commentary [sharhihi, i.e., his paraphrase] on On the Heavens, when he says that the celestial body has no substrate [la mawdua lahü]. Likewise [wa-kadhalika] Abu Nasr [al-Fârâbi] stressed this point.[531]

Although this quotation is a precious testimony for my overarching argument, it is not without its ambiguities. The most obvious, yet cru­cial point is that Ibn Rushd in this passage ascribes the theory of imma­terial and non-hylomorphic heavenly bodies to al-Fârâbi, a report that corroborates the evidence found in Ára and Siyasah. If the celestial bodies are devoid of “substrate,” as Ibn Rushd tells us on al-Fârâbi’s behalf, then they obviously cannot possess any kind of matter, for mat­ter always functions as a substrate for form.[532] Because Ibn Rushd makes a point to cite al-Fârâbi together with the Greek thinkers (but he does not, significantly, mention Ibn Sinâ, whose theory of celestial substance is more explicitly hylomorphic), one must presume that he found al-Fârâbï’s position on this issue noteworthy enough to mention him by name. As we shall see shortly, the connection Ibn Rushd establishes between Alexander, Themistius, and al-Fârâbï vis-à-vis the problem of celestial matter is substantiated both historically and doctrinally: the former by what we know of the transmission and reception of the texts written by these Greek authors in medieval Baghdad, the latter by a comparison of al-Fârâbï’s, Alexander’s, and Themistius’ theories of sub­strate. Hence, Ibn Rushd seems to be well informed both in terms of the historical connection between the Greek and Arabic philosophers and the contents of their works.

On the other hand, what is surprising about Ibn Rushd’s report is that it mentions the term “substrate” (mawdu) instead of the term “matter” (maddah) to describe al-Fârâbï’s view. Al-Fârâbï’s theory as it appears in Ára and Siyasah is that the heavenly bodies are deprived of “matter,” but not of a certain “substrate,” which is closely linked with the celestial soul. Moreover, al-Fârâbï employs the concept of substrate to show that the celestial substance is composite, not simple (ch. 3, 2.7.). Ibn Rushd could not have failed to grasp these points had he read al-Fârâbï’s emanationist works carefully. This raises the obvious ques­tion of which Fârâbïan work Ibn Rushd had in mind when making this statement. This question is all the more valid given that Maimonides refers in Guide to al-Fârâbï’s Physics, a work which is no longer extant and which seems to have contained doctrines that differ quite impor­tantly from those articulated in al-Fârâbï’s later works.[533] In spite of this, Ibn Rushd appears to use the two terms ‘substrate’ and ‘matter’ synony­mously in this passage, and his report informs us that all of these thinkers, i.e., Alexander, Themistius, and al-Fârâbï, agreed in depriving the celestial bodies of material substrates or of any kind of material composition.

1.2.3.    Conclusion

The previous survey of celestial matter in the Fârâbïan corpus and in later reports has brought to light several discrepancies and indicates that al-Fârâbï’s doctrines on this issue are not homogeneous. In his cur­ricular works and in his summaries of Aristotelian philosophy, al-Fârâbï discusses celestial matter in a way that is quite germane to the aether theory of On the Heavens, although he omits the Arabic terminology usually associated with this concept and also introduces minor modifi­cations.[534] According to these works, the celestial bodies are made of matter (maddah), even though this matter is different from the one of sublunary bodies. This special matter is presumably incorruptible— although al-Fârâbï does not specify this himself—and it is also charac­terized by circular motion. Explicit references to On the Heavens are made in these works.

In the emanationist treatises, in contrast, al-Fârâbï refrains from ascribing any kind of matter (maddah) to the heavens, and he intro­duces the concept of substrate (mawdu) instead. He does not mention On the Heavens at all. One notices a clearly definable trend in Ára and Siyasah to minimize the association between the heavenly bodies and matter and even to present them as non-material entities. Finally, the evidence that can be gleaned from later sources seems to intensify these discrepancies: while Ibn Rushd refers to al-Fârâbï’s view that the celes­tial bodies lack substrate and, therefore, matter, Maimonides quotes al-Fârâbï’s commentary on Physics as upholding a theory of multiple types or degrees of celestial matter.

But more should be said about how al-Fârâbï handles this issue in the emanationist treatises. On the basis of these texts, we may conclude either that the heavenly bodies have no matter at all or that they possess a special matter that is essentially different from that of perishable beings.[535] On the one hand, al-Fârâbï holds that all bodies are composed of form and matter, two of the six principles that make up his ontol- ogy.[536] Since the orbs and planets are bodies (ajsam), they should accord­ingly be hylomorphic. Al-Fârâbï claims that the heavenly bodies emit light and possess the best corporeal qualities, which also implies that they are material.[537] On the other hand, he says virtually nothing in his emanationist treatises about the nature of celestial matter, but instead seems to replace matter with a new concept of immaterial substrate. He defines the celestial bodies essentially as intellectual beings closer to the divine realm than to the world of material and corporeal existents. How, then, is one to interpret this doctrine of celestial substrate?

One may justifiably argue that al-Fârâbï’s failure to mention aether or to articulate a coherent theory of celestial matter does not stand as sufficient proof that he believed the heavens to be immaterial. After all, Proclus sometimes calls the heavenly bodies “immaterial” (auXov), although in other instances he endows them with a material substrate made of a refined version of the elements, especially fire.[538] Accordingly, al-Fârâbï’s statement in Siyasah that the celestial substrates are “not matters” (laysat mawadd) could be interpreted as meaning simply that they are not composed of the four elements fire, air, earth, and water, but not that they are literally immaterial. While possible, this reading does not agree with the accumulated evidence presented above, and there are several reasons to discard it.

To begin with, al-Fârâbï deliberately omits all hylic terms in connec­tion with the heavens (such as maddah, ‘unsur, and hayüla), a fact which cannot be merely coincidental. Second, he replaces matter with the concept of substrate (mawdu), which he uses very consistently in both Ára and Siyasah to the exclusion of terms signifying matter. This concept of substrate is conceived of as being semantically broader than the concept of matter, with the result that not all substrates are mate­rial. In Fusü l al-Fârâbï distinguishes three classes of beings on the basis of their relation to matter and states: “There are three genera of existing things: those devoid of matter, celestial bodies, and material bodies,” to which correspond “three worlds: spiritual, celestial, and material [rühaniyyah wa-samawiyyah wa-hayülâniyyah]”[539] Al-Fârâbï therefore makes a clear distinction between the material beings and the celestial beings on the grounds of their relation to matter. Third, while Aristotle and the later Peripatetic tradition regarded aether as a simple substance and the celestial bodies as possessing a homogeneous nature, al-Fârâbï’s concept of substrate implies the opposite: the celestial bodies are composite substances, which can be divided into form and substrate. Moreover, unlike aether, which pervades the entire heavens and consti­tutes the corporeal substance of the orbs and planets, al-Fârâbï explains that the celestial substrates are proper to each celestial body and can only receive one specific form, i.e., the soul of this celestial body, thus undermining the idea that the celestial bodies possess a common matter.

Fourth, since the celestial souls are defined by al-Fârâbï as intellects, it is inconceivable that they would inhere in a material substrate. In fact, these substrates are presented as being closely related to the celes­tial rational soul to the extent that one even wonders if they are not to be seen as a part of it, just as al-Fârâbï calls mawdu certain faculties of the human rational soul.[540] Finally, whereas aether was connected with the perfect circular motion of the heavens in the Peripatetic tradition— a connection which al-Fârâbï makes on behalf of Aristotle in the con­text of his defense of aether in Radd—the emanationist treatises omit any connection between aether and motion, comparable to the one that appears in On the Heavens 1.2-4, nor do they stress the kinematic quality of the heavenly substance. Rather, as will be seen in chapter 4, al-Fârâbï makes soul the primary cause of motion. All of these factors compellingly point to the conclusion that al-Fârâbï departed from the Peripatetic tradition on aether and that he articulated the theory of an immaterial celestial substrate instead.[541]

At first glance al-Fârâbï’s reticence to ascribe any kind of matter to the heavenly bodies appears as an unexpected and intriguing departure from most of the Greek cosmological traditions of antiquity. These had developed various different theories of celestial matter: it could consist of aether (Aristotle), of a refined version of the four elements with a predominance of fire (Plato, Proclus, Simplicius), or even of the same elements as those that exist in the sublunary world (Philoponus). Regardless of the differences between their views, these thinkers ascribed some kind of materiality to the heavens, including Philoponus, who rejected Aristotle’s cosmology and mounted the most serious rebuttal against it. One of the basic premises of these views is the cor­relation between perceptibility and materiality. Accordingly, the stars and planets are perceptible bodies and so they must be composed of matter, everything that is perceptible to the senses being material. Aristotle articulates this idea clearly in On the Heavens when he writes: “Now since the universe is perceptible it must be regarded as a particu­lar; for everything that is perceptible subsists, as we know, in matter.”[542] Several centuries later, Philoponus reiterates this point in his attack against a group of unnamed philosophers. He writes: “it is quite ridicu­lous ... to say that the heavens are immaterial [auXov], For they are not intelligible, but perceptible.”[543] Philoponus’ tone is denigrative, but his statement testifies that the idea of an immaterial heaven was not unknown in antiquity.

What is more, al-Fârâbï’s position seems to depart from that of his predecessors in the Arabic tradition. Al-Kindï, for instance, refers several times to the fifth substance of the heavens in his corpus[544] and provides a definition of matter in his Risalah fi hudüd al-ashya that stresses a literal understanding of celestial hylomorphism. In the latter treatise, al-Kindi writes that “falak [the celestial orb] is matter [unsur] which has a form [sürah].”[545] This definition proves that he perceived the celestial bodies as hylomorphic beings. Ibn Sina and Maimonides, to name but two major post-Farabian thinkers, also stress the hylomor­phic nature of the heavens and talk at length about the matter (maddah) of the orbs.[546] Al-Farabi’s views contrast singularly with those of these other Arabic thinkers.

Al-Farabi therefore departed from one of Aristotle’s core cosmologi­cal tenets in his emanationist treatises. In doing so, he was continuing an ancient exegetical tradition on aether that had generated a wide variety of interpretations regarding the exact nature of celestial matter. In some cases, the departure from Aristotle had been so drastic that thinkers such as Xenarchus in the Peripatetic school, Plotinus, and later on Philoponus felt entitled to challenge the seminal views of the Stagirite on aether.[547] Al-Farabi perpetuates these exegetical efforts in his own works, thereby inscribing himself in this long philosophical tradition and demonstrating a willingness to put forth innovative inter­pretations regarding ideas he inherited from past thinkers.

To recapitulate, then, the previous analysis has led to a distinction between three very different theories of celestial substance, which cor­respond to a three-fold division of the Farabian corpus: the first one consists of Fusül, Ára, Siyasah, to which should also be added Ibn Rushd’s quotation; the second one consists of Ihsa ’, Falsafat Aristü ta lis, and Radd; and the third one is represented by Maimonides’ quotation referring to al-Farabi’s commentary on Physics. When one takes into account some of the other findings reached in the previous sections of this book, one can reconstruct three main theories of celestial sub­stance in al-Fârâbï’s works, which can be organized as follows:

1)    Ára and Siyasah a) equate the souls of the heavenly bodies with their forms; b) combine them with a non-material substrate; c) and use analogical language to describe the heavens, which both empha­sizes their remoteness from the sublunary world and at the same time offers a convenient means of comparing the two.[548]

2)    These points, which do not appear in any other work by al-Fârâbï, are opposed to the more ‘standard’ descriptions of aether given in Ihsa ’, Falsafat Aristü ta lis, and Radd, which a) explicitly mention the matter (maddah) of the heavens and omit to mention substrate (mawdu); b) mention celestial form, but neither equate the celestial soul with form, nor mention the soul of the heavenly bodies in this context; and c) shun analogical language.

3)    Finally, there is the theory of various grades of celestial matter that Maimonides ascribes to the Second Teacher in his Physics com­mentary, which is derived from the observation of the various degrees of transparency of the heavenly bodies.

While several hypotheses can be proposed to explain these discrepan­cies, the most convincing one, in my opinion, is the hypothesis of an evolution in al-Fârâbï’s conception of this cosmological problem. In this view, al-Fârâbï’s theories evolved over time, and he composed these works during different periods of his life. The main argument support­ing this developmentalist approach so far is a chronological one: there is a correspondence between the hylic theories exposed in al-Fârâbï’s works and the dating of his corpus. It is generally held that Árü’, Siyasah, and Fusü l belong to a late phase in the Second Teacher’s life.[549] In con­trast, it is reasonable to surmise that most of al-Fârâbï’s commentaries on the Aristotelian corpus, such as his commentaries on Physics and On the Heavens, as well as his curricular works and summaries of Aristotelian philosophy (Ihsâ’, Falsafat Aristutâlïs), were produced during an earlier phase, when he was studying Aristotelian philosophy from the perspective of the Alexandrian school tradition and through the mediation of the Christian Aristotelians in Baghdad.

It is striking that the previous classification of al-Fârâbï’s works based on his doctrine of celestial substance accords with the little that is known about the dating of the Fârâbïan corpus. This interpretation has the merit not only of explaining the heterogeneous evidence concern­ing matter that can be gleaned from the Fârâbïan corpus, but also of accounting for the contradictory reports made by later authors such as Maimonides and Ibn Rushd. In order to further strengthen the funda­mental hypothesis of an evolution in al-Fârâbï’s cosmology, I will dis­cuss some of the factors that may have been responsible for this shift in doctrine, and then turn to an examination of al-Fârâbï’s views on the causation of the material world.

1.3. Four Explanations of al-Fârâbï’s Theory of Substrate (mawdu)

In the following paragraphs, I examine what I believe are four convinc­ing reasons why al-Fârâbï may have engaged in a revision of his early Aristotelian views on the question of celestial substance and developed the concept of substrate (mawdu) in his later works. First, al-Fârâbï was positively influenced by the commentaries of Alexander of Aphrodisias and Themistius, which provided him with new exegetical possibilities on the question of celestial matter. Second, al-Fârâbï was negatively influenced by the severe criticisms that Aristotle’s theory of aether incurred at the hands of Philoponus. In addition, the prevalent Greek and Islamic precedents for the view of a material heaven (nota­bly those of Philoponus and al-Râzï) would not have been doctrinally acceptable to al-Fârâbï, because they clashed with other aspects of his thought. Third, al-Fârâbï’s emanationist treatises are marked by a depreciation of the principle of matter in general. Fourth, Aristotle’s aether was difficult to reconcile with the Ptolemaic theories of celestial motion.

1.3.1. Substrate (vnoKsipsvov) in the Greek Commentatorial Tradition

Given that many of al-Fârâbï’s cosmological views stem from a long philosophical tradition that flourished especially in the late antique world of the Eastern Mediterranean, it is worthwhile examining whether his theory of celestial substrate had any precedent in the Greek commentaries. The concepts of matter (uTh) and substrate (únoKeípevov) figure in many ancient debates about the nature of the heavens. They were part and parcel of the Greek philosophical termi­nology that was transmitted to the Islamic world, even though no Arabic thinker before al-Fârâbï makes such ample use of substrate (mawdu) in his cosmology and psychology.[550] This suggests that he was well informed about the philosophical debates of late antiquity and that he knew some of the Greek commentaries written on On the Heavens, Physics, and Metaphysics. A study of the works of the Greek commenta­tors immediately reveals a doctrinal link between al-Fârâbï, Alexander of Aphrodisias, and Themistius with regard to these issues. There fol­lows a brief overview of celestial matter in these thinkers’ works and its relation to al-Fârâbï’s cosmology.

The connection between substrate and matter was already made by Aristotle, and these passages provided a starting point for subsequent exegetical elaborations on the issue of celestial matter.[551] Ancient com­mentators, such as Alexander of Aphrodisias and Themistius, were intent on clarifying the nature of celestial matter as it appeared in the Aristotelian corpus, but in the process of interpreting Aristotle, they often ended up elaborating a different doctrine from that of their mas­ter. For instance, Alexander and Themistius sometimes seem to reject the idea that the heavens are material. Building on certain passages of the Aristotelian corpus such as Metaphysics 8.4.1044b7-8 in which Aristotle seems to hint at the possibility that the heavens are immate­rial, the later commentators developed a new interpretation of celestial substance only loosely based on On the Heavens and inspired by other concepts such as substrate and soul.

An example of this kind of exegetical endeavor appears in Alexander’s commentary on Metaphysics, in which he claims that “the substrate in the divine [bodies] is not matter,” and that “the body that moves in a circle is also a natural body, but matter is not the substrate for this body.”[552] In another passage dealing with the relation between form, matter, and body, Alexander writes: “In this connection, one might inquire about the forms in the divine bodies, for these forms are nei­ther enmattered nor perishable and are separable in thought from their underlying body.”[553] Finally, in De mixtione, Alexander writes that “the whole divine body, which is active, is unmixed and unable to be recip­rocally acted on by the body acted on by it; for only enmattered bodies can be acted on.”[554] As I. Bodnár wrote in his article on Alexander’s cos­mology, “the celestial element, which Alexander tends to call Orlov omqa, divine body, is removed from the components of the ever­changing sublunary world to the extent that it can be a legitimate ques­tion whether the substrate of celestial bodies can be called matter.”[555]

Themistius also proposes a similar reading of Aristotle’s aether when he writes in his commentary on On the Heavens: “The body which rotates has no contrary, as will become clear shortly. Nor does it have any substrate, for elsewhere it was stated that it lacks matter.”[556] This view is also envisaged, but not endorsed, in his paraphrase of Aristotle’s Metaphysics, Book Lambda, where he suggests that the celestial bodies may be pure forms devoid of matter or that they may contain matter only in an equivocal sense.[557] Finally, Proclus also states on numerous occasions that the heavens are immaterial (auXov), although he devel­ops in parallel a theory of celestial matter that is based on Plato’s account in Timaeus 40A, according to which the celestial bodies are composed of a pure version of the four elements, with a predominance of fire.[558] To my knowledge, however, Proclus does not include substrate in his discussion of the celestial bodies. Hence, the similarities between Alexander’s, Themistius’, and al-Fârâbï’s interpretation of celestial substance are striking and suggest that al-Fârâbï may have derived his theory of immaterial substrate from these thinkers.[559]

It is unlikely that Alexander’s and Themistius’ interpretations are faithful to Aristotle’s view on aether as exposed in On the Heavens. Nevertheless, they represent interesting cosmological developments in late antiquity.[560] In this connection, however, how literally should one construe Alexander’s statements that the celestial bodies are immate­rial? Could the heavenly body consist of another type of matter? In other instances Alexander and Themistius seem to posit the existence of some kind of matter in the heavens that they associate with the potency of motion in place. For example, in Quaestiones 1.10 and 1.15, Alexander argues that the heavens are material, albeit made of a matter which shares nothing in common with sublunary matter: he therefore posits the existence of two matters, one sublunary, and one heavenly.[561] This conflicting evidence makes it difficult to reconstruct Alexander’s position on celestial matter and raises the question of whether he actu­ally held a consistent position on this issue throughout his life. In any case, the important point for my argument is that some of Alexander’s and Themistius’ views were likely known to al-Fârâbï as a result of the Greek to Arabic translation movement and probably served as the starting point for his own interpretation of this problem. Alexander’s comments on celestial matter and substrate in particular may have opened new perspectives for al-Fârâbï’s interpretation of Aristotle’s On the Heavens.

There is, however, a significant difference between Alexander’s and Themistius’ views on celestial matter, which should be underlined due to its connection with al-Fârâbï’s theory. Themistius not only believes that the heavens are immaterial, but he also seems to exclude the pos­sibility of their having a non-material substrate, since he equates sub­strate with matter. He writes: “Nor does it [the celestial body] have any substratum, for elsewhere it was stated that it lacks matter.”[562] Alexander, on the other hand, explicitly refers to a celestial substrate that is not material, but which is meant to act as matter for the celestial bodies. He thus replaces celestial matter with celestial substrate, while maintain­ing a conceptual distinction between the two. As Alexander explains in his Metaphysics commentary, “the term ‘substrate’ [to hupokeimenon] has greater extension than the term ‘matter’ [hule], for the substrate in the divine [bodies] is not matter.”[563] On the issue of celestial matter, then, Alexander’s and al-Fârâbï’s interpretations are strikingly similar. Both reject the straightforward notion that the heavens are mate­rial, and both use substrate (únoKeípevov/mawdñ') as a substitute for matter. Substrate in their philosophy is conceptually broader than mat­ter, since some things can have a substrate without having matter.[564] In addition, both Alexander and al-Fârâbï seem to reject any correla­tion between celestial matter and celestial motion.[565]

The previous analysis strongly suggests a link between Alexander, Themistius, and al-Fârâbï on the question of celestial matter and substrate. This connection acquires additional plausibility when one takes into account the fact that many of Alexander’s and Themistius’ works were translated into Arabic. These include the former’s com­mentary on, and the latter’s paraphrase of, Book Lambda, as well as Themistius’ paraphrase of On the Heavens.[566] Furthermore, the Arabic translators of these works were in direct contact with al-Fârâbï, who gravitated around their circle. Thanks to Ibn al-Nadïm, we know that Mattâ ibn Yûnus translated part of Alexander’s and Themistius’ com­mentary on and paraphrase of Metaphysics respectively and that the latter translation was copied and perhaps corrected by Yahyâ ibn Adï.[567] Now it is noteworthy that both Mattâ ibn Yûnus and Yahyâ ibn Adï were close acquaintances of al-Fârâbï: the former was an older col­league and possibly his teacher in Baghdad, while the latter was his foremost student. For this reason, it is not surprising to find a passage in Mattâ ibn Yûnus’ preserved commentary on Aristotle’s Physics 2.7-9 that shows a marked similarity with the Greek commentators’ and al-Fârâbï’s views on celestial substance. In his answer to a question addressed to him concerning Aristotle’s theory of the four causes, Mattâ ibn Yûnus says:

The sun and man are equally one and the same with respect to the form of body [that is, inasmuch as they are bodies], but the sun is bereft of all other causes, because it is unaffected by whatever it affects since it has no matter [hayüla]; however, it has something like matter [¡akin laha shibh bi-l-hayüla]—where ‘matter’ is that which is susceptible to affectation— and so it might receive the transmitted form that is simple.[568]

Two points are of interest here. First, there is the parallel between Matta ibn Yûnus’ statement concerning the immateriality of the sun and Alexander’s and al-Fârâbï’s belief that the celestial bodies are not material. Second, one notices that Matta ibn Yûnus and al-Fârâbï share a common analogical language to stress that the heavenly bodies are made of something that is “like” or “resembles” (shibh bi) matter.[569] The similar contents and style of their statements on celestial matter, the close historical link between Matta ibn Yûnus and al-Fârâbï, and the former’s role in the translation of Greek commentaries—including some by Alexander—definitely point to a continuous exegetical trend stretching from Alexander to the Baghdad philosophers of the tenth century.

1.3.2.    Philoponus and Abü Bakr al-Rdzi on Matter

Al-Fârâbï may also have reacted against some of the theories elabo­rated by his Greek and Arabic predecessors. Philoponus, al-Kindï, and Abû Bakr al-Râzï, whose works were probably well-known to al-Fârâbï, developed very different doctrines of matter in their cosmologies. But these models presented serious obstacles to al-Fârâbï’s commitment to the eternality and causality of the world and matter in his late meta­physical works. The incompatibility of these thinkers’ doctrine of mat­ter with al-Fârâbï’s mature metaphysics may have prompted him to move away from the commonly held notion of the materiality of the heavens and to adopt a different exegetical approach, which was par­tially suggested to him by the Neoplatonica arabica and by Alexander’s and Themistius’ commentaries.

Philoponus in particular may have had a strong impact on the Second Teacher, who was well acquainted with his criticism of Aristotle’s cosmology. As C. Wildberg explains, the Against Aristotle shaped subsequent debates over the creation of the world in Islam.[570] Muslim and Christian theologians, whose views were often indebted to Philoponus’ arguments, also debated the theory that the heavens are made of a different matter from that of the sublunary world. Most Muslim theologians held the view that the heavens are material, yet they ascribed neither eternity nor incorruptibility to this matter. According to the occasionalists, the world is composed of atoms that are reorganized at each instant through divine power.[571] The celestial world does not escape God’s fiat and is essentially composed of the same elements as the sublunary world. Hence, the Aristotelian dichot­omy between an incorruptible heaven and a lower world of change and corruption is rejected, as is the notion of a simple heavenly substance.[572] [573]

Al-Fârâbï surely had to contend with the views of Philoponus and the mutakallimün. We know that he responded to Philoponus’ critique of Aristotle’s cosmology in several of his works, including in his no longer extant commentaries on Physics and On the Heavens, as well as in On Changing Beings and in the still extant Radd.7 That al-Fârâbï devoted such effort to refuting Philoponus’ views shows that these must have played an important role in the development of his own cosmo­logical ideas, possibly inciting him to move away from Aristotle’s the­ory of aether in his later years. Philoponus’ arguments concerning the corruptibility of the heavens were never endorsed by al-Fârâbï, even in Jam’ and Jawdbdt, which put forth a creationist view. In spite of this, they probably brought to his attention some of the problems inherent in the Aristotelian doctrine of aether.

The second doctrine al-Fârâbï may have had to contend with was al-Râzï’s idea of an eternal, uncaused matter. According to al-Râzï, matter represents one of the five eternal and uncaused principles of the universe, together with time, soul, space, and God. At the moment of creation, the demiurge allowed soul to mingle with matter, and all the corporeal existents of the universe, including the stars and planets, resulted from this unfortunate alliance. Al-Râzï defines prime matter (or “absolute matter,” hayülâ mutlaqah) before creation as an amorphous mass of atoms. At the moment of creation, this prime matter combines with void to form the bodies of all created beings. At the end of time, all matter will return to this amorphous primal state.[574]

There are a few striking features in al-Râzï’s account that would have been unacceptable to al-Fârâbï. The first and most obvious is the idea, directly derived from Plato, of an eternal and uncaused primal matter existing beyond the demiurgic power of God. This view could not be accepted by al-Fârâbï, who makes the entire universe and all its existents causally dependent on the First Cause. The second feature of al-Râzï’s account of creation is the homogeneity of matter, the idea that the mat­ter of all beings is essentially the same, i.e., atomistic, and that there is no hierarchy based on hylic distinctions. There is no dichotomy in al-Râzï’s universe between two opposed or essentially different types of matter, terrestrial and heavenly.[575] This again is alien to al-Fârâbï’s Aristotelian division of the cosmos in two distinct entities, the higher level of the eternal heavenly bodies and the lower level of perishable beings. In this respect, al-Râzï’s doctrine also contrasts with its Platonic source, since Plato establishes a qualitative difference between the heaven and the sublunary world on the basis of a hylic hierarchy.[576] Finally, al-Râzï’s idea that all matter is resolved into absolute prime matter at the end of time does not fit into al-Fârâbï’s eternalist frame­work as exposed in the emanationist works. In fact, al-Fârâbï is sup­posed to have written a treatise refuting some aspects of al-Râzï’s metaphysics, and it is possible that this work focused partially on his theory of matter.[577]

To conclude, it is clear that Philoponus’ and al-Râzï’s hylic theories could not be reconciled with some of the basic physical and metaphysi­cal tenets of al-Fârâbï’s philosophy. Whether in the polemics of Philoponus and the mutakallimün or in the Platonizing model of al-Râzï, the prevailing theories of a material heaven presented insur­mountable philosophical difficulties for al-Fârâbï. They required dras­tic concessions at the metaphysical level, such as the belief in the uncaused status of prime matter (al-Râzï), the intrinsic perishability of the heavens (Philoponus), or the non-eternity of the world (al-Kindï). The blatantly ‘materialistic’ theory of celestial substance upheld by these thinkers—elemental for Philoponus, aetherial for al-Kindï, and atomistic for al-Râzï—may have prompted al-Fârâbï to move away from these trends and to minimize the materiality of the heavens in his later emanationist treatises. Hence, it is not surprising that al-Fârâbï opted for a different solution, which relied on the commentaries of Alexander, Themistius, and on the Neoplatonica arabica. By introduc­ing the concept of an “immaterial” substrate and by emphasizing the noetic nature of the heavenly bodies, al-Fârâbï bypassed the problems he perceived in these thinkers’ hylic doctrines as well as their criticisms of Aristotle’s views.

1.3.3.    Prime Matter and Heavenly Substance: The Baseness of hayülâ

The status of prime matter in al-Fârâbï’s philosophy deserves inves­tigation, because it bears a direct link to the problem at hand. Regardless of whether ancient Greek and medieval Arabic philosophers estab­lished a radical or relative difference between heavenly and terrestrial matter, many of them agreed in establishing prime matter as the source principle out of which all types of matter arise, including celestial mat­ter. This is the case, for example, of Philoponus, who develops a con­cept of prime matter as three-dimensional corporeal extension, and which therefore encompasses the celestial bodies within its scope.[578] For al-Râzï, ultimate prime matter is not substantially different from the atomic matter that constitutes the things of the earth and heavens. As for Ibn Sïnâ and Ibn Rushd, they develop a theory whereby prime matter and the corporeal form are at the basis of all corporeal existents, including the celestial bodies.[579] The Ismâ'ïlï and Pseudo-Empedoclean traditions also establish a direct connection between prime matter and celestial matter, the former being the matrix out of which all the corpo­real beings—both heavenly and sublunary—are formed.[580]

Al-Fârâbï, in contrast, has a completely different view on the subject. Prime matter in his system is exclusively confined to the sublunary world, where it serves as the source out of which the four elements arise; it has no role whatsoever in the superlunary world. A clear indication of this is that its very existence is dependent on the rotat­ing activity of the celestial bodies, which are explicitly described as the causes of the existence of prime matter. In Siyasah, for example, al-Fârâbï writes: “The substance, nature, and activity of the celes­tial body is such that there immediately follows from it the existence of prime matter [al-maddah al-üla]”[581] This view is reiterated in Fl l-‘aql, when al-Fârâbï writes: “Indeed it has been ascertained in the book entitled On Generation and Corruption that the celestial bodies are the first efficient causes of these [sublunary bodies] and it is them therefore that provide the Agent Intellect with the matters and sub­strates in which it acts.”[582] According to al-Fârâbï, then, prime matter is not a cause or principle for the celestial bodies; rather, it is the celestial bodies themselves and their circular motions that cause its existence.[583] While this theory does not in itself imply the immateriality of the heavens, it suggests that al-Fârâbï sought to distance himself from what appears to have been a relatively common position in Greek and Arabic thought, namely, that prime matter is the ultimate principle for the materiality of all things, including the celestial bodies.[584]

One notices a general depreciation of matter in al-Fârâbï’s emana- tionist treatises, in a way that sometimes recalls Neoplatonic thought. On one occasion prime matter is described as the basest and “lowest of existents.”[585] It is situated below even the simple elements in al-Fârâbï’s ontological hierarchy. Although al-Fârâbï does not equate matter with evil, there is the idea in his works that matter is inevitably accompanied by potency, imperfection, and a base form of existence. The low status of prime matter and matter in general in al-Fârâbï’s ontology goes hand in hand with his desire to remove the celestial bodies as far as possible from any kind of materiality and substantial imperfection.

Hence, when compared to the views of his contemporaries, such as the Ikhwân al-Safâ’ and Abû Bakr al-Râzï, Ismâ'ïlï thinkers such as Abû Hâtim al-Râzï and al-Sijistânï, as well as those in the Pseudo- Empedoclean tradition, and even in comparison to the view of al-Kindï, al-Fârâbï’s position on the status of prime matter appears unconven­tional in the Arabic context, yet in a sense closer to Aristotle’s original doctrine.[586] Al-Fârâbï, unlike these thinkers, relegates prime matter to the very bottom of his ontological hierarchy and establishes a radical dichotomy between prime matter and the superlunary world. One implication is that there is no relation whatsoever between prime mat­ter and the substance of the celestial bodies. The further implication is that the substance of the celestial bodies is not only different from sub­lunary substances, but it cannot in any way be derived from prime mat­ter or a material principle either, since al-Fârâbï does not explicitly posit another source for matter apart from prime matter. Accordingly, the cause emanating from the separate intellects and responsible for the existence and corporeality of the celestial orbs is not described as a material cause. This raises the intriguing question of how al-Fârâbï’s cosmology accounts for the perceptibility and corporeality of the heav­ens and the fact that they possess qualities, such as motion, sizes and volumes, and luminosity, traditionally attributed to bodies.

1.3.4.    Aether and Motion

Finally, a word must be said about the relation between aether and the Ptolemaic theories of celestial motion. As chapter 2 showed, al-Fârâbï adopts the main features of Ptolemaic planetary theory, including the eccentrics and epicycles. On the other hand, he may have perceived an inherent tension between Aristotle’s aether theory and the Ptolemaic model, that is, between the idea exposed in On the Heavens 1.2-4 of a fifth nature possessing inherent circular motion and the existence of multiple and different celestial movements. In this respect, al-Fârâbï could have been influenced by some passages of Philoponus’ Against Aristotle, which uses the Ptolemaic theories of eccentrics and epicycles to undermine the notion of a special element possessing a propensity for regular, circular motion. As R. Sorabji writes, “he [Philoponus] also exploits the theory of epicycles, worked out by Hipparchus and Ptolemy, to argue that since they make celestial motions eccentric and complex, the case for the fifth element, with its simple rotation, is already refuted.”[587]

Evidence for this is mostly of a negative nature: in his personal works al-Fârâbï never establishes a correlation between celestial matter and celestial motion, and thus avoids explaining the movements of the orbs by reference to material causes.[588] His account, as we shall see in chap­ter 4, is exclusively based on the qualities of the celestial souls and in that sense perpetuates the ‘vitalist’ or ‘psychological’ trend adopted by many Neoplatonists before him. One may surmise that the diffi­culty involved in reconciling the kinematic implications of aether and the Ptolemaic planetary theories represents yet another reason for al-Fârâbï’s reticence to adopt a clearly recognizable aether theory in his emanationist treatises.[589]

2. The Origin of Matter: From Creationism to Eternal Causation

The previous section clarified al-Fârâbï’s views on the celestial sub­stance and also introduced the hypothesis of an evolution in his per­ception of this issue. In the remaining part of this chapter, I will address another key issue connected with celestial matter, namely, its origin and how it is caused to exist. We shall see that the developmentalist hypothesis that has been sketched above is also supported by the evi­dence in al-Fârâbï’s corpus concerning the relation between matter and creation.

The problem of how al-Fârâbï approaches the question of the crea­tion of matter should be contextualized in terms of the legacy of Greek thought on the one hand and the Arabic-Islamic theological back­ground on the other. More precisely, it is linked to the issue of the creation or eternity of the universe. This debate was already acute in the late antique Greek tradition and found a remarkable embodiment in the works of Proclus, Philoponus, and Simplicius. However, it acquired a new meaning in the Islamic milieu as a result of certain developments proper to this civilization, such as the appearance of an influential class of theologians (mutakallimün) at a social level and the emphasis on the absolute unity of God and His transcendence from the world at a creedal level.

As it stands today, the Fârâbïan corpus adopts two ‘paradigmatic’ interpretations concerning the origin of the material world. The first is based on the concepts of absolute creation out of nothing and on the world’s temporal finitude; the second, on the concepts of atemporal causation and the eternity of the physical universe. I use the word ‘par­adigm’ in order to stress the pre-existent conceptual framework these interpretations imply, as well as to emphasize the fact that they are mutually irreconcilable and rely on fundamentally different premises. This means that al-Fârâbï had to abandon the first paradigm in order to adopt the second.

At first glance, one may not perceive a strict correlation between al-Fârâbï’s theories of celestial substance and matter in general and his views on the creation of the world. But in late antique Greek and early Arabic philosophy, these two questions are intimately connected, since the status and nature of (celestial) matter in a thinker’s philosophical system depends partly on his perception of how the world was created and vice versa. For example, the postulation of an eternal and uncaused prime matter (e.g., Abû Bakr al-Râzï) clashed with the kalam notions of God’s unique eternality and of His absolute demiurgic power. Indeed, the orthodox Christian and Muslim creationist positions make matter a direct effect of God’s creative act. Its existence is therefore contingent on divine will and power. For this reason, it is worthwhile asking one­self what the prevailing views on the origin of celestial matter were in the tenth century and how they were integrated in a creationist or eter- nalist picture. How did al-Fârâbï respond to these pre-existing inter­pretations? And what are the main features that characterize his account? In the following paragraphs, I examine al-Fârâbï’s views on the existence and creation of matter in his various works and try to identify the sources and intellectual currents that informed them. I will then provide an overarching interpretation of al-Fârâbï’s intellectual development on this issue.

2.1. Aether and Creationism: An Exercise in Harmonization

Two important issues pertain to al-Fârâbï’s interpretation of Aristotle’s theory of aether and how he connected it with the thesis of the eternity of the universe. Al-Fârâbï was undeniably acquainted with the Aristotelian tenet that aether is a special, incorruptible element lacking the properties of the sublunary elements. Not only did he write a com­mentary on On the Heavens, but he also discusses this aspect of Aristotle’s cosmology in some of his extant works, such as Falsafat Aristü ta lis, Ihsa ’, and Radd.

One point that should be underlined from the outset is that the the­ory of aether—at least as it is exposed in Aristotle’s original cosmologi­cal system—would have represented a theoretical obstacle to al-Fârâbï’s own cosmological and metaphysical commitments and presented him with a fundamental incompatibility. The reason for this is that Aristotle gives no indications in On the Heavens or in any other work to the effect that aether and the heavens are caused and are essentially depend­ent on higher principles for their existence. Indeed, Aristotle’s cosmol­ogy has most often been defined by modern scholarship as an eternal system that nonetheless lacks a clear theory of creation or efficient causality.

In al-Fârâbï’s philosophy, in contrast, all existents, including of course the celestial bodies, as well as the primary elements and prime matter itself, are caused by higher principles. Surprisingly at first glance, al-Fârâbï nowhere highlights this as a shortcoming in Aristotle’s cos­mology. In order to understand why this is the case, one must contex­tualize al-Fârâbï’s approach to the Aristotelian works in light of the late antique Greek philosophical tradition. This tradition articulated a new interpretation of Aristotelian cosmology and of the nature and activity of the Aristotelian God by using Platonic concepts and by relying espe­cially on the account of creation found in Plato’s Timaeus. Through this exegetical device, late antique philosophers managed to supplement a compelling theory of efficient causality to the Aristotelian model, effec­tively defining the First Unmoved Mover not only as a final cause of motion, but also as an efficient cause responsible for the existence of the world. While this trend may have started with Alexander, it was articulated in its most consummated form by Ammonius, Simplicius, Syrianus, and other late Neoplatonists. It is this well-entrenched com- mentatorial tradition that al-Fârâbï inherited and through which he read and construed Aristotle’s cosmology.[590] With respect to celestial physics, this indicates that al-Fârâbï’s interpretation of the aether the­ory was significantly different from the original doctrine developed by the Stagirite. While for the latter, aether is uncaused and eternal, or both “ungenerated and indestructible” as Aristotle puts it in On the Heavens 1.3.270a13-14, for al-Fârâbï on the contrary the celestial sub­stance necessarily has a cause responsible for its existence, even though it may be conceived of as possessing eternal duration.

In view of the foregoing, it is important to realize that al-Fârâbï sub­sumes the question of the causedness of matter under the broader problem of the creation or causation of the universe. Unlike Aristotle, whose discussion of aether appears in his physical works, al-Fârâbï’s rare digressions on the celestial substance and matter in general are to be found in a metaphysical context and are usually connected with the causality of the separate intellects or the celestial bodies. This is because al-Fârâbï defines matter as one of the existents (mawjüdat) and princi­ples (mabadi) of his ontology, which, like all the other entities apart from the First, requires a cause for its existence. Accordingly, if we look at how al-Fârâbï deals with the problem of matter throughout his cor­pus, it readily appears that matter is either subordinated to a creationist account in which the entire universe is produced out of nothing by a Creator God (Jam, Jawabat, and possibly Radd), or, conversely, it is integrated in a causal scheme that ensures the temporal eternity of mat­ter, but which subordinates it to the causality of higher principles (Ara and Siyasah). My point is that in both cases matter is given an explicit cause and origin for its existence, and therefore the issues of the cosmo­logical status and nature of celestial matter are subordinated to the more fundamental issue of the causation or creation of the world. Hence, the two models that can be found in the Fârâbïan corpus (non­eternal creation ex nihilo and eternal causation) can be interpreted from the outset as cosmological developments perpetuating the late antique debates and discussions concerning creation and efficient cau­sality in Aristotle’s cosmology. As a corollary, and regardless of which paradigm is intended, there can be little doubt that al-Fârâbï inter­preted the Stagirite as upholding a view on efficient causation and the causedness of matter and the corporeal world that was similar to his. This can be explained either because he assumed that Aristotle, the greatest of all philosophers, could not have failed to develop such a theory and to account for the origin of matter, or more likely because he construed Aristotle’s cosmology in light of the late antique (mostly Neoplatonic) commentaries and the doctrines of causation found in the Neoplatonica arabica.

But before this aspect of his cosmology is examined in more detail, it should be stressed that the idea according to which al-Fârâbï may have articulated over the course of his life two different and conflicting cosmological models is not accepted by all scholars. There is in fact widespread disagreement on this point. Some scholars have explained this apparent contradiction by questioning al-Fârâbï’s author­ship of Jam’ and Jawabat, the two works which explicitly defend a creationist position. M. Rashed has argued in two recent articles that these treatises must be inauthentic, since they convey a view of creation, matter, and time that cannot be reconciled with al-Fârâbï’s other works. Although Rashed’s contention partly rests on earlier criticism, notably by J. Lameer, his articles nevertheless provide the most detailed and sustained argumentation in support of this revision­ist view.[591] Against Lameer and Rashed, other scholars continue to defend the authenticity of Jam’ and underline the many doctrinal and thematic parallels it shares with al-Fârâbï’s other works.[592] Hence, as the situation presently stands, it appears that evidence both for and against al-Fârâbï’s authorship can be mustered on the basis of a doctrinal anal­ysis of these treatises, making any final resolution of the debate extremely difficult.

I cannot engage here in a full-fledged discussion of this complicated problem, since this would require an analysis of the entire contents of Jam’ and Jawabat and thus take me too far from the topic at hand. Suffice it to say that the cumulative evidence supporting their authen­ticity cannot be ignored and renders the attempt to reject them from the Fârâbïan corpus premature.[593] In what follows, I propose to focus once more on the cosmological sections of these works in order to pro­vide fresh insight into their contents and sources and comment on some of the conclusions reached by previous studies. This reassessment pertains chiefly to the intellectual affiliations of the author of these works and to his use of the Neoplatonica arabica. On these points, my interpretation departs both from that of M. Mahdi, M. Galston, and T.-A. Druart, who believe that al-Fârâbï is relying on this corpus for apologetic reasons and with full cognizance of its non-Aristotelian ori­gin, and from that of C. Martini Bonadeo and C. D’Ancona, who regard the Neoplatonica arabica as a link connecting Jam’ to al-Fârâbï’s emana- tionist treatises and who argue that these works all put forth a similar doctrine of eternal emanation.

One observes that these scholars have relied either on the similari­ties or dissimilarities that the cosmology of Jam’ bears to al-Fârâbï’s other works in order to assess its authenticity, thus adopting what is essentially a comparative method.[594] My approach to the problem is somewhat different from the one embraced by these scholars, since in my view the authenticity of Jam’ cannot be decided solely on the basis of how the particular doctrines it puts forth compare to those in al-Fârâbï’s other works. Indeed, doctrinal resemblance or divergence cannot be used in itself as a decisive criterion, since it neglects other factors, such as chronology, intention, or context, which might play a preponderating role. Moreover, this comparative approach has limited explanatory potential, since it does not account satisfactorily for the peculiar features of these works, even if one upholds their authenticity and stresses their connection with al-Fârâbï’s other treatises.

The approach I will endorse relies instead on the hypothesis of a chronological evolution of al-Fârâbï’s cosmological works, which is supported by data and evidence independent of Jam’ itself, as has already been shown in the first section of this chapter dealing with celestial matter. In this view, the dissimilarities and discrepancies between Jam’ and the rest of the Fârâbïan corpus would indicate a development in al-Fârâbï’s reflection on these philosophical issues, which can best be explained by some of the historical and cultural cir­cumstances of his time and biographical factors. Throughout the fol­lowing analysis, I will therefore hypothetically accept the report of traditional Arabic historiographers, as well as the view of many mod­ern scholars, who identify al-Fârâbï as the author of Jam’ and Jawabat, and I proceed to a discussion of how these writings explain the origin of the material world. The analysis will in turn enable the elaboration of a new hypothesis concerning the meaning and place of these treatises in the Fârâbïan corpus.

2.1.1. Jam and Jawabat

I have already provided a detailed analysis of the main features of the cosmological account in Jam’ and Jawabat in a recent article.[595] In what follows, I emphasize only the key elements that are of impor­tance for the present inquiry. In Jam’, al-Fârâbï adopts a particular position on the issue of the creation of the world, which he also ascribes to Aristotle. Noticeable from the outset is the fact that this treatise deploys a rich array of terms to describe the creator: God is originator (mubdi) or originator of all things ( mubdi kull shay’), arti­san (sani’), and creator (bdrï). The world, including the heavens (falak), were created absolutely (ibda), from nothing (la ‘an shay’in and la min shay’in),[596] all at once (dafatan), and without time and not over a period of time (bi-la zaman). As in Timaeus 38B, time came into being with the universe, and it is defined as the “number of the celestial motion” (‘adad harakat al-falak), which means that it results from and is meas­ured by the constant circular motion of the celestial bodies.

As much of the following discussion with regard to al-Fârâbï and other thinkers will focus on the relation between time and creation, it should be emphasized right away that the author’s defense for the atemporality of creation does not entail his adherence to a doctrine of eternal creation or emanation. This is obvious from the fact that his intention in this passage of Jam’ is precisely to show that the world is not eternal (qadtm), that it was created by a willing God, and that it will be destroyed in the future. Al-Fârâbï merely intends to stress the fact that creation itself (ibda) is atemporal and that time begins to exist only with the existence and motion of the celestial orbs. In that sense, absolute creation does not occur in (ft) time, nor does it unfold gradu­ally (awwalan fa-awwalan) over a period of time. The argument was clearly intended against the view of certain literalist scholars who interpreted the account of creation in scriptures as a temporal process similar to the generation (takawwun) of plants and animals, for instance.[597]

The author of Jam’ asserts that in addition to being created, the world will come to an end and is temporally finite: “whatever comes from a thing will inevitably corrupt [yafsudu] and return to that thing,” and: “the world is innovated out of nothing and will thus revert to noth- ing.”[598] When combined with the proposition of creation with time, that is, with the view that time has a beginning and is concomitant with the motion of the first body, these statements underscore the finitude and contingency of the corporeal universe and its absolute dependence on the creator. In fact, al-Fârâbï criticizes various religious groups for fail­ing to articulate a clear theory of the world’s “complete annihilation” (al-talasht l-mahd)[599]

This creationist picture is explicitly ascribed by the author of Jam' to the Stagirite, both with regard to Book Lambda of Metaphysics and to the spurious Theology of Aristotle, here clearly considered a genuine Aristotelian work. When it comes to the creation of matter in particu­lar, the author makes a special point to cite the latter work and to refer to its authority in order to prove the Aristotelian pedigree of this idea:

it is made clear [in Theology of Aristotle] that the Creator created matter absolutely [abdaaha l-bari’] and from nothing [la 'an shay in], and that it was made corporeal and organized by God and by His will [‘an iradatihi].[600]

The use of the verb abdaa (“he created absolutely”) and the expression la ‘an shay’in (“not from a thing”) indicate that the existence not only of the material world, but of matter per se or prime matter is directly dependent on God’s absolute creative act. This idea is particularly sig­nificant to the author, for he accuses other religious groups (such as the Jews and Mazdeans) of upholding the eternity of matter and of not providing a clear account of its origination. He then adds that this mat­ter was made corporeal (tajassamat) and was organized (tarattabat) by God in a fashion reminiscent of the activity of the Demiurge in Timaeus, suggesting that God is not only responsible for creating matter out of nothing, but also for its harmonious organization into various groups of corporeal existents.[601]

Finally, considerable emphasis is placed on divine will throughout the cosmological passage of Jam‘. God created the world and matter through will (iradah), an idea which goes hand in hand with the doc­trine of divine knowledge of particulars also defended in this work. In this respect, al-Fârâbï describes God as the “ruler” or “organizer” (mudabbir) of the world and states that “He is ignorant not even of a grain of mustard seed,” an obvious reference to verses from the Quranic sürahs “The prophets” (21.47) and “Luqman” (31.16). In addition, he writes that “not one part of the world escapes His providence (‘inayah)” and that “the universal providence encompasses the particulars.”[602]

Question 9 of Jawabat articulates a view that is strikingly close to that of Jam'.[603] Its author explains that the entire world is composed of form (sürah) and matter (maddah), that it was created “all at once and not over a period of time” (fa-kawnuhü kana daf atan bi-la zaman), in spite of the fact that the beings it contains were created in time (ft zaman). In addition, the author clearly states that the world as a whole will undergo corruption (fasad), although this passing away, too, will not be a temporal event and will occur instantaneously and all at once. Unlike Jam, however, Question 9 of Jawabat develops an argument, or rather a proto-argument, to explain why the world is generated and destroyed. The gist of it is that since the world is composed (murakkab) of form and matter, it will undergo dissolution (tahltl or inhilal), because every composition undergoes dissolution.

In my article on Jam, I analyzed some of the sources underlying these accounts and argued that the cosmogonical views they put forth are indebted primarily to a Greco-Arabic theological tradition as embodied in the works of John Philoponus, as well as to some of al-Kindi’s treatises and the Neoplatonica arabica. The Philoponian con­nection can be perceived clearly in the following passage, which belonged to John’s work Against Aristotle, and which was preserved by Simplicius in his commentary on Physics:

God not only produces the forms of the things directly generated by him, but is believed to originate and to create even matter itself. ... Therefore, if the things generated by nature are generated out of existing things, it does not necessarily follow that the things directly generated by God are generated out of existing things as well, given that nature on the one hand needs some time and a process of generation in order to create each of the physical objects and that God on the other hand gives existence to the things directly generated by him without a time lapse and without a proc­ess of generation, that is to say without a gradual forming and shaping of the objects. For mere willing suffices for him to give substance to things.[604]

And also:

For the things created by God immediately are neither generated out of something pre-existent nor by way of a process of generation or a stretch of time. For God brought into existence both matter itself and time simul­taneously together with the universe, so that motion did not pre-exist the world in time.[605]

The last point on the creation of time together with the world is explained in more detail in a passage of Philoponus’ Against Proclus:

[B]y a temporal beginning I mean, as has been repeatedly stated, not one that has taken place within a part of time, time already being in existence, but [for a thing] to begin existing along with time, which had not previ­ously existed.[606]

These passages contain many of the key points discussed in Jam’ and Jawabat, such as the creation of matter ex nihilo and the creation of the world with time and not over a period of time, as well as the doctrine of divine will. They are presented in such a neatly condensed form that one may wonder whether these or other similar passages from Philoponus’ works were not used as a direct model by al-Fârâbï for the composition of his Jam’. In any case, he seems to have combined these Philoponian ideas with material derived from the late antique philo­sophical tradition and the Neoplatonica arabica, as is suggested by several conceptual and terminological parallels.[607] Yet it should be pointed out that the concepts which Jam’ and Jawabat share with the Arabic Neoplatonic texts—especially atemporal creation ‘all at once’— are deployed to express a different view of creation. For in the case of the former, they stress the temporal finitude and contingency of the corporeal world. The world was created all at once by an omnipotent divinity—at which point the heavenly motion and time started to exist—and it will also be destroyed all at once at a fixed point in the future, presumably by the same agent that made it.[608] Conversely, in the case of the Neoplatonica arabica, these same concepts are integrated in an eternalist scheme characterized by continuous emanation or crea­tion, with no mention of the world’s future dissolution. Accordingly, eternity is embodied in the celestial world, whereas the First is said to transcend eternity itself.[609]

A last point should be addressed: Does Jam’ posit intermediary intellectual beings between God and the corporeal world in a way simi­lar to al-Fârâbï’s later treatises? Even though it has been construed in this fashion by some scholars, the evidence in this regard is ambigu­ous.[610] On the one hand, the cosmogonical account of Jam’ does not explicitly mention any other causes of existence apart from God or any intermediaries operating between God and the corporeal world. On the contrary, it emphasizes divine omnipotence and omniscience and God’s absolute creative act (ibdü‘), even specifying that God created matter directly. In a passage dealing with the separability of form, the author explains that the divine forms and intelligibles subsist in God’s essence, not outside of It like “ghosts” or “spirits” (ashbah).[611] In this connection, he also warns that one should not con­ceive of the realm of intellect (’aql) as being essentially separate from the Creator.[612] On the other hand, in one passage, al-Fârâbï states that Aristotle expounded on “the corporeal and spiritual parts of the world.”[613] Although the term rühâniyyah, “spiritual” or “divine,” could be an implicit reference to a level of intermediary intellects, it could also merely serve to evoke the exalted nature of the superlunary world. Hence, the overall evidence in Jam’ seems to exclude a well-articulated theory of intermediary causation and defines God as the unique cause and creator of the world.

The foregoing remarks underscore the particular view expressed in Jam’ and Jawdbdt concerning the creation of matter, including the heavens. This account is defined by its compatibility on many points with the orthodox Christian and Muslim cosmogonical position and consists of the following key features: creation of the material world ex nihilo—including matter itself, a point emphasized by the author; creation with time, as opposed to both creation in time—time already being in existence—and creation over a period of time—time express­ing a process of change such as the growth of a plant; divine will as the reason for creation; and the emphasis on the future finitude and perishability of the world. No intermediate intellectual beings are posited that assist God in the act of creation. This position contrasts on virtually every point with al-Fârâbï’s mature treatises. In spite of this, one observes that the creationist paradigm exposed in these works fulfills at least one crucial function in the context of al-Fârâbï’s philosophy: it provides a clear and straightforward account of the ori­gin of matter, and thereby avoids the postulate of an eternal and uncaused material principle, as in Râzï’s philosophy. More specifically, it defines God as the absolute cause of the material world (both super­lunary and sublunary, no differentiation between the two is made in this work).

2.1.2. Radd

Radd offers additional, but ambiguous information about al-Fârâbï’s position vis-à-vis Aristotle’s aether theory and the debate over the crea­tion of the world, which might very well represent a certain departure from Jam’ and Jawdbdt. This treatise was written as an attempt to refute Philoponus’ critique of Aristotle’s theory of the elements in the context of the Christian thinker’s broader rebuttal of the eternity thesis in his Against Aristotle.[614] Al-Fârâbï’s argument is that Aristotle’s comments about aether and the elements were not intended to prove the eternity of the world (as Philoponus contends), but rather to differentiate between the various simple elements, that is, between the four sublu­nary elements on the one hand, and the fifth celestial element on the other.[615]

Apart from this straightforward fact, which is stated by al-Fârâbï at the beginning of the treatise, this text is particularly difficult to inter­pret due to its polemical character. According to M. Mahdi, who edited the Arabic version and translated it into English,[616] this treatise argues that Aristotle’s On the Heavens is essentially a discussion about the ele­ments, which by no means should be construed as defending the uncre­atedness and eternity of the world. Accordingly, al-Fârâbï intends to undermine Philoponus’ criticism by showing that there is no contra­diction between aether and the creation of the world, and that these notions can be easily reconciled. As Mahdi writes, “He [al-Fârâbï] does not believe that the first body as established by Aristotle is necessarily incompatible with the doctrine of the creation of the world.”[617] This view is echoed by al-Fârâbï himself in the first sentence of his work, where he quite surprisingly asserts that “none of Aristotle’s statements in On the Heavens and the World that John the Grammarian intended to destroy were intended by Aristotle to establish the eternity of the world.”[618]

There is, however, a fundamental ambiguity in this treatise, which is not highlighted by M. Mahdi in his introduction, but which was recently pointed out by C. Martini Bonadeo.[619] It concerns al-Fârâbï’s own inten­tion or skopós and his exact doctrinal position vis-à-vis Philoponus’ critique of Aristotelian cosmology. Is al-Fârâbï’s aim in this treatise to defend Aristotle’s thesis of the eternity of the world by arguing that, pace Philoponus, there is no real link between aether and eternity in On the Heavens and that aether is not meant in any way to represent a proof for eternity? Or is his aim to show, like the author of Jam, that Aristotle himself held a creationist and non-eternalist doctrine and thus that Philoponus has completely misinterpreted On the Heavens? In other words, is al-Fârâbï defending Aristotle from the perspective of an eternalist or a non-eternalist?

The relation between the concepts of eternity, creation, and the incorruptibility of aether are ambiguous in this treatise, to say the least. As Mahdi points out, “Alfarabi does not commit himself either way on the question of the eternity of the world.”[620] Although Mahdi does not address this question in depth, he seems to opt for the view that al-Fârâbï combined aether with a theory of eternal causation, which would imply that the Second Teacher is defending Aristotle from an eternalist viewpoint.[621] Mahdi may very well be right in construing the text in this manner. This interpretation would connect Radd not only to the later emanationist treatises, but also to other no longer extant works, such as On Changing Beings, in which al-Fârâbï is said to have defended the thesis of the eternity of the world.[622] This would imply that al-Fârâbï had departed from the position defended in Jam’ and Jawdbdt when he wrote this work.

Yet even if one grants the point that Radd assumes an implicit eter­nalist position, al-Fârâbï’s exact aim remains somewhat obscure. To illustrate this, one may further refine and subdivide the eternalist thesis into three interpretations, an ‘exclusive,’ an ‘inclusive,’ and a ‘relative’ one. According to the exclusive interpretation, al-Fârâbï is claiming that there is absolutely no connection between aether and eternity in Aristotle’s On the Heavens, although Aristotle does uphold the eternity of the physical universe in his other treatises. In this view, Aristotle was an eternalist, but never made the connection between aether and the eternity of the world (including the heavens). Consequently, Philoponus would have completely misrepresented Aristotle’s cosmology and his aim in On the Heavens, which was merely to describe the specificity of the heavenly element. This interpretation is, however, difficult to sustain, given the explicit connection between aether and eternity that Aristotle makes in On the Heavens, which is obvious to any careful reader of this work.[623] This exclusive interpretation should therefore not be given serious consideration.

The inclusive interpretation, in contrast, is more convincing. It rests on the idea that al-Fârâbï acknowledged the connection Aristotle estab­lished between aether and eternity, but did not regard aether as a proof leading to the proposition of the world’s eternity. What al-Fârâbï would be criticizing in this case would be Philoponus’ erroneous claim that Aristotle intended his theory of aether to stand as a demonstration (ùnoSei^iç/burhan) of the world’s eternity. This is apparently how M. Rashed understands al-Fârâbï’s aim, and it may very well underlie the latter’s statement to the effect that “none of Aristotle’s statements in On the Heavens and the World that John the Grammarian intended to destroy were intended by Aristotle to establish the eternity of the world.”[624] The problem with this approach, however, is that al-Fârâbï does not use the Arabic term burhan (“demonstrative proof”) in this sentence (as one would expect), but rather the term ithbat, which can be translated as “proof,” but also simply as “exposition,” “establishing that,” etc. Hence, this inclusive interpretation is only valid if one con­strues ithbat in the narrow sense of “demonstrative proof,” which is far from clear in this context. In any case, this interpretation again down­plays the connection between aether and eternity. For even if Aristotle did not intend his arguments in the opening section of On the Heavens as demonstrative proofs strictly speaking, he undoubtedly regarded them as a “confirmation” of the eternity thesis.[625]

Finally, according to the relative interpretation, al-Fârâbï accepts the connection between aether and eternity and may even regard the aether theory as a proof, but one which can be applied only to the heavens and not to the entire universe. In this third scenario, he would be criticizing Philoponus’ unjustified claim that Aristotle inferred the eternity of the entire universe—and not just that of the heavens—from his doctrine of aether. This interpretation should be compared to what al-Fârâbï says in some of his logical works concerning the applicability of proofs only to parts of a given inquiry and not to its whole.[626] But it is significant that the arguments al-Fârâbï puts forth in his refutation completely avoid any references to eternity and focus instead on Philoponus’ dis­cussion of Aristotle’s theory of the elements, of the distinction between them, and of their various motions. This approach seems somewhat inappropriate, if one keeps Philoponus’ intention in mind. For as al-Fârâbï himself admits at the beginning of the treatise, Philoponus’ avowed aim is to undermine the Aristotelian thesis of the world’s eter­nity. In that sense, it is particularly perplexing that the Second Teacher does not explain why aether cannot be used as a proof to establish the everlastingness of the whole world, even though it does prove the immortality of the celestial bodies.

If al-Fârâbï was indeed defending Aristotle from an eternalist per­spective, it is difficult to understand why he ignores these points. Following one line of reasoning, he could for instance have explained why aether is not a proof for the eternity of the world, why Aristotle preferred to defend the world’s eternity using other arguments, and where these arguments are to be found in his works. Yet al-Fârâbï does nothing of the sort. What we seem to witness on his part, then, is an endorsement of the aether theory with an adamant effort to cancel its eternalist implications.[627]

In addition to this complex of interpretations from the eternalist perspective, which all seem unsatisfactory, it is possible to construe al-Fârâbï’s aim and arguments from a creationist angle. This alternative interpretation was briefly discussed by C. Martini Bonadeo in her recent analysis of Jam'.[628] According to this interpretation, al-Fârâbï upholds a creationist position in this treatise and therefore attempts to refute Philoponus’ critique on its own grounds. Several hints point to the plausibility of this interpretation. First, and assuming that Jam’ is authentic, al-Fârâbï ascribes such a creationist view to Aristotle in this treatise and also presents the problem in very similar terms. Besides, there are many structural parallels between the two treatises. For instance, one finds the following statements in Jam':

It has escaped those who disagree [those who claim that Aristotle asserts the eternity of the world] that, first, what is set forth as an example does not stand as a belief and, also, that Aristotle’s purpose in the Topics is not to explain about the world; instead, his purpose is to explain about syl­logisms composed of widely-held premises.

And:

What also leads them in this presumption [those who claim that Aristotle was an eternalist] is what he mentions in the book On the Heavens about the whole having no temporal beginning, for they presume that he is there speaking about the world’s being eternal. That is not the case, since he had already explained in that and in other books about physics and theology that time is only the number of the motion of the celestial sphere and is generated from it.[629]

These two passages of Jam’ are important insofar as they may poten­tially throw light on al-Fârâbï’s aim and method in Radd. They are par­ticularly close to the opening statement of this treatise mentioned above.[630] In both cases, his aim is similar in that he wants to refute the views of those who wrongly ascribe the eternity thesis to Aristotle on the basis of physical concepts found in On the Heavens and other trea­tises: time in Jam’ and aether in Radd. Apart from the very close word­ing and tenor of these passages, al-Fârâbï’s strategy in these texts is similar and rests on the premise that these people have misinterpreted Aristotle’s aim and method and consequently that they have errone­ously inferred their conclusion about eternity. Although al-Fârâbï does not mention any name in Jam’, it is likely that he included Philoponus as one of the thinkers who wrongly claimed that Aristotle was an eter- nalist. Radd may thus be construed as echoing al-Fârâbï’s warning in Jam’ and as representing a more elaborate attempt to refute Philoponus’ position from a creationist perspective.

This interpretation is further supported by another passage in Jam, which appears just after al-Fârâbï’s mention of Theology of Aristotle and whose function is to buttress his general claim that Aristotle recog­nized the existence of a Creator.[631] According to this passage, Aristotle in both Physics and On the Heavens criticized the view of those who believe that the world came into being “by chance and randomness” (bi-l-bakht wa-l-ittifaq)P[632] He also highlighted the beautiful order of the various parts of the universe, thereby developing cosmological arguments showing the need for a wise architect. The implication of this passage is clearly that Aristotle defended the existence of the Creator in his physical works, including, and this is important, On the Heavens. Hence, the entire Aristotelian corpus, and not just Book Lambda of Metaphysics, was geared toward this theological purpose. This in turn enables us to better understand the creationist perspective possibly adopted by al-Fârâbï in Radd.

It was mentioned above that Radd endorses the aether theory, but without accepting its implications vis-à-vis eternity. One need not be surprised by this, for in al-Fârâbï’s mind the issues of the eternity of the heavens and of the special characteristics of aether may not have been connected. In other words, it is possible that al-Fârâbï is combining aether with a non-eternalist creationist picture, a combination which he would also have ascribed retrospectively to Aristotle. That this com­bination was theoretically possible in Arabic philosophy is demon­strated by al-Kindï, who adopts Aristotle’s postulate of a ‘first body’ or ‘fifth element’ that is in essence incorruptible, but at the same time sub­ordinates this theory to the more fundamental belief in the creationist act of God.[633] In other words, celestial matter is incorruptible as long as the world exists and up to the point when God destroys it. Despite its special nature and incorruptibility, its existence depends absolutely on the First Principle.[634] Finally, and apart from al-Kindï’s precedent, evidence from the Arabic translations of On the Heavens should be taken into account, for it is not implausible that the reconciliation between aether and creation was facilitated by, if not prefigured in, the Arabic versions of this work.[635]

If we accept the creationist, non-eternalist interpretation of Radd articulated above, then al-Farabi’s cosmological theories in Jam, Jawdbdt, and Radd would be similar: he would, following al-Kindi, combine a creationist and non-eternalist view of the universe with a theory of incorruptible celestial matter. This interpretation seems rein­forced by the fact that al-Farabi does not uphold the corruptibility of heavenly matter in any of his works, even in Jam’ and Jawdbdt, where he seems to defend the creation of the world ex nihilo. In these trea­tises, he explains that the world will be destroyed all at once and in no time, thus cancelling the possibility that the heaven will slowly decay due to the corruptibility of its matter. On this point, both al-Kindi and al-Farabi depart from Philoponus, who exerted considerable energy to refuting Aristotle’s theory of aether and to showing that the heavenly substance is perishable by nature and composed of the same elements as sublunary bodies. It would seem that throughout his corpus, and even in his creationist works, al-Fârâbï never adopted the Philoponian view of the intrinsic corruptibility of celestial matter.

This interpretation would also enable us to understand why al-Fârâbï in Radd simultaneously refutes the correlation made by Philoponus between aether and eternity, and yet defends the existence of the fifth element as expounded by Aristotle in On the Heavens. While in agree­ment with Philoponus on the question of creation, al-Fârâbï opposed him on the question of aether, which, like al-Kindï, he managed to rec­oncile with his cosmogonical account. The irony is that al-Fârâbï’s account of creation during this early phase was itself deeply influenced by Philoponus. It is precisely because al-Fârâbï was able to reconcile these two ideas (creation and aether) and attributed this view to Aristotle, that he misunderstood Philoponus’ attack on Aristotelian cosmology, which rested upon the correlation made between aether and eternity.[636]

If the previous interpretation is correct, then one would have to connect Radd to Jam’ and Jawdbdt. Indeed, an eternalist reading of Radd is discouraged by the parallels between this treatise and Jam’ and by the peculiar insistence al-Fârâbï shows to dissociate aether from eternity. There is another hint suggesting the correctness of this approach: the theory of celestial substance in Âra and Siyasah— treatises in which al-Fârâbï upheld an eternalist position—is very dif­ferent from the one that appears in Radd. As we have seen, by the time al-Fârâbï was writing the emanationist treatises, he had definitely moved beyond an Aristotelian conception of aether. This important observation suggests that these works belong to a different period in al-Fârâbï’s life from the one to which Radd belongs. Hence, in tenor, intention, and content, Radd is much closer to Jam’ than it is to the emanationist treatises. Although the previous interpretation should be regarded as a tentative one, in the absence of additional evidence con­cerning Radd, it helps us to maintain a broader interpretive framework and to insert this treatise in the developmentalist perspective previ­ously outlined.

2.2. Ihsa’ and Aghrad: Two Transitional Works?

2.2.1. Ihsa’ on Metaphysics and Creation and its Relation to Jam’

Al-Fârâbï’s Ihsa’ is an interesting work, which has nevertheless not attracted much scholarly attention and remains poorly studied and understood. Its general aim is to offer a systematic description of the philosophical curriculum by enumerating the different sciences, their parts, and their subject matter. It is clearly inscribed in the tradition of Alexandrian philosophical teaching, as Gutas stressed,[637] but it also contains other features that are characteristic of the Arabic intellectual context in which it was composed. It is precisely on these features that I wish to focus, especially al-Fârâbï’s description of metaphysics (al-'ilm al-ildht), which appears after his treatment of mathematics and physics, and which shows a high degree of similarity with the creation­ist position articulated in Jam'.[638]

In this section, al-Fârâbï identifies three parts that constitute meta­physics, the first two of which (the study of beings and their accidents, and the quest for the first principles of the sciences) are not immedi­ately relevant to my purposes. Rather, it is the third part I am interested in. It is by far the most extensive of the three and focuses on the aspect of metaphysics that investigates theological or divine matters, i.e., it deals with the immaterial existents that lie beyond the physical investi­gation. A close examination of this passage reveals that it may be divided further into three shorter sub-sections. In sub-section 1 (99,14­100,6), the author explains that metaphysics examines whether any immaterial beings exist, and if so, their number, whether they are infi­nite, etc. He also explains that this part of metaphysics proceeds up the ontological ladder through demonstrations to establish the existence of a perfect immaterial being above which no other and more perfect being can exist, and that this being is the First (al-awwal). This is clearly a summary of Aristotle’s Metaphysics, Book Lambda, which deals with the unmoved substances and asserts the existence of the First Unmoved Mover. Then follows sub-section 2 (100,7-13), which focuses on the nature of the First and especially on Its being a cause of existence (wujüd), unity (wahdah), and reality or truth (haqq) in all the other beings. This sub-section, which already introduces the theme of pro­cession, goes beyond Book Lambda and relies substantially on other, Neoplatonic sources. Finally, sub-section 3 (100,13-101,10) witnesses the identification of this deity with Allah and provides an account of Its actions and Its creation of the other existents.

This breakdown of the text shows clearly that according to al-Fârâbï, theology or divine science represents only one part (qism) of meta­physics, which is nonetheless the principal objective or aim (gharad/ skopós) sought in this science. As A. Bertolacci has shown, this view is inscribed in the Alexandrian Neoplatonic tradition, especially in the Ammonian tradition of metaphysical studies.[639] This focus on the theo­logical aim of metaphysics in turn explains why al-Fârâbï devotes so much space to describing the third part and its various sub-sections and why he begins the opening sections of Ára and Siyasah with a dis­cussion of the immaterial and divine entities.[640]

Now, one detects significant terminological and conceptual parallels between Ihsa and Jam, which are crucial for our understanding of how Ihsa fits in al-Fârâbï’s intellectual development, and which indicate that this work probably belongs to his creationist phase as well. The terminology used by al-Fârâbï to define the highest divinity, its nature, and its creation, borrows extensively from the theological domain and shows a clear overlap with the creationist treatises. The divinity is “the First” (al-awwal), “Allah the exalted” (Allah ‘azza wa- jalla), who possesses “attributes” (sifat) and “divine names” (taqaddasat asmauhü), who performs “acts” (af al), who “created the existents” (al-mawjüdat allatt khalaqaha), and “from whom the existents were originated” (kayfa hadathat al-mawjüdat ‘anhu).

Al-Fârâbï does not rely here on the specific terminology of causation that is prevalent in his later metaphysical treatises and which will be analyzed later on in detail. In this connection, one also notices that al-Fârâbï virtually ignores the separate intellects or thawant, a theory which will form the cornerstone of his mature cosmological system. The only potential reference to such intermediary beings (99,16) is vague and limited to the statement that the immaterial existents identi­fied by metaphysics are multiple (kathtrah). This statement appears in the context of al-Fârâbï’s description of Book Lambda and the ‘ascend­ing’ metaphysical inquiry in sub-section 1, but it plays no role in his description of the rest of metaphysics in sub-sections 2 and 3. This omission is all the more surprising, given that these sub-sections focus on procession and on the First’s relation to the other beings. Hence, instead of the multi-layered account of causation one finds in the later works, there is an emphasis in this text—especially in sub-section 2—on the oneness and unicity of God as Creator and on His being a source of unity and existence for all the other beings, as if He were the only cause operating in the superlunary world. This is another con­spicuous feature that Ihsa’ shares with Jam’.

Moreover, al-Fârâbï betrays in these two texts an identical under­standing of Aristotelian metaphysics, which in his view may be divided into an “ascending part,” which proceeds through demonstrations to establish the existence and oneness of God and which is contained in Book Lambda, and a “descending part,” which examines God’s relation to the other beings qua Creator and His role as a cause of existence and unity for these beings. This latter part is discussed in the Neoplatonica arabica, which al-Fârâbï obviously includes in the Aristotelian meta­physical corpus, even though he does not mention it by name. A com­parative table is provided below that highlights the key terms and shows the degree of overlap between Ihsa’ and Jam’:

 

Jam'

Section 57: Having introduced these premises, he [Aristotle] then proceeds upwards [yartaqt] to the discussion of the corporeal and spiritual [or immaterial, rühaniyyah] parts of the world ... in his books [lit. “letters,” hurüj] on metaphysics, Aristotle proceeds upward [yartaqt] from       the             necessary               and

demonstrative premises to the exposition in Book Lambda of the unicity of the Creator.

He then proceeds downwards [i.e., from the First to the lower existents] and returns to an exposition of the soundness of his previous premises until they are treated in detail [ila an yastawftha].[641]

Ihsa

Sub-section 1:He [the metaphysician] then demonstrates that they [i.e., the various different classes of immaterial beings] on account of their multiplicity proceed upward [tartaqt] from the basest to the nobler, until they arrive at the last [i.e., God], which is perfect and in comparison to which nothing more perfect can exist.

Sub-section 2: He then examines after that all the remaining things by which God is described until they are treated in detail [ila an yastawftha kullaha].

Sub-section 3: He then examines the order of all of Its [the First’s] remaining acts on the existents until they are treated in detail [ila an yastawftha kullaha].

 

He then shows clearly that all of them [the existents] were originated from [hadathat 'an] the absolute creation of the Creator.

Section 56: Aristotle showed in his book entitled 'Theology that the One exists in all multiplicity . ... He [Aristotle] then shows that [thumma yubayyinu anna] the True One [al-wahid al-haqq] is that which endows the other existents with unity [afada sair al-mawjudat al-wahdiyyah].142

He then explains how the existents originated from [hadathat 'an] Him [God].

He then shows [wa-yubayyinu anna] . that He [God] is Truth [wa-annahu huwa l-haqq] ... that He is the One and First that endows all things except Himself with unity [huwa l-wahid al-awwal alladhl afada kull shay’in al-wahdah].

 

The above analysis and textual comparison demonstrate clearly the overlap in phrasing, contents, and outlook between Ihsa and Jam'. In view of this, we may formulate some important conclusions. First, the results show convincingly that al-Fârâbï considered Aristotle’s meta­physics to consist both in the investigation leading upward to the First or God and in the investigation of how the First or God relates to the other beings, bestows unity and existence on these beings, as well as how It created the world. According to al-Fârâbï, these two aspects of Aristotelian metaphysics were embodied in Metaphysics Book Lambda and in some works of the Neoplatonica arabica respectively, especially in Theology of Aristotle. In this regard, Jam' outlines the Aristotelian metaphysical project in a clear fashion, marking both stages of the met­aphysical inquiry, and identifying the texts that correspond to them. Ihsa, which was obviously modelled closely on the account in Jam', was written with this outline in mind: sub-section 1 corresponds to the upward investigation of Book Lambda, whereas sub-sections 2 and 3 correspond to the investigation going from the First to the other existents. One of the upshots of this conclusion is that, in spite of the view held by Mahdi, Druart, and others, al-Fârâbï clearly was not aware of the true origin of Theology of Aristotle and perceived it together with Metaphysics as forming an integrated metaphysical corpus, which he ascribed as a whole to Aristotle. This is stated explicitly in Jam, and it is unmistakably the premise on which the entire account of Ihsa ’ is written.[642]

Second, the terminological and conceptual parallels between Ihsa ’ and Jam’ clearly point to a common period of composition for these texts, which most likely corresponds to what I shall call ‘al-Fârâbï’s early Baghdad phase.’ Ihsa’ both continues the Alexandrian philosoph­ical tradition and also contains many idiosyncratic features—especially with regard to its adoption of the creationist paradigm already identified in Jam’, Jawabat, and Radd—two aspects which can best be explained by the influence of al-Fârâbï’s Christian teachers. This coheres with the fact that Ihsa projects a picture of the Alexandrian philosophical curriculum as it was transmitted and adapted by the Christian Syriac tradition to which al-Fârâbï’s teachers belonged. The classification of the sciences proposed in Ihsa, the emphasis on philo­sophical harmonization in Jam’, and the intention of elucidating the theological aim (gharad/skopós) of metaphysics in Ihsa and Aghrad (more on this treatise below), are all aspects that connect these works with the Alexandrian philosophical legacy that was revived in Baghdad. However, they possess a new raison d’etre, which is to natu­ralize philosophical praxis in the Islamic context and to show the inherent harmony between religion and philosophy. More specifically, they express key religious doctrines in philosophical language.[643] The foregoing suggests that these works were in all likelihood composed when al-Fârâbï was studying in the circle of the Syriac scholars in Baghdad.

Finally, and as a corollary, in both Ihsa’ and Jam’ the Neoplatonica arabica are used to buttress a creationist position that is compatible with religious dogma. This creationist position displays a unique inter- twinement of elements drawn from both the theological tradition and from the Arabic Neoplatonic works. God is defined as the First Principle, which confers oneness to all beings, but He is also a Creator God that creates the world absolutely—khalaqa in Ihsa’, abda’a in Jam’—and which is explicitly identified with Allah. This creationist connection is further strengthened by the common statement in Jam’ and Ihsa ’ that the existents are “originated from” (hadathat ‘an) God, a verbal formula that never appears in al-Fârâbï’s later metaphysical writings to define the activity of the immaterial entities. While al-Fârâbï explicitly attributes this cosmogonical position to Aristotle in Jam‘, Ihsa provides valuable additional evidence that he endorsed it him­self. In addition, the two texts define God similarly as the giver of unity (wahdah) in addition to existence (wujüd) to all beings. In this respect, Jam’ and Ihsa use the idiosyncratic expression “the True One” (al-wahid al-haqq) or a variant of it to describe God, with explicit reference to Aristotle in the former case. This expression appears fre­quently in Theology of Aristotle, thereby lending more weight to the hypothesis that this Neoplatonic source influenced both metaphysical accounts.[644]

But unlike Jam‘, which is ambiguous on this point, Ihsa is also note­worthy in that it explicitly identifies “multiple” (kathirah) immaterial beings, thereby indicating that al-Fârâbï at this stage in his life may have endorsed the theory of an intermediary level of immaterial existents between God and the world. As we have seen, however, this did not prevent him from defining God as the sole creator and cause of the cosmos, and the causative role he ascribes to these existents seems to have been minimal. This in turn might suggest a certain departure from the cosmogonical model of Jam’ and Jawabat, but the similarities between these works are in any case stronger than their differences. Hence, we may conclude that Ihsa was written from a similar philo­sophical standpoint and belongs to al-Fârâbï’s creationist phase together with Jam‘, Jawabat, and probably Radd.

2.2.2. Aghrad

This treatise is ambiguous and not easily classifiable. On the one hand, it bears striking terminological and doctrinal parallels with the crea­tionist treatises, especially Ihsa ’. On the other hand, its extreme brevity prevents a definitive conclusion as to how it may relate to the rest of the Fârâbïan corpus. Like the creationist works, and Ihsa ’ in particular, this treatise is imbued with the philosophical tradition of Alexandrian Aristotelianism and possesses a distinct curricular format. It also shares the aim of summarizing Aristotelian philosophy and of elucidating its relation to the revealed religions. This is clear from the author’s identi­fication of the highest object of metaphysics with “Allah,” whose name is systematically accompanied by the use of honorific formulas (Exalted be He, etc), as in the creationist works.[645] As A. Bertolacci observed, al-Fârâbï stresses the primacy of theology in the metaphysical inquiry and defines the overarching aim (gharad/skopós) of Metaphysics as the knowledge of the divinity, even though divine matters are expressly discussed only in one section (qism) of the work, namely, in Book Lambda.[646]

In this connection, however, al-Fârâbï’s statement that Metaphysics only lightly touches on “the Creator [al-barï], Praised and Exalted be He, the intellect, and the soul,” in spite of what “many people” (kathtr min al-nas) believe, should not in my view be construed as an indica­tion that he regarded these notions—including the study of God qua Creator—as being foreign to Aristotelian metaphysics.[647] It rather indi­cates that according to al-Fârâbï, Aristotle discussed these issues in depth in some of his other metaphysical works, i.e., Theology of Aristotle, which were therefore meant to complement Metaphysics. This interpre­tation is strongly supported by the analysis of the creationist treatises that was given previously, which showed that al-Fârâbï divided Aristotelian metaphysics into an ‘ascending’ part corresponding to Book Lambda, and a ‘descending’ part focusing on procession and God’s relation to the created existents and corresponding to the Neoplatonica arabica. In this respect, one should keep in mind that Aghrad is a summary of Metaphysics alone, and not a summary of the entire Aristotelian discipline of metaphysics as al-Fârâbï may have con­ceived it.

Some hints supporting this view can be found in the treatise itself, although they are not decisive. In his description of the subject matter of metaphysics, al-Fârâbï states that one of the objects of study is “the principle common to all existing beings [al-mabda l-mushtarak li-jamt al-mawjüdat], namely, the thing that should be called God.” Now, al-Fârâbï frequently uses the term mabda in his other works to refer to an efficient principle of existence, and it is presumably in this sense that he intends it here as well. This interpretation is strengthened by the statement made shortly thereafter that God is a “principle of the existent in the absolute sense [mabda’ li-l-mawjüd al-mutlaq]”i4j And in the same treatise al-Fârâbï describes Book Lambda as dealing with “the principle of substance and of all existence” (mabda’ l-jawhar wa- l-wujüd kulliht) and with the “establishment of His [God’s] special existence” (ithbat huwiyyatiht).[648] [649] The general point implied in these passages seems to be that God is the principle of existence of all entities and the universal and efficient principle of ‘what exists’ (al-mawjüd). He is not only a final cause, but an efficient cause of existence as well.

Since these metaphysical ideas and this conception of God as an effi­cient principle of existence are absent from the Greek Book Lambda and are either absent or not articulated in any length in its Arabic ver­sions, it would seem that al-Fârâbï is construing this text through the lens of other works, such as Theology of Aristotle. In this case as well, the best way to construe these statements of Aghrad is to assume al-Farabi’s access to a ‘metaphysics file’ similar to the one compiled in the Kindi-circle. This file juxtaposed Book Lambda with other texts such as Theology of Aristotle with a harmonizing intention. This file presumably informed al-Farabi’s particular understanding of Aristotelian metaphysics, even though he also departed from al-Kindi on other key points, notably on the place of theology in metaphysics. At any rate, it would seem that Aghrad is not a straightforward and faithful exposition of Aristotelian metaphysics. It shares many key fea­tures with the creationist treatises, even though it neglects the distinc­tive language of creation that is found in these works.

There is another point of interest for our purposes. In his extremely condensed summary of Book Lambda, al-Farabi posits several imma­terial beings after the First (al-mawjüdat al-mufariqah allati badahü), whose existence is said to constitute part of the subject matter of this book.[650] This statement is comparable to the fleeting reference to a mul­tiplicity of immaterial beings in Ihsa’. On this point both Ihsa ’ and Aghrad seem to mark a certain departure from Jam’ and Jawabat, even though all of these works continue to describe God as the only efficient cause and demiurge of the universe. However, if Ihsa’ and Aghrad both belong to a slightly later stage of al-Farabi’s creationist phase, as I am inclined to think, then this raises the question of how al-Farabi would have reconciled the doctrine of the contingency and temporal finitude of the corporeal world with the doctrine of a plurality of immaterial beings distinct from God. Would these immaterial beings be eternal and the corporeal world temporally finite? Or would all levels of exist­ence—both the corporeal and immaterial—be originated and destroyed by God? It is interesting to note that a similar ambiguity underlies the account of creation in Theology of Aristotle.[651]

I cannot provide a compelling explanation of these questions at the present time. However, this ambiguity might be alleviated by means of the developmentalist approach adopted in this book. Accordingly, Ihsa and Aghrad would embody a later stage of al-Farabi’s creation­ist phase, in that they explicitly posit a level of immaterial beings between God and the world. Al-Farabi would have introduced this theory in his metaphysical system, even though he continued to uphold the doctrines of the temporal finitude of the world and of the absolute creative power of God. It is even possible that al-Fârâbï believed that both the intelligible and corporeal existents were created and that neither is actually eternal.[652] Putting this issue aside, the crea­tionist position identified in Jam’ seems to underlie the metaphysical accounts of Ihsa ’ and Aghrad.

2.3. A Common Cosmogonical Paradigm

In the previous paragraphs, I argued that Jam’, Jawabat, Radd, Ihsa’, and possibly Aghrad were most likely written from a similar creationist viewpoint indebted to Neoplatonica arabica and the Philoponian tradi­tion. This creationist paradigm is defined chiefly by: a) the absolute creation of the world ex nihilo and with time; b) the idea that God cre­ated the world as a result of His will; c) the finitude of the temporal existence of the world; d) the idea that time is the measure of the heav­enly motion and comes into existence together with the heavens; and e) the assumption that God can be described using both philosophical terminology (First Agent, First Cause, etc.) and religious terminology (Allah, the Creator, the Originator, etc.), and thus that religious truths can be formulated in philosophical language. Interestingly, this crea­tionist picture can also be found in an almost identical form in the works of some Jewish authors, such as Isaac Israeli and Saadia Gaon, which shows that it was widespread and highly influential in the vari­ous philosophical circles that flourished during the classical period of Islamic civilization. In addition, however, it may have penetrated the circle of the Christian Peripatetic scholars in Baghdad to which al-Fârâbï gravitated. While it is customary in studies on Arabic thought to oppose the Christian Peripatetics to al-Kindï and his legacy, little is known about entire aspects of their philosophy, including their cosmology, and so this judgment should not be accepted a priori and without certain reservations. For this reason, and because these Christian thinkers represent a crucial link in the reconstruction of al-Farabi’s philosophical development, I will provide in what follows additional insight into al-Kindi’s views on creation, briefly mention the Jewish thinkers, and subsequently provide a tentative reconstruction of Matta ibn Yûnus’ cosmology on the basis of the surviving fragments of his commentary on Physics. This will in turn lead to a clearer apprecia­tion of the many links between their works and al-Farabi’s creationist treatises.

2.3.1.    Al-Kindt on Body, Motion, and Time

Al-Kindi’s creationist view has been discussed quite extensively in the modern literature, and so I will limit myself here to certain features that have in my opinion not been sufficiently stressed.[653] In his various works on cosmology, al-Kindi defines God’s act of creation by relying on terms derived from the Qur’an and the Arabic theological tradition, as well as from the philosophical culture prevalent during his time. Hence, God is called the “Originator” and “Creator” (al-mubdi, al-bari, al-muhdith),[654] as well as “the First Agent” (al-fail al-awwal), the “First Cause” (al-‘illah al-üla), and “the end of each cause” (ghayah kull ‘illah).[655]

Al-Kindi holds that God created the world from non-being (‘an lays) and as a result of His will.[656] Although the expression “creation in time” has often been used—confusedly—to describe al-Kindi’s position, he regarded creation itself as something atemporal, which means both that it did not unfold over a period of time and that it did not take place at a particular point in time—time already being in existence. On the contrary, time is defined as the measure of bodily motion, and its exist­ence is therefore concomitant with body and motion, and more specifi­cally with the movement of the first body, i.e., the heavens. Body, motion, and time, al-Kindi repeatedly stresses, were brought into exist­ence together and cannot exist independently one from the other. They possess only a finite existence and are not eternal. Hence, although creation itself is atemporal, the world’s existence is clearly finite: it has a beginning and an end and will eventually be destroyed by God.[657]

This account is relatively straightforward, but al-Kindi adds other features that complicate it somewhat. As we saw in the previous sec­tion, he believes that the heavens are made of a special substance that is in nature incorruptible and unchanging, and that this heavenly sub­stance will remain unchanged until God decides to destroy the world.[658] This celestial substance is therefore potentially everlasting, even though it will effectively cease to exist at a certain point due to divine decree. Interestingly, al-Kindi seems to extend this view to motion and time as well. Since the heavenly body as a whole is made of this special sub­stance, its motion and in turn the time which measures its motion, are theoretically and potentially everlasting. Hence, the phenomenon of celestial motion, for instance, is not only regular, unchanging, and con­tinuous, but also potentially infinite, although it will cease when God decides to destroy the world.

The foregoing helps us to understand in what sense al-Kindi in one of his treatises repeatedly uses the terms daim and abadan to qualify the celestial bodies. This usage might at first glance appear surprising, since these terms often mean “eternal” or “perpetual” in the Arabic philosophical and theological contexts. As al-Kindi writes, the heav­enly body is “a living being that is always [or eternally] in actuality” (hayy bi-l-fil abadan); it is endowed with “perpetual life” (hayat daimah); its motion is “perpetual” (da’iman).[659] In this case, however, and in light of what was said above, the terms daim and abadan should not be construed as meaning “(actually) eternal,” but rather as meaning “continuous,” or better “potentially unceasing or perpetual.” Al-Kindi thus manages to combine an adapted version of aether and the notion of the continuous and potentially perpetual motion of the heavens with the ideas of the temporal finitude of the world and of its absolute crea­tion. While seemingly contradictory, al-Kindi’s position hinges on a subtle interpretation of the distinction between “actual perpetuity” and “potential perpetuity” or, as he writes, between “potentially infinite” (la nihayah bi-l-quwwah or min jihat al-imkan) and “actually infinite” (la nihayah bi-l-fil).[660] Since, according to al-Kindi, an actual infinite is impossible, the world, including the heavens, its motion, and the time that measures it, are necessarily finite, and this even though they are potentially perpetual. The subtlety—and to some extent ambiguity—of al-Kindi’s view is conveyed in his statement that “the body, motion, and time [of the universe] are not eternal [azaliyyah], even though they are an eternal essence at the beginning of existence [bal dhat azaliyyah fi bad al-anniyyah] .”[661]

Consequently, al-Kindi’s view shares several key parallels with the doctrine articulated in al-Farabi’s creationist treatises. The ideas that God created the world through His will; that it is an absolute creation from nothing, or from non-being; that creation itself is atemporal; that time is concomitant with body and motion and comes to be with the creation of the heavens; and that the world and the heavens possess a beginning and an end and will be destroyed, even though the heavens are made of a special incorruptible substance, are all features that can be found in al-Kindi’s cosmological treatises and in Jam’ and Jawabat. These treatises are also characterized by a dual description of God that relies on both the philosophical terminology of efficient causation and the orthodox Islamic names of God as Creator. Many of these features can be traced to the Philoponian tradition in Islam, which shows that the Arabic translations of this thinker’s writings had a lasting and dif­fused impact on cosmological theories in classical Baghdad, the metropolis in which both al-Kindi and al-Farabi were active.[662] Having elucidated this connection, one may turn to the question of how other major thinkers of this period fit in this cosmological tradition.

2.3.2.    Isaac Israeli and Saadia Gaon on Creation

The creationist views of two of the most important Jewish thinkers who flourished during the Abbasid period will be briefly examined, in order to show their overlap with those of al-Kindi and al-Farabi in his early works. Saadia Gaon (d. 942 CE) provides a detailed account of creation and surveys the various arguments proving the existence of the Creator in his work entitled The Book of Beliefs and Opinions and in his com­mentary on Book of Creation. He defends the theses of the ex nihilo creation of the world by God (ikhtaraa la min shay’), of divine voli­tion, and of the temporal finitude of the universe. The world and the heavens are said to have a beginning and an end, to have been created with time and all at once (dafatan wahidatan), and to be finite (mutandhiyyatdn).[663]

The creationist position of Isaac Israeli (d. ca. 955 CE) is more ambiguous and has been the object of some debate in the secondary literature, but here I will merely highlight a few salient features of his doctrine without engaging in its deeper implications.[664] According to the surviving writings of Israeli, God is described as “the Creator” (al-bart), as well as “the First,” “the Agent” and “the Cause of causes.” God willed the ex nihilo and absolute creation of the world, or alterna­tively, of intellect through which He created the other entities, and He subsequently appointed the celestial sphere as governor of the proc­esses of generation and corruption in the sublunary world.[665] This the­ory of creation is at any rate presumably not an eternalist one, implying that the world has a finite existence.[666] Also noteworthy is that Israeli’s definitions of ‘innovation’ (al-ibda) as “making existent existences from the non-existent” (ta’yis al-aysat min lays) and of time as “an extension separated by the movement of the sphere” echo al-Kindi’ views on the one hand and al-Farabi’s Jam’ on the other.[667]

This brief overview shows that the creationist doctrine adopted by Isaac Israeli and Saadia Gaon correspond on essential points to the one that can be found in al-Kindï’s works and in al-Fârâbï’s early treatises, especially Jam. The main features of this doctrine, as well as the Neoplatonic and Philoponian sources underlying it, overlap to a remarkable degree, implying that this syncretistic creationist para­digm was shared by both Muslim and Jewish authors active in Baghdad during the ninth and tenth centuries. This fact lends further weight to the hypothesis that al-Fârâbï adhered to it during a period of his life.

2.3.3.    Matta ibn Yunus Cosmology and his Commentary on Physics

One element of the puzzle that remains obscure is the connection between al-Fârâbï and his teacher Matta ibn Yûnus with respect to their views on cosmology. Since virtually all of the latter’s many writings have perished, it is particularly difficult to assess in what sense he may have influenced al-Fârâbï during his stay in Baghdad and whether he may in his capacity as Christian thinker have contributed to shaping the latter’s creationist position. Fortunately, however, various excerpts from Mattâ ibn Yûnus’ commentary on Aristotle’s Physics have sur­vived, which enable us to shed some light on this important question. In what follows, I analyze certain key passages from this commentary, which has rarely been studied, and which stands as a unique piece of evidence to better understand the early stage of al-Fârâbï’s philosophi­cal development and his relation to his Christian teachers.

The commentatorial notes by Mattâ ibn Yûnus that have come down to us focus on Books 2-3 of Physics and were added to the translation of this work executed by Ishâq ibn Hunayn sometime in the late ninth or early tenth century CE.[668] Although they are not directly concerned with cosmological issues, the many remarks Mattâ ibn Yûnus makes with regard to Aristotle’s physical principles, such as form, matter, motion, etc., enable us to identify some key features of his cosmology. The global cosmological picture that can be reconstructed from these excerpts appears at first glance thoroughly Aristotelian, but I will focus here only on those aspects which depart from this norm and which are of direct relevance to the issue at stake.

First, it is striking, albeit not surprising, that Matta ibn Yûnus fol­lows the late antique philosophical tradition in defining Aristotle’s divinity both as a final and efficient cause, with the implication that God is not only a mover or first cause of motion, but, in addition, responsible for the origination and existence of the world. This view appears clearly in many passages of the commentary, where Matta ibn Yûnus describes God as “the First Principle” (al-mabda l-awwal) with respect to the end (ghayah), as “the Unmoved Agent” (al-fail ghayr al-mutaharrik), as “the First Agent” (al-fail al-awwal), and as “the Creator” (al-bari and al-khallaq).[669] These last two terms clearly indi­cate that Matta ibn Yûnus considered the supreme deity to be not only a final cause, but also an efficient cause and a demiurge, Who could be defined by means of the Arabic theological vocabulary that was shared by both Christians and Muslims during this time.[670] What we witness in these excerpts, then, is the survival of the late antique commentato- rial tradition on Aristotle and its accommodation within a monotheis­tic model. This seems to have been a pattern in the early Arabic context, judging from the variety of works in which it can be observed, which range from al-Kindi’s treatises and the commentaries of the Baghdad Christian scholars to the Neoplatonica arabica as well as to al-Fârâbï’s Jam’ and Jawabat. In contrast to this trend, however, it should be noted that the Arabic names of God as creator are entirely absent from al-Fârâbï’s mature metaphysical treatises, which refer to the highest divinity by relying solely on the philosophical vocabulary of causation (First Cause, First Principle, etc.).

It is difficult to draw the outlines of Mattâ ibn Yûnus’ cosmology more precisely, due to the lack of relevant information in his commen­tary. In particular, one hesitates to reach any conclusion concerning his position on the eternity or finitude of the world and on the mode in which God created it. Some of his statements seem to point to the infin­ity of time and motion, which could imply that Mattâ ibn Yûnus believed in the eternity of the corporeal world, and thus in the eternal creation of the world by God. For instance, Mattâ ibn Yûnus mentions that the motions of the heavenly bodies are perpetual (daiman), as are certain sublunary phenomena, such as the seasons, which occur on a cyclical basis.[671] In addition, his discussion of motion seems to rest on the assumption that this principle is infinitely continuous, even though a first mover must be posited to explain it.[672] It could very well be, then, that Mattâ ibn Yûnus endorsed Aristotle’s thesis of the world’s eternality, which he somehow reconciled with the notion of a Creator God and thus with the proposition of the world’s eternal creation or causation.

But this conclusion is not devoid of ambiguity and is not supported by other statements that appear in the commentary. Indeed, there are some reasons to think that Mattâ ibn Yûnus may have upheld a crea­tionist theory similar to the one adopted by al-Fârâbï and al-Kindï. To begin with, there is the strong likelihood that the term daiman used by Mattâ ibn Yûnus to refer to the motions of the heavenly bodies should be understood as meaning merely “continuous” or “potentially perpet­ual,” rather than “eternal,” with the same meaning as the one encoun­tered in al-Kindï’s treatises. This is suggested by the context in which this statement appears, which consists of a discussion of the purposive­ness of nature and of the source of motion in things. Having just stressed that celestial motion does not occur by chance, but for a pur­pose, since it is regular and perpetual, Mattâ ibn Yûnus then inquires whether its cause is inherent in the heavens or lies outside of it. And he writes:

Now, the world as a whole is finite [wa-l-‘alam kulluhü mutanahin], but infinity cannot exist in what is finite. Hence, the nature of this infinite power [tabïat al-quwwah ghayr al-mutanahiyyah] must exist separately from these [finite] natures [tabai‘].[673]

This passage immediately brings to mind al-Kindi’s own proofs for the world’s creation and his views on finitude and infinity as discussed in the previous section. Although it is not spelled out in detail, the impli­cation of this argument could be the same as the one reached by al-Kindi: the world is finite and therefore possesses a finite power, with the implication that time and motion continue to exist as long as an external infinite power, i.e., God’s power, is conferred upon it. The per­petual rotation of the heavens is not due to its inherent nature, but rather dependent on the will and power of the Creator. This passage should be compared to another statement made by Matta ibn Yûnus to the effect that the “revolution of the heaven is continuous [or perpet­ual] [daiman] due to [‘an] the agent [al-fail, i.e., God].”[674] In this case as well, the intended meaning could be that the celestial motion is only potentially “continuous” and “perpetual” and exists during the period of time allotted by God. Hence, we seem to find in Matta ibn Yûnus’ work the double thesis of the creation of the world—clearly expressed by his description of God as al-khallaq and al-bari—and of the idea that the body of the world, as well as motion and time, while finite, derive potential perpetuity from the divine power.[675] This cluster of doctrines, which is a marking trait of al-Kindi’s works and which can also be traced to an excerpt of Philoponus arabus, could very well have been adopted by Matta ibn Yûnus in his Physics commentary, in spite of the fragmentary and ambiguous evidence.[676]

If the foregoing interpretation is correct, Matta ibn Yûnus could be connected with al-Kindi and the Arabic Philoponian tradition on the one hand, and with the early Baghdad phase of al-Farabi on the other, thereby uncovering an intellectual lineage that has not yet been fully acknowledged in previous studies on early Arabic thought. As the anal­ysis showed, a cluster of somewhat idiosyncratic cosmological features can be found in an identical form in al-Kindi’s cosmological works, in Isaac Israeli’s and Saadia Gaon’s writings, and in al-Farabi’s Jam, Jawabat, Radd, and Ihsa ’. These features may also underlie Matta ibn Yûnus’ commentary, thus making him a link between al-Farabi and these earlier philosophers.[677] As P. Lettinck observed, Matta ibn Yûnus relied extensively on Philoponus’ commentary on Physics to compose his own commentary on this work, and it is likely, in addition, that he knew excerpts of Philoponus’ Against Aristotle, which circulated widely in the Arabic context.[678] The Philoponian trend identified in the case of al-Kindi and al-Farabi seems to play an important role in this case as well, especially with regard to the proposition of the world’s finitude, which could very well form part of a larger cosmogonical picture in the philosophy of Matta ibn Yûnus. This interpretation nevertheless remains hypothetical at this stage, due to the fragmentary nature of his work.[679]

2.3.4.    Ibn Suwar on Creation

Abü l-Khayr al-H asan Ibn Suwar, who flourished during the late tenth century CE and was a disciple of Yahya ibn ‘Adi in Baghdad, provides slightly later, but equally valuable testimony for our discussion on crea­tion. By virtue of his intellectual lineage, he is connected to al-Farabi, with whom Yahya had studied. It is remarkable in this respect that Ibn Suwar wrote a short treatise on the subject of creation that contains virtually all the essential points discussed in the previous analysis.[680] This treatise was written in order to criticize the kalam proof from bod­ies and accidents aiming to show the world’s contingency. Ibn Suwar begins his treatise by identifying the shortcomings of the mutakallimun and by refuting their handling of this creationist argument, and he sub­sequently explains why John Philoponus’ argument for creation from the finite power of the world should be preferred.

What is important for our purposes is the insight Ibn Suwar pro­vides in the course of his exposition into his own view on creation. His position, which is clearly inscribed in the creationist paradigm out­lined previously, consists of the following points: a) God can be described both as a Creator and a cause; b) God created the world all at once and not over a period of time; c) God created the world through His will (Ibn Suwar cites scripture to this effect: “He [God] said [to a thing “be”], and it was [qala fa-kcrna]”)[681]'2; d) time is the measure of heavenly motion, and its existence follows that of the orbs; e) eternity belongs to God only, while the world may be said to be temporally per­petual. It should be noted that Ibn Suwar, like al-Kindi and al-Farabi in Jam, ascribes this creationist position to Aristotle.

These doctrinal points, as well as the terminology used throughout the treatise, are identical to the ones that can be found in the accounts of al-Kindi and al-Farabi in his creationist works. Unlike these authors, however, Ibn Suwar does not explicitly mention the temporal finitude of the world and its eventual destruction by God. This omission, when combined with his view on the atemporal causation of the world, could lead to the impression that Ibn Suwar believed in eternal creation.[682] In spite of this, there is evidence that Ibn Suwar’s view on creation is in fact identical to that of al-Kindi and al-Farabi on this point as well. To begin with, Ibn Suwar himself states that the world is “not eternal,” by which he clearly means to say that its temporal existence is finite, and he also endorses one of Philoponus’ proofs for the contingency of the world.[683]

Moreover, he refers to the authority of Proclus (i.e., of Proclus ara­bus) to argue that the term azali can be applied to both God and the world, but has a different meaning in each case: in the case of God, azali means “true everlastingness” (dahr), while in the case of the world it is merely synonymous with time (zaman). And Ibn Suwar pointedly adds that time is what befits the contingent (al-mutakawwin).[684] These statements should surely be understood in the same way as al-Kindi’s identical statement that the world is daim and azali, even though God alone is truly eternal. Hence, it would seem that, like al-Kindi, Ibn Suwar regarded the existence of the world as being temporally continu­ous and (potentially) perpetual, but not as something actually eternal. This in turn means that while God’s creation is atemporal, the world itself has a beginning and an end.

When combined with the focus on Philoponus and the creationist reading of Aristotle, all of these points make Ibn Suwar’s treatise a mir­ror image of al-Kindi’s and al-Farabi’s accounts on creation. This indi­cates that the creationist doctrine identified previously continued through al-Farabi to some of his disciples, and even to disciples of his disciples. This historical continuity and the endurance of this cosmo­gonical paradigm in Baghdadi philosophical circles with which al-Farabi was associated lends even more weight to the hypothesis that he adopted this particular creationist position during a period of his life.[685]

2.4.    Conclusion

The previous analysis has shown that several works by al-Farabi, namely, Jam', Jawdbdt, Radd, Ihsa’, and possibly Aghrâd, share idiosyn­cratic terminological and conceptual features and a common creation­ist doctrine, and that these features and creationist doctrine are inscribed in a ‘cosmogonical paradigm’ shared by many other Muslim, Christian, and Jewish thinkers who flourished during the ninth and tenth centuries. This cosmogonical or creationist paradigm can be attributed convincingly to al-Kindi, Saadia Gaon, and Ibn Suwar, and possibly also to Isaac Israeli and Matta ibn Yûnus, even though the evi­dence is sparse in their case. It seems to have been adopted by Yahya ibn ‘Adi as well, one of al-Farabi’s immediate disciples.[686] This is not to say that these thinkers shared an identical view on creation, but rather that their position on this issue agrees on fundamental points, which, when taken together, constitute a distinct and clearly recognizable cos­mogonical model. The salient traits of this paradigm are a syncretistic creationist doctrine combining elements from the Philoponus arabus, the Neoplatonica arabica, and the Biblical and Quranic texts, as well as the conviction that religion and philosophy are not opposed and that fundamental religious tenets can be formulated in philosophical lan­guage; hence, the juxtaposition in all of these works of religious and philosophical terminology to describe God and His act of creation and the frequent reliance on citations from scripture to illustrate a particu­lar point.[687]

The central place of Aristotle’s Metaphysics, Book Lambda, and of the Neoplatonica arabica in al-Farabi’s approach to metaphysics and in his creationist doctrine suggests that these were in some ways a con­tinuation of al-Kindi’s philosophical project.[688] Accordingly, I would hypothesize that during this period of his life, al-Farabi had access to a variant of what F. Zimmermann called the “metaphysics file,” which had been assembled in the Kindi-circle some time before. This file con­sisted of an arrangement of these Aristotelian and Neoplatonic works into a coherent program of study.[689] This would account for the fact that al-Farabi discusses Book Lambda of Metaphysics and Theology of Aristotle side by side in his works and why he probably considered both to be genuine Aristotelian texts. It would also explain his intention to reconcile Greek philosophy with the Islamic revelation, which was a priority of the Kindi-circle.

But this raises the thorny question of how these authors interpreted the doctrine of creation in the Neoplatonica arabica. For they employ the common strategy of using Theology of Aristotle and germane mate­rial from the Arabic Neoplatonic corpus to argue for the contingency and non-eternity of the world. In this connection, it has been widely assumed in the modern literature that Theology of Aristotle articulates a theory of eternal creation, but the fact remains that some authors, such as al-Kindi, al-Farabi during his creationist phase, probably Isaac Israeli,[690] Ibn Suwar, and presumably others, did not interpret it in this fashion, surely with regard to the corporeal world, and perhaps even with regard to the intelligible world.

As P. Adamson has noted, the doctrine of creation this work puts forth is in many ways ambiguous, and it would have been relatively easy for the medieval authors to construe it through a creationist and non-eternalist lens.[691] For instance, the Adaptor (of Theology of Aristotle) at one point states that “the world is not abolished entirely,” therefore implying that part of it (presumably its corporeal part) will perish. But even with respect to the intellectual world, the Adaptor hints at the potential finite existence of the immaterial beings: “the intellect does not dissolve or corrupt, but rather it endures forever and abidingly, unless He [God] wishes it [to go back] to [its] first state, that it per­ish.”[692] Hence, we should note that the Adaptor, like al-Kindi, seems to uphold the potential perpetuity of the world, but also leaves open the possibility that God may want to destroy it at one point in the future. This ambiguity might explain why al-Farabi in Jam’ defends the thesis of the world’s temporal finitude and contingency and at the same time relies on Theology of Aristotle to develop his creationist argumentation. The conclusion, then, is that the upholders of the cosmological para­digm described above probably construed the Neoplatonica arabica in a manner that suited their own creationist agenda. However, while it is clear that they conceived of the corporeal world as being temporally finite, contingent, and subject to future destruction, further research is required to settle the point of whether they also believed that the intel­lectual world would undergo such destruction.[693]

In any case, it should be noted that the main exponents of this crea­tionist model defined themselves chiefly as philosophers and were operating outside of the main Muslim theological circles of their time. Indeed, many theologians probably regarded this harmonization of philosophy and religion, as well as some aspects of their cosmogonical position, with suspicion. As we shall see in a later section, the various features constituting this creationist paradigm, as well as the funda­mental intention of reconciling scripture and philosophy, will be either abandoned or profoundly transformed in al-Fârâbï’s later cosmological works. In that sense, and in spite of what some scholars have argued, the creationist picture articulated in Jam’ and Jawâbât should defi­nitely not be assimilated to the cosmology of al-Fârâbï’s emanationist treatises.

The intellectual milieu associated with the creationist paradigm identified above is defined primarily by the geographic and cultural centrality of Baghdad during this period. This urban environment ena­bled close interactions between religious and philosophical ideas, which are reflected in these thinkers’ ongoing attempt to establish an adequate philosophical framework for religious tenets and thereby to make philosophy a legitimate and widely accepted activity. In al-Fârâbï’s creationist works in particular, there is a conspicuous tendency to Islamicize philosophy or to philosophize the Islamic revelation.[694] While this trend found a clear and outstanding embodiment in al-Fârâbï’s early treatises, it endured well into the tenth and eleventh centuries and found a new formulation—this time in relation to Christianity—in the works of the Baghdad thinkers who were directly or indirectly connected with al-Fârâbï, such as Yahyâ ibn ‘Adï and Ibn Suwâr. In that sense, the previous analysis also sheds light on this later phase, in that it uncovers a new link and intellectual congruity between al-Fârâbï and these Baghdad thinkers, who in many ways continued the cosmological project begun by their master.[695]

2.5.    Falsafat Aristu ta lis

In light of the foregoing, and turning to the rest of the Fârâbïan corpus, it is worthwhile to examine the views expressed in al-Fârâbï’s other cos­mological and metaphysical works and to assess their contents. How do they compare with regard to celestial matter and creation to the cluster of works examined previously? Do they also adopt the ‘creation­ist paradigm’ highlighted above? Or do they articulate other views on time and the existence of the universe?

As was shown earlier, Falsafat Aristu ta lis articulates a revised ver­sion of the Aristotelian theory of aether. On the one hand, like Radd, it contrasts aether to the other four elements and establishes a qualitative distinction between sublunary and superlunary matter that is in line with the Peripatetic tradition. On the other hand, it mentions the form and matter (the hylomorphic nature) of aether and also defines it as the cause of the other elements, thereby departing slightly from On the Heavens. But what is the view on the creation of matter adopted in this treatise?

Al-Fârâbï says very little about the question of the creation or eter­nity of the world in Falsafat Aristu ta lis. This is somewhat surprising given that this work focuses not only on the logical and psychological doctrines of the Stagirite, but also on his physics.[696] There are neverthe­less a few hints in the text suggesting that al-Fârâbï upheld an eternalist position and ascribed eternalism to Aristotle as well. In one passage al-Fârâbï mentions the infinite number of moved things; in another he describes the “perpetual circular motion” (al-harakah al-mustadirah al-daimah) of the celestial bodies.[697] In addition, al-Fârâbï discusses in detail the role of the Agent Intellect and the celestial bodies in sublu­nary generation and corruption, a theory which is characteristic of his emanationist treatises.[698] These hints are brief and do not constitute decisive evidence, but they definitely point to an eternalist position and suggest that al-Fârâbï’s interpretation of Aristotle’s cosmology had evolved by the time he was writing this work. If this hypothesis is correct, then it would mean that al-Fârâbï rejected the creationist posi­tion he combines with aether in Jam, Jawdbdt, and Radd and had already moved toward a conception of eternal causality, in a fashion akin to that expounded in the emanationist treatises.[699]

One point should be examined in more detail. Had al-Fârâbï developed his theory of the separate intellects when he wrote Falsafat AristittdIts? Does this treatise broach the topic of metaphysical causal­ity and of an intermediary level of intellects between God and the material world? As was stated above, al-Fârâbï says little about crea­tion and causation in this treatise. Although it has been suggested that this is because he is describing Aristotle’s philosophy and considered emanation foreign to the Stagirite’ system, this omission can best be explained in my view by the fact that al-Fârâbï restricts his survey to logic and natural philosophy and barely touches on metaphysical issues. Since al-Fârâbï does not address metaphysics in this work in any depth, it is not surprising that the theme of immaterial causation is left out.[700]

In spite of this, some crucial evidence can be gleaned from this trea­tise with regard to secondary causation and the presence of an interme­diate level of intellectual beings. When speaking about the rational faculty or intellect (aql) in humans, for instance, al-Fârâbï describes it as an “efficient principle” (mabda’fail), and “a cause and principle by way of finality” (sabab wa-mabda ‘aid tartq al-ghdyah), formulations which already hint to a Neoplatonizing interpretation of Aristotelian noetics.[701] This is accentuated some lines later, when al-Fârâbï posits the necessary existence of an Agent Intellect (‘aqlfa'al) to account for human intellection. This Agent Intellect is always actual, separated from matter, eternal, and continuously acting on the sublunary world. It is a substance distinct from the human mind, which it actualizes, and it is, furthermore, not identifiable with God. It is defined as an efficient, final, and formal principle and governs, together with the celestial bod­ies, the realm of sublunary nature, where it participates in the processes of generation and corruption.[702]

This passage from Falsafat shows beyond doubt that al-Fârâbï pos­ited at least one intermediary separate intellect between the First and the sublunary world and that he ascribed this view to Aristotle. In doing so, he followed certain Neoplatonists in construing the active intellect vaguely described in On the Soul 3.4-5 as an eternal and sepa­rate substance endowed with causative powers. This conclusion is important in various respects. First, it undermines the view that al-Fârâbï is expounding a pure or authentic Aristotelian doctrine in this work. Apart from the fact that it is contradicted by evidence drawn from the work itself, this interpretation suffers from its ahistorical character, which bypasses the influence that the secular tradition of late antique commentaries had on al-Fârâbï. The foregoing analysis con­firms that al-Fârâbï relied on Neoplatonic material in most, if not all, of his Aristotelian’ works to interpret the Stagirite, as was shown already in the case of Ihsa ’, and as will also be shown later on in the case of Fl l-‘aql.[703] Falsafat Aristütalls is no exception, and it is likely that this would have been even more conspicuous had al-Fârâbï included Aristotle’s metaphysics in his survey. Second, and taken together with the hints pointing to an eternalist position, it shows that Falsafat Aristütalls shares a metaphysical and cosmological connection with the late metaphysical treatises, Ara’ and Siyasah. This work therefore does not contain theories that depart radically from al-Fârâbï’s emanationist treatises and which would justify a division of the Fârâbïan corpus in two opposed parts, an Aristotelian, and a Neoplatonic.

These results nevertheless do not enable us to decide whether al-Fârâbï had already developed a full-fledged theory of the thawânt when writing this work, as he explicitly mentions only one intellect apart from God, i.e., the Agent Intellect. Regardless of this issue, Falsafat Aristü ta lis can be compared with the emanationist treatises on various points of doctrine: infinite time and motion, and the conception that time arises from the perpetual revolution of the heavens; the influence of the heavenly bodies on the sublunary elements; and the existence of a separate intellect (and possibly separate intellects) that exercises effi­cient and final causation on the sublunary world by intervening in human reflection and in the processes of generation and corruption.[704] In conclusion, then, and in spite of some ambiguity, our basic assump­tion concerning this work should be that it upholds some of the theo­ries that later formed the crux of al-Fârâbï’s mature metaphysical treatises. This makes Falsafat Aristü ta lis and its account of matter and causation—as brief as it is—an early sketch for Ara’ and Siyasah and possibly a transitional work between Jam, Ihsa’, and Aghrad, and the emanationist treatises.

2.6.    The Eternalist Paradigm: Ara’, Siyasah, Tahstl, Fusu l, and Ft l-aql

If there is a chance that al-Fârâbï interpreted Aristotelian cosmology through a creationist lens during the early Baghdad period of his life, and that Aristotle’s aether theory was thus combined with the belief in the creation of the world, al-Fârâbï’s more mature works indicate that his perception of these issues underwent considerable development later on in his life. This philosophical maturation is already apparent in Falsafat Aristütalts, which mentions Aristotle’s aether theory, but ignores creationism, and where several, albeit brief, statements point to a doctrine of eternal causation. But the eternalist position is developed in a much more consummated form in Ara’ and Siyasah, while some essential features also appear in Tahstl, Fusül, and Ft l-aql.

In these treatises, al-Fârâbï not only rejects aether and any recogniz­able theory of celestial matter to provide a new formulation of the com­position of the celestial bodies based on the concept of substrate. In addition, he also provides an entirely new account of the existence of the heavens and of the material world, which reflects a shift from a creationist paradigm to one of eternal causality that unfolds on several different ontological levels. In this new model, the concepts of demi- urgy and efficient causation are extended to various metaphysical enti­ties of an intellectual nature (called al-thawant), which are responsible for causing the existence of the various celestial bodies. In turn, these celestial bodies act on the sublunary world through their powers and motions and cause the existence of prime matter (al-maddah al-üla), which underlies the process of change in all the hylomorphic existents. One striking feature of this scheme is that the First is not involved directly in the creation of matter—both of the celestial substance and sublunary prime matter—since it only causes the existence of a single immaterial being.

Some key features of this eternalist model of causation appear in Tahstl. While this work does not dwell on this subject, one passage in particular allows us to assess the nature of al-Fârâbï’s metaphysics at this stage in his life and to situate this work vis-à-vis the later emana- tionist treatises. In the context of describing the metaphysical method and its subject matter, al-Fârâbï explains that the metaphysical inquiry will eventually result in the postulation of a being to which the four causes do not apply and which will itself be the First Principle (al-mabda’ l-awwal) of all the other beings. This being about which al-Fârâbï speaks is none other than the First, which receives a detailed treatment in the opening part of Ara’. Al-Fârâbï then mentions the other meta­physical beings:

When he [the philosopher] reaches this stage, he should examine after this whatever occurs necessarily in the [other] existents if [it is posited] that this existence is their principle and the cause of their existence [fa-idha waqafa 'ala hadha fahasa ba'd dhalika amma yalzamu an yahsula ft l-mawjüdat idha kana dhalika l-wujüd mabdaaha wa-sabab wujüdiha]. He begins with the existent which is most prior and closest to this existence [i.e., the First], until he reaches the last existent in rank and the most remote to this existence.[705]

Since al-Fârâbï is focusing on metaphysics in this passage, there can be little doubt that the other existents he mentions apart from the First are the thawânt, the immaterial intellectual beings whose subsistence depends on the First Principle. This is confirmed by two points. First, by the hierarchy he establishes between the intellects, which defines some as being metaphysically and causally prior or “close” to the First and others as being posterior or “remote” from It. This hierarchy also helps to explain the order of the various levels of the visible heavens in the other metaphysical treatises, each level being caused by an intel- lect.[706] Second, the terminology, which relies chiefly on the terms laz- ima ‘an and hasala ‘an, is distinctive and is the same that appears in Ára and Siyasah. What is more, al-Fârâbï defines the First Principle as a “cause of existence” (sabab wujüdiha) for these separate entities, and not merely as a final cause of motion for the universe, and he also refers to the other intellects themselves as causes (asbab) and as “the divine principles” (al-mabadt l-ilahiyyah).[707] In spite of its brevity, then, this passage shows that al-Fârâbï’s theory of the thawant and most likely his corollary theory of eternal efficient and final causation were already formulated when he composed this treatise, which should be con­nected with his late works, Ára and Siyasah.

A very similar picture can be found in Ft l-‘aql.[708] There the separate intellects are defined not only as final causes of motion for the orbs, that is, as movers (sing. muharrik), but also as causes of existence: each separate intellect is “the cause of [the celestial body’s] existence [fa-innahü huwa sabab ft wujüdiht]” This proves that this treatise goes beyond the Aristotelian cosmology exposed in Book Lambda in attrib­uting efficient causality to each unmoved mover. While it is not spelled out, this treatise implicitly endorses the same cosmology as the one articulated in the late metaphysical treatises: the First, which is the ulti­mate principle of existence, towers the metaphysical hierarchy; then follow the separate intellects, explicitly defined both as final and effi­cient causes; and finally the celestial bodies, which derive their exist­ence and motion from these higher principles and in turn act on sublunary nature. Both the doctrines and terminology of Fl l-‘aql are strikingly similar to those in Ára and Siyasah, and these works convey a common paradigm of efficient and final causality that hinges on the activity of the thawant. Given these facts, it is difficult to understand on what grounds some scholars have described this treatise as a faithful exposition of the Stagirite’s doctrine and as belonging to al-Fârâbï’s “Aristotelian texts.”[709] The early date of composition that has sometimes been proposed for Fl l-‘aql cannot be accepted without hesitation, and it is rather tempting in the frame of the developmentalist hypothesis to connect it with a later period in al-Fârâbï’s life.

It is, however, in al-Fârâbï’s two latest works, Ára and Siyasah, that one gets the deepest insight into his eternalist causative model. In order to better grasp the doctrinal subtleties developed in these treatises, it is necessary to take a closer look at al-Fârâbï’s terminology of causation and at the role that the First and the secondary intellects play in this causal scheme. Emphasis will be placed on the connection between intellection and causation and on how the corporeal beings are said to emerge from these principles.

To begin with, let us examine the causative activity of the First. Al-Fârâbï uses several Arabic terms to describe the way in which other beings are caused to exist by the First’s intellectual activity. An investi­gation of his metaphysical treatises reveals that these terms consist mostly of the roots f-y-d, l-z-m, h-s-l, and w-j-d. In Ára for instance, one reads that “the First is that from which existence is brought about [‘anhu wujida]” that “the substance of the First is a substance from which every existent emanates [tafldu ‘anhu]” and that “the substance of the First is also such that when the existents are derived [idha hasalat [‘anhu] l-mawjüdât], they are necessarily united and connected with one another.”[710]

Two points are worth noting from the outset. The first is the com­plete absence of the roots b-d-‘ and kh-l-q to describe the First Cause in al-Farabi’s works. Since these roots were used frequently by al-Kindi and the early Muslim theologians, this omission should certainly not be seen as coincidental, but rather as a deliberate choice on al-Farabi’s part to avoid any association with these previous and/or contemporary doctrines. It is notable that, on this point, al-Farabi also departs from Ibn Sina, who occasionally uses the terms ibda and khalq to define God’s creation.[711] Second, in spite of repeated attempts by scholars to emphasize or particularize the concept of ‘emanation’ or the ‘overflow­ing of being’ (expressed by terms from the rootf-y-d) in al-Farabi’s cos­mology, it is far from clear that these terms possess a special and distinctive meaning that differs from that of the other roots expressing efficient causation.[712] In fact, there does not seem to be any significant semantic differences between fada ‘an and the other verbal construc­tions used by al-Farabi, such as lazima ‘an and hasala ‘an.[713] All of them are employed in their intransitive form and aim primarily at expressing the atemporal causal connection between an effect and its cause and the dependence of the lower existents on the First. Although al-Farabi does not define these terms in his works, there are no hints suggesting that the root f-y-d is meant to evoke a different metaphysical aspect or meaning, be it even at the metaphorical level.[714]

The primary concern for al-Fàràbï in these various passages is to express the concept of efficient causality and the corollary notion of necessary entailment. These concepts are used as a means of organizing the various immaterial beings in terms of their essential priority and posteriority vis-à-vis one another and vis-à-vis the First. While these concepts have their roots in Aristotle to some extent, the Second Teacher is, in this instance, elaborating a new metaphysical hierarchy in light of Ammonian and other Neoplatonic influences, which applied efficient causality to the entities of the superlunary world and espe­cially to Aristotle’s First Unmoved Mover. Like many of these late antique thinkers, al-Fàràbï conceives of the First’s causation of the world as an atemporal act, whichever of the above-mentioned Arabic terms is employed. This means that this act or activity does not take place in time—time already being in existence—or over a period of time.[715] The causation deriving from the First rather unfolds in a time­less realm and from all eternity. It is even possible that al-Fàràbï, fol­lowing the Proclus arabus, would have envisaged the causative activity of the First as lying beyond eternity itself, since this concept is associ­ated with the eternal and constant motion (harakah sarmadiyyah or daimah) of the celestial bodies in his philosophy. Regardless of this point, it is important to stress that the First Cause induces existence as a result of Its self-intellection. Intellection or thought is the very essence of the First, and it is from this activity that the lower existents emerge.

But al-Fârâbï’s account of causation with respect to the First is under­mined by ambiguity. On the one hand, the First is described as the first and fundamental cause of all things. On the other hand, it is said to cause only one effect, the first separate intellect, with the implication that this effect in turn becomes the proximate cause of existence of what lies beneath it. We thus seem to be faced with two different and incompatible views of how the existents and the world as a whole relate to the First. This dual account represents a tension, if not a contradic­tion, in al-Fârâbï’s system, although it is also a problem that underlies much of Neoplatonic metaphysics.[716] This tension acquired a new sig­nificance in falsafah, as a result of the close interaction that developed between philosophy and theology in Islam and of the doctrinal and creedal emphasis on divine oneness and simplicity. In the case of al-Fârâbï’s metaphysics, however, it is further compounded by the way in which he describes the causative activity of the secondary causes, the thawânt. As the modern scholarship has not precisely defined the role of these causes in al-Fârâbï’s metaphysics, it is worth devoting some space to a comparative analysis between the thawânt and the First with respect to causation. The following analysis will cast in an even starker light the different facets underlying al-Fârâbï’s account of divine causality.[717]

In parallel to the exclusive status of the First as the cause of all beings, al-Fârâbï articulates another theory that endows the separate intellects or thawânt with a significant power and autonomy of their own and defines them as purveyors of existence for the lower entities. With this question, we reach one of the crucial stages in the development of al-Fârâbï’s cosmology. For although the Second Teacher’s cosmological model is in many ways indebted to Aristotle’s Book Lambda and its late antique commentaries, there was no precedent in the Aristotelian tra­dition for transforming each separate unmoved mover into a cause responsible for the existence of other intellects as well as each heavenly orb. One may legitimately hypothesize, as I did in a recent article, and as was also intimated in chapter 2, that al-Fârâbï was the author of this innovation and that he developed this cosmological proposition by applying Neoplatonic, and more specifically Proclean, theories of causation and demiurgy to the Aristotelian doctrine of the unmoved movers.[718] This hypothesis, which is supported by the wide circulation of Arabic versions of Proclus’ Elements in tenth-century Baghdad and by the many terminological and doctrinal parallels between it and al-Fârâbï’s works, will be further explored in the following paragraphs.

2.6.1. The Causative Powers of the Separate Intellects

In al-Fârâbï’s cosmological system, the various levels of the heavens are caused to exist by the separate intellects and not by the First directly. By reflecting on the First or God, Who is the ultimate principle of their existence, each intellect produces a lower separate intellect, and by thinking its own essence, it produces a celestial orb and its soul. Yet a frequent assumption made by scholars is that al-Fârâbï followed the Neoplatonica arabica in regarding the separate intellects merely as intermediaries between God and the lower existents. On this view, these intellects would be responsible for transmitting the divine crea­tive power to the principle of soul and the corporeal beings. But is this really an accurate description of al-Fârâbï’s metaphysics?

Understanding how al-Fârâbï relates to the Greek and Arabic Proclus with regard to this particular issue of mediation (tawassut) and the role of the separate intellects is crucial in order to fully grasp the scope of his originality. Let us begin by examining al-Fârâbï’s vocabulary of cau­sation. The most common term found in al-Fârâbï’s treatises to express the relation between the separate intellects and their effects is lazima ’an, “to follow necessarily from.” In Ára, for instance, it is said that “as a result of its [the first separate intellect after God] thinking of the First [God], a third existent follows necessarily from [lazima ‘an] it.”[719] This verbal construction stresses the dependence of the intellects and heav­enly bodies qua effects on the higher intellectual principles that pre­cede them essentially. In this context, the terms lazima ’an first and foremost express necessary connection or logical entailment, together with the notion of concomitance, since this connection exists in a realm that transcends time. Indeed, in al-Fârâbï’s metaphysics, lazima ’an and the derived term luzüm denote both necessary consequence and onto­logical concomitance due to the atemporal character of the relation between these metaphysical entities.[720]

But this verb may also express causation in a more straightforward way. Al-Fârâbï explicitly describes the separate intellects as “causes” (asbab) in Siyasah,[721] and by this term there can be no doubt that he means causes of existence, that is, efficient causes responsible for bring­ing about the existence of lower celestial entities. This appears clearly when he writes that “the secondary causes are the causes of the exist­ence of the celestial bodies [al-thawani hiya asbab wujüd al-ajsam al-samawiyyah]” and that “the existence [wujüd] of each one of the celestial bodies is a necessary consequence [yalzamu ‘anhu] of them [the separate intellects] .”[722] Finally, al-Fârâbï states in Siyasah that “the existence [wujüd] of each heaven emanates from [yafidu min] the exist­ence of each [separate intellect].”[723]

Several points are worth stressing here. First, and as stated above, al-Fârâbï explicitly describes the separate intellects as proximate causes of existence and efficient causes for the beings below them. On this point he departs markedly from the Proclus arabus, where intellect is merely a purveyor of form for the soul and an intermediary between the First and the lower beings. This appears clearly in Proposition 3 of Mahd al-khayr, which states that the First Cause “created [abdaat] the being of the soul through the mediation of the intellect [bi-tawassut al-‘aql]” and in Proposition 17, where it is stated that “the intellect gives knowledge and the other things to what is below it in the manner of form, not in the manner of origination [bi-naw‘ süratin la bi-naw’ ibdain], because the manner of origination belongs to the First Cause alone.”[724]

Second, these passages show that al-Fârâbï uses the exact same ter­minology to express the causative power of the First and the thawant. In other words, the first separate intellect “emanates from” and is “nec­essarily caused” by God, but in the same way the celestial souls and orbs are also said to “emanate from” and to be “necessarily caused” by the separate intellects. Hence, the verbs lazima ’an and fada ’an are applied with a similar meaning and aim to the First and the separate intellects. Al-Fârâbï makes no distinction between these entities’ mode of causation at the terminological and conceptual levels. This in turn further invalidates the idea put forth by some scholars that al-Fârâbï applied a special language of emanation to the First to distinguish and particularize Its creative activity. On the contrary, we see that al-Fârâbï uses the various terms expressing causation synonymously and that he applies them to all the intellectual beings of this metaphysics, the thawant as well as the First.[725] It is significant that al-Fârâbï departs markedly on this last point from the Neoplatonica arabica, which reserve a specific terminology derived from the roots b-d-' and kh-l-q for God in order to distinguish His authentic creative act from the mere mediatory role of intellect and its ‘information’ of the soul.[726] In contrast, al-Fârâbï made a conscious effort to shun the roots b-d- and kh-l-q in his works. This shows that he envisaged his terminology of causation as being fundamentally different from the language used not only by the mutakallimün, but also in the Arabic Neoplatonic works.[727]

Furthermore, there is a passage in Siyasah that deserves close atten­tion. At one point, al-Fârâbï writes that “on its own it [i.e., each separate intellect] is capable of bringing something else into being [iyjad ghayriht] without seeking the help of any instrument or circumstance beyond its own substance”[728] This striking statement is a crucial piece of evidence for my overarching argument. The formula iyjad ghayriht (“bringing something else into being”) used in this sentence implies much more than logical derivation or causative intermediacy. It rather posits an autonomous and self-contained power in the separate intel­lects that can give being to other entities. This statement explicitly stresses the active, demiurgic role of the intellects in the production of the lower celestial existents in al-Fârâbï’s ontological hierarchy.[729] Moreover, it is clear from this passage that the intellects themselves do not need an instrument or an intermediary to assist them in the pro­duction of the lower entities. According to al-Fârâbï, the intellects can, like the First, produce other existents directly without relying on any­thing else but their own substance.

In conclusion, not only are al-Fârâbï’s separate intellects not inter­mediaries in God’s creation in the way portrayed in the Neoplatonica arabica, but in addition they themselves do not need any intermediar­ies to produce other beings and therefore possess unmediated demiur­gic powers. In this respect, they are the direct and absolute causes of existence of the celestial souls and bodies. This is again contrary to the Arabic Neoplatonic texts, which describe soul as the intermediary between intellect and nature or corporeality.[730]

For all of these reasons, it appears that al-Fârâbï’s metaphysics in many ways endows the intellects with a high degree of autonomy and a demiurgic power of their own, which is not directly derived from that of the First. The intellects do not passively communicate the First’s causative power. On the contrary, through their own power and intel­lectual activity, they participate in the production and multiplication of existence (wujüd). The causative activity of the First and the separate intellects occurs as a result of their contemplation. In the case of the First, this intellection is purely self-reflexive, whereas in the case of the thawânt, it is both self-reflexive and oriented at another higher intelli­gible, namely the First. Each intellect is therefore characterized by a unique intellection that produces unique effects, which are suited to its own nature and being. In this regard, al-Fârâbï is quite close to the Greek Proclus, who posits a multiplicity of immaterial beings that pro­duce other entities through their (self-reflexive) intellection.[731]

2.6.2.    Syrianus, Proclus, and al-Farabi on Causation and Intellection

This last point on the connection between intellection and causation will be explored in more depth. It should be noted that since intellec­tion is the only activity that characterizes the immaterial beings, it is necessarily as a result of their contemplation that they are able to pro­duce the lower effects. In other words, intellection and causation appear to be essentially linked in al-Fârâbï’s account, to the point that the prin­ciple of intellection possesses an inherent demiurgic power.[732]

Now, according to Proposition 193 of Elements, each soul has its ori­gin in an intellect and proceeds from an intellect. The link between the souls and intellects is also discussed in Propositions 166 and 182. And again in Proposition 160, Proclus writes that the “divine intelligence ... produces the others from its own being.” Intellect is therefore a demi­urgic principle in Proclus’ metaphysics, and one responsible among other things for the existence of soul. Furthermore, Proclus explains that creation occurs through intellection. For each intellect, he says, “its creative activity is in thinking, and its thought is in creating -,.1«9.34

I'q noinoiç ev to voeiv k«i n vonoiç ev to noieivj.[733]

Proclus provides further information on the various intellects considered as minor demiurges in his commentary on Timaeus, a subject covered in detail by J. Opsomer and J. Dillon.[734] What is important for our purposes is that Proclus recognizes a whole series of secondary demiurges below the main Demiurge mentioned in Timaeus. These demiurges are also intellectual beings that are responsible for the creation of the lower entities such as the souls. In Proclus’ cosmol­ogy, then, there is a variety of minor creator-gods who create through intellection, and who are not presented merely as intermediaries, but as genuine demiurges of the cosmic beings. These passages show that al-Fârâbï followed his Greek predecessor on three crucial counts: in deriving the cosmological principle of soul from the principle of intel­lect, in defining causation as an inherently intellectual act or activity, and, finally, in positing a multiplicity of intellectual entities endowed with demiurgic powers.

It is nevertheless interesting to note that this aspect of Proclus’ phi­losophy was considerably watered-down by the Muslim and Christian adaptors who received and studied the Greek Neoplatonic works. Their objective as monotheists was to preserve or re-establish the divine omnipotence and the absolute priority of God in matters of creation. They accomplished this in two ways. First and as previously mentioned, they used the root b-d-’ to express God’s absolute creation of intellect or of the world as a whole.[735] Second, the principle of intellect itself is stripped of any real demiurgic ability and is described as an intermedi­ary through which God’s creation or emanation filters. In one passage of Mahd al-khayr, for instance, God is said to create the “being of soul,” while intellect is merely responsible for endowing it with intellective powers.[736] Liber II, the other known recension of Mahd al-khayr, states that the First Cause “created the intellect without any intermediary and created soul and nature through the intermediary of intellect.”[737] Theology of Aristotle and Sayings of the Greek Sage uphold a similar view.[738] Hence, Proclus arabus does not connect intellect and causation in the way that both the Greek Proclus and al-Fârâbï do. When com­pared to the Neoplatonica arabica, al-Fârâbï’s theory of the thawdnt is in many ways closer to Proclus’ doctrine of the minor demiurges as articulated in his Greek works than to the Arabic adaptations of these works.[739]

There is another Neoplatonic source that was translated into Arabic and that may have contributed to shaping al-Fârâbï’s theory of the separate intellects, namely, Syrianus’ commentary on Metaphysics. Syrianus (d. ca. 437 CE) succeeded Plutarch as head of the Neoplatonic school of Athens and was also the master of Proclus. Hence, it is hardly surprising to find a continuous line of thought on this subject run­ning from him and his disciple Proclus, through the Arabic transla­tors and adaptors, to al-Fârâbï himself. While Syrianus’ commentary on Metaphysics has survived only incompletely, there is sufficient evidence in its remaining parts to conclude that he posited various separate, intellectual principles, and that he made these principles responsible for the creation of the heavens. According to Syrianus, there are “divine and unmoved separable causal principles of the whole cosmos.”[740] These principles, it should be noted, are explicitly defined as efficient causes: they have “creative causality” and are “causes of existence.”[741] Interestingly, Syrianus further distinguishes between gen­eral and specific or particular causes, the latter being responsible for the causation of the various heavenly orbs. He writes:

One must postulate that within Intellect there are more general causal principles and others that are more particular, seeing as Aristotle himself, in admitting that there is the same order pervading the visible celestial spheres in the aether as is possessed by the intellectual causes of the uni­verse, is plainly agreeing that some of them are more comprehensive and others are particular.[742]

As in al-Fârâbï’s cosmology, then, specific intellectual causes are respon­sible for the causation of the various heavenly orbs, even though all of them share a common immaterial nature. The fact that Syrianus’ state­ment appears in a commentary on Metaphysics indicates that he regarded this interpretation essentially as an elaboration on Aristotle’s theory of the unmoved movers, but one which was nevertheless fully compatible with Aristotelian metaphysics. Although this aspect is not emphasized in the surviving parts of his commentary, it is clear that these causes operate as a result of their intellection. The idea that immaterial causes are responsible for the creation of the world through their intellectual or contemplative activity was standard in Greek Neoplatonism and was elaborated in depth by some thinkers such as Proclus. It appears clearly when Syrianus writes that the forms are always “within” intellect and “create inasmuch as they are Intellect.”[743]

The above clearly shows that Syrianus—in a way even more appar­ent than Proclus due to the nature of this work, i.e., a commentary on Aristotle’s Metaphysics—anticipated al-Fârâbï in construing the Aristotelian unmoved movers as separate efficient causes responsible for the existence of the visible heavens. His commentary also contains the crucial idea that these causes are intellectual beings that possess demiurgic powers by virtue of their intellection. On these grounds, one cannot exclude the possibility that al-Fârâbï may also have been famil­iar with Arabic excerpts of Syrianus’ Metaphysics commentary.

2.6.3.    Conclusion

The previous analysis offered a re-interpretation of the nature and role of the separate intellects and stressed the close interplay between the concepts of intellection and causation in al-Fârâbï’s metaphysics. It showed beyond doubt that al-Fârâbï’s cosmology and metaphysics are to a certain extent genuinely Neoplatonic. More specifically, they are indebted to Proclus and possibly his master Syrianus, some of whose writings were translated in Arabic. It is not so much the concept of emanation that indicates al-Fârâbï’s allegiance to some fundamental aspects of late antique Neoplatonic metaphysics, since this concept has been vaguely described in the secondary literature with respect to al-Fârâbï’s works and does not possess a meaning distinct and different from his general theory of causality. Rather, it is the other points dis­cussed above with regard to causation and intellection—especially the interrelatedness of these two concepts in his metaphysics—which point to this conclusion. Although it has been suggested that al-Fârâbï and Ibn Sïnâ were not cognizant of or did not use Mahd al-khayr, the fore­going analysis strengthens Maróth’s hypothesis as well as more recent claims that this work represents a key element in the elaboration of al-Fârâbï’s metaphysics and celestial noetics, and, through al-Fârâbï’s works, of Ibn Sïnâ’s as well.[744]

The foregoing allows us to re-assess al-Fârâbï’s relation to late antique philosophy and to the contemporary Islamic Weltanschauung in which he lived. In contrast to M. Mahdi, F. Zimmermann, and others, who believe that it was al-Fârâbï’s aim to establish an ‘Islamic philosophy,’ I argued that al-Fârâbï’s cosmology and metaphysics as articulated in his late works are in many ways closer to late antique Neoplatonic philosophy—both to the Ammonian tradition of Alexandrian Neoplatonism and to the Athenian School of Proclus and Syrianus— than to the prevalent ‘Islamic’ cosmological models of his time.[745] Indeed, al-Fârâbï shows little if no concern in his mature works to defend the orthodox religious position on divine creation, construed in the sense of there being a single Demiurge or Creator-God responsible for the origination of the world. This view was not only the norm in most Christian and Muslim theological circles; it was also the position defended by earlier thinkers such as al-Kindi, Saadia Gaon, and al-Farabi himself in his ‘early Baghdad phase.’

But al-Farabi goes even further: he denies any specificity to the way in which God creates the world and adopts instead a model of eternal causation that is articulated on various different levels and that endows the separate intellects with a complete demiurgic autonomy compara­ble to that of the First. These separate intellects are not mere interme­diaries, but efficient causes of existence in no lesser sense than the First, even though the existence of each one of them is dependent on a higher cause. The special status of the thawânt is fully expressed when al-Farabi describes them as the “divine principles” (al-mabddt l-ilahiyyah) in Tahstl, a formula which evokes the pagan polytheistic system of the Greek Neoplatonists.[746] And indeed, since the thawant are both intelli­gibles and intellective causes, it is tempting to regard them as a synthe­sis of the intelligible-intellective beings and the lower demiurges of Syrianus’ and Proclus’ metaphysics. In upholding these views, al-Farabi may be seen as an heir to some of these thinkers’ doctrines, although he creatively adapted and transformed them to elaborate his own meta­physical model. The result is distinct not only from the Arabic Neoplatonic adaptations and the Greek prototypes on which they are based, but also from the kind of metaphysical speculation that had developed in Islam prior to al-Farabi’s life.

Finally, the analysis showed that in most cases it is idle to divide the Farabian corpus in ‘Aristotelian’ and ‘Neoplatonic’ works. Many texts believed to be ‘Aristotelian’ develop theories that consist of a subtle combination of Aristotelian and Neoplatonic doctrines, or put differ­ently, they interpret Aristotelian tenets in light of the late antique com- mentatorial tradition. Accordingly, al-Farabi’s theory of the separate intellects and his corollary theory of final and efficient causality can be identified in varying degrees in works as diverse as Falsafat Aristütülts, Ft l-‘aql, and Tahstl, not to mention the emanationist treatises, and they therefore overlap the Aristotelian-Neoplatonic dichotomy main­tained by Mahdi, Galston, and Druart. Even Ihsa and probably Aghrad, which more likely belong to al-Farabi’s creationist phase, betray the infiltration of Neoplatonic elements. Hence, these works cannot be considered faithful expositions of the Stagirite’s doctrine, and they should instead be contextualized in terms of the late antique philo­sophical tradition that al-Fârâbï is drawing on and perpetuating not only in regard to his general approach to philosophy, but to Aristotelian metaphysics specifically. In contrast, one may propose a new division of the Fârâbïan corpus between works that convey a theory of eternal final and efficient causation (the synonymous concept of emanation- ism is subsumed under this category) and works that defend instead the view of the creation and temporal finitude of the world, emphasize the omnipotence of God qua Creator, and do not posit this intermedi­ate level of intellective causal beings between the Godhead and the cor­poreal world.

2.7. Causation, Compositeness, and the Celestial Substrate

Having discussed in detail al-Fârâbï’s concept of celestial substance and his views on causality in previous parts of this book, I will provide additional insight into how both concepts are linked in his cosmology. What metaphysical role does substrate fulfill in this new causal model? The paragraphs below address this question, aiming to further strengthen the idea that al-Fârâbï’s adoption of substrate was not ran­dom or accidental, but rather a conscious departure from the theories he previously held.

One particularity of the eternalist causative model described in the previous sections is that it leads to a different account of how matter comes into existence. Whereas in Jam’ and Jawâbât matter is created ex nihilo and absolutely by a Creator God, al-Fârâbï’s later metaphysical treatises depart from this picture on two crucial points. First, matter per se or prime matter is relegated to the very bottom of al-Fârâbï’s ontological hierarchy and thus beyond the direct causative reach of the First. It is described as the “basest of existents,” and its main function is to serve as a substrate for all processes of change, such as generation and corruption. On the other hand, al-Fârâbï explicitly connects the existence of prime matter with the causation of the celestial beings. As he writes in Siyasah, “a necessary result of the power common to the whole celestial body is the existence of the prime matter common to everything below the heaven.”[747] Since the activity of the celestial bodies and Agent Intellect is eternal and continuous, this means by implication that the existence and receptivity of prime matter is also continuous and eternal, and thus that the processes of generation and corruption are endless. Hence, not only is matter completely detached from the direct power of the First, but it stands as one of the fundamen­tal principles (mabâdï) of al-Fârâbï’s new cosmological model.

The second striking feature is the dissociation of the heavenly sub­stance and the principle of matter. In Jam’ and Jawabat, there is no distinction between celestial and sublunary matter, since matter itself is a product of God’s absolute creation. Although it is not explicitly artic­ulated, the view upheld in these treatises is that God created the matter of the heavens and of the sublunary world together and ‘all at once,’ no distinction being made between the two. But in al-Fârâbï’s late meta­physical treatises, matter is a principle that is restricted to the sublu­nary world and defined as a direct effect of the heavenly beings, while the heavens themselves are strictly speaking devoid of a material cause. As a result, the heavenly substance is not hylomorphic—or only called so analogically—for al-Fârâbï replaces matter with the concept of celes­tial substrate (mawdu). In that sense, it is striking that al-Fârâbï’s account of the causation of the orbs does not include a material cause that can be distinguished from the cause of their soul. Rather, these two effects (body and soul) are due to the same cause, i.e., a separate intel­lect. By thinking the First, each separate intellect causes another intel­lect to exist; by thinking its own essence, it causes the existence of an orb and its soul. In contrast, Ibn Sïnâ mentions three causes: one for the intellect, one for the celestial soul, and a third cause that is responsible for producing the matter (maddah) and corporeality of the celestial bodies.[748] The omission of this third material cause is yet another indication that the principle of matter is minimized in al-Fârâbï’s cosmology.

In spite of this, the heavenly bodies are caused and are therefore not simple substances. The first function of substrate appears clearly in this regard and can be highlighted through a comparison of Alexander’s and al-Fârâbï’s cosmologies. Although Alexander defines the celestial body as a soul inhering in a substrate, and although there is some ambi­guity as to whether this substrate is to be understood as being com­pletely immaterial or as a second type of matter,[749] he is consistent in claiming the absolute simplicity of the heavenly beings. For example, in Mabadi one reads: “As for the divine body, since it is simple [bastía n] — because it could not be eternal if it were composite—and its motion is also one and simple, it does not have any nature at all other than the soul.”[750] [751] Alexander establishes a direct equation between simplicity of substance and soul: because the celestial bodies are essentially a soul, they are devoid of multiplicity.

Al-Fârâbï, in contrast, has a very different view on this issue. According to him, the fact that the heavenly bodies consist of substrate and soul is used to argue against their simplicity. Unlike Alexander, al-Fârâbï emphasizes the duality of soul and substrate and presents them as the two components of the orbs’ substance. He writes: “The substance [jawhar] of each one of the heavens [samawat, i.e., main orbs] is composed [murakkab] of two things: a substrate [mawdu] and a soul [nafs] ”252 Furthermore, in Ára, al-Fârâbï specifies that the celes­tial body “thinks with an intellect that is not identical with its entire substance.” And he adds that “because it [the celestial body] also thinks its substrate which is not intellect, that part of its essence which it thinks is not entirely intellect.”[752] This passage shows that the concept of substance is broader than that of intellect. The celestial bodies are primarily defined in terms of their intellects, but they also possess substrates, which are responsible for making the heavenly sub­stance composite. This explains why al-Fârâbï mentions the “things” (ashya) and “parts” (ajza) that constitute the heavenly substance.[753]

Hence, al-Fârâbï never describes the heavenly bodies as beings that are simple in substance, in the manner that Alexander does in Mabâdi’. While for Alexander the substrate does not prevent the orbs from being simple bodies, for al-Fârâbï it is the main reason why they are composed.

This point could remain a minor interpretive divergence in these thinkers’ concept of substrate, but when related to broader issues, such as the question of the eternity and causation of the world, it acquires a new significance. Alexander’s cosmology is in many ways like Aristotle’s: it describes the heavens as eternal and divine, and although Simplicius ascribes to him the view that the First Unmoved Mover is an efficient cause of the world’s existence, no clear articulation of this idea can be found in his extant works.[754] In this respect, Alexander’s intention in stressing the simplicity of the celestial bodies probably had little to do with causation or creation as such, but rather aimed to remove these beings as far as possible from the sublunary world and accentuate their divine nature.

Al-Fârâbï has an altogether different aim in mind when stressing the composite nature of the orbs. Since each entity of his cosmology is dependent on a higher cause for its existence, all of these existents must somehow be integrated in the causal chain that begins with the First and then continues with the thawânt, the celestial bodies, and ends with the sublunary elements and prime matter. According to al-Fârâbï, one of the direct consequences of a thing being caused is that it is com­posite. Either it is itself made of a plurality of things that are united through its cause, as is the case with corporeal existents, or it possesses a degree of complexity in its essence, without however being compos­ite, as is the case of the separate intellects. This compositeness and/or complexity is in turn responsible for the deficiency of these existents. As al-Fârâbï writes in Fusü l,

anything whose existence comes about by means of combination and composition ... is defective in existence [naqis al-wujüd] because of its constitution’s needing the things of which it is combined—whether that is a combination of quantity, a combination of matter and form, or any other of the sorts of combinations.[755]

The triangular relation between causality, complexity or composite­ness, and deficiency described by al-Fârâbï in this passage explains why he has no problem accepting the proposition of the compositeness of the heavenly bodies, and thus why he goes against a well-established Peripatetic tradition that regarded the heavenly bodies as simple enti­ties and aether as a homogeneous substance.[756] Since the celestial bod­ies are part of the cosmic scheme and are caused by higher beings, they must by the same token be composite (murakkab) and therefore defi­cient. But as we saw previously, al-Fârâbï is reluctant to attribute a hylo- morphic constitution to the heavens, and hence he must seek the source of their compositeness elsewhere. He defines them instead in terms of the duality of substrate and soul. These two principles fulfill the same function as form and matter, namely, they make the celestial substance composite, although they possess none of the negative attributes of matter, such as potentiality and passivity.

Al-Fârâbï’s theory of substrate clearly emphasizes the noetic nature of the celestial bodies in a manner reminiscent of the Neoplatonists. Because substrate does not represent a material principle opposed to the psychological nature of the orbs, the celestial bodies acquire an existence that is almost completely intellectual. This particular under­standing of celestial substance belongs to al-Fârâbï’s general strategy of making intellect and soul the main principles of his cosmology, and in this sense it can help us to understand how the celestial beings can coherently be said to be caused by immaterial beings.

The absence of matter (the standard Aristotelian principle of indi­viduation) means that the differentiation of the celestial bodies occurs purely as a result of their intellection and the hierarchy of their objects of thought, not of a decreasing nobleness of their matter. Each orb aspires to imitate its corresponding separate intellect, and it is the hierarchy of the separate intellects that dictates the hierarchy of the celestial bodies. For example, the outermost orb is nobler than the orb of the sun, because it contemplates the first separate intellect, which is closer to the One than the separate intellect corresponding to the orb of the sun.[757] Finally, the substitution of immaterial substrate for matter in the heavenly substance helps to explain why al-Fârâbï describes the celestial souls as intellects, and not, as Ibn Sïnâ, as “corporeal souls.”[758] The main reason for this difference lies in the divergent explanation that both thinkers give concerning the substance of the celestial body, which is truly material for Ibn Sïnâ, and merely a composite of non­material substrate and intellect for al-Fârâbï.

The concept of substrate also serves to establish a bridge between heavenly and human intellection in the emanationist treatises and Fl l-aql. It figures prominently in al-Fârâbï’s noetics, a subject to which the Second Teacher is known to have dedicated several treatises.[759] In Fl l-aql, which provides a detailed examination of the various meanings of the term ‘intellect’ and the stages of human intellection, al-Fârâbï explains that the potential intellect, which is “a certain soul, or a part of a soul, or one of the faculties of the soul,” enables human beings to abstract the forms from the material objects they apprehend.[760] This potential intellect is succeeded by the active and acquired intellects, and finally by the separate Agent Intellect, which is also the tenth cos­mic intellect that governs the sublunary world and ends the cycle of superlunary causation. What is of particular concern here is the fact that the material intellect is described as being “like a kind of matter” (shablhah bi-maddah) and as being “itself that which is like matter and substrate” (al-dhat allatl tushbihu maddatan wa-mawdu an)[761] for the forms it receives and for the intellects above it, especially the actual intellect, which acts like a form on the potential intellect.[762] [763]

In another passage of Fl l-aql, a-Fârâbï goes even further and explains that each intellect is like a substrate for the intellect above it and a form for the intellect below it. Even the acquired intellect ( aql mustafad), the highest intellectual faculty in humans, is like a substrate for the forms it receives (wa-l-aql al-mustafad shablh bi-mawdu).26i A similar description of the human intellect occurs in Âra, where al-Fârâbï calls each faculty of the soul “matter” for the faculty above it and form for the faculty below it.[764] These passages are all characterized by the use of analogical language, which compares the faculties of the human soul to a substrate or matter for higher faculties.[765] That any part of the human soul may represent a substrate in which higher principles can act recalls the heavenly substrate, which is also acted upon by the higher faculty of the celestial soul, i.e., its purely intellectual part. Substrate is not material strictly speaking, but possesses some of the characteristics of matter, such as receptivity. Both the heavenly bodies and the various intellectual faculties in humans are substrates in their capacity to receive form from a higher agent, and yet they are strictly speaking immaterial.

This parallel in the cosmology and noetics of al-Fârâbï is strength­ened by the fact that the heavenly bodies possess a rational soul, which, like the human rational soul, is primarily defined by its intellection and its being a source of perfection. This intellectual kinship is emphasized in Siyasah when al-Fârâbï writes that “the celestial souls ... have only the soul that intellects, which in some sense is congeneric with the rational soul [in humans].”[766] Hence, although human and heavenly souls and intellects are not identical, they share a number of similari­ties and are defined through a common terminology. Substrate plays an important role in the ontological structure of soul in al-Fârâbï’s philosophy.

The common terminology, conceptual framework, and analogical approach employed by the Second Teacher in his discussions of human and celestial intellection indicate an overlap between the cosmologi­cal and psychological disciplines in al-Fârâbï’s philosophy.[767] For this reason, it may be surmised that he derived the concept of substrate from the field of human psychology and subsequently applied it to his cosmology and metaphysics. This concept, which is usually associated with the human intellect, is transferred to the level of the celestial souls, where it fulfills new noetic functions. Al-Fârâbï’s cosmology thus seems to exploit ideas from human psychology.[768]

3. Strengthening the Developmentalist Hypothesis

The previous sections dealing with the nature and origin of celestial matter have brought to the fore some major tensions and discrepancies in al-Fârâbï’s various works, which were interpreted by means of a developmentalist hypothesis. Naturally, as M. Rashed aptly reminds us, these various doctrinal contradictions should not be construed in themselves as proofs for an evolution in al-Fârâbï’s thought.[769] They may instead be due to various authorships or to a corrupt manuscript trans­mission, which resulted in the attribution of several spurious treatises to al-Fârâbï. However, it was argued before that this approach does not take into account the considerable positive evidence pointing to al-Fârâbï’s authorship of Jam’ and Jawâbât. Moreover, it should be said that if the presence of doctrinal contradictions do not stand as proof of an author’s intellectual evolution, they by no means infirm such a hypothesis, especially when it is supported by a host of independent hints and indicators. In what follows, I explore these hints and try to weave them into the developmentalist hypothesis, in order to mount a comprehensive case for it. But before I do so, it would seem appropriate to briefly summarize the main alternative interpretations that have been adopted in the last decades in Fârâbïan studies, both in order to show where their shortcomings lie and why the developmentalist hypothesis carries the most weight.

Mahdi’s thesis was already addressed briefly in chapter 1 with regard to his views on the place and meaning of cosmology in al-Fârâbï’s ema- nationist works. Here I will say merely a few words concerning his broader interpretation of al-Fârâbï’s thought, especially given that some of its fundamental premises have already been criticized by D. Gutas and P Vallat.[770] According to Mahdi, the Fârâbïan corpus can be divided into the “popular works” and the “serious” or “Aristotelian works.” In the former, chiefly represented by Ára and Siyâsah, al-Fârâbï would be exposing a popular, exoteric doctrine to assuage the religious fervor of his contemporaries. He would be relying on Neoplatonica arabica expressly for this purpose, that is, by defining God as a cause responsi­ble for the world’s existence. Aware of the non-Aristotelian provenance of this Arabic Neoplatonic corpus, al-Fârâbï nonetheless drew from it on particular occasions in order to make his philosophical system more acceptable to the orthodox camp. In contrast, in his “serious works” al-Fârâbï would be commenting and elaborating on Aristotle’s genuine doctrines in a manner free of any Neoplatonic infiltration. Intertwined with this argument is the idea that al-Fârâbï owed little to the history of late antique Neoplatonism and was chiefly influenced by Middle Platonism, as his political theories are supposed to make clear.[771]

In spite of the valuable insight provided by Mahdi’s and Druart’s interpretations, it is clear today that they are undermined by several shortcomings. First, in attributing to al-Fârâbï the conception of a ‘pure’ or ‘authentic’ Aristotelianism, and in defining some of his works as an objective account of the Stagirite’s doctrine, which would be very much akin to the one endorsed by modern scholarship, these interpre­tations rely on an ahistorical approach. They do not sufficiently take into account the import of the late antique tradition of philosophical exegesis and the sustained process of adaptation that Aristotle’s doc­trines experienced in the Eastern Mediterranean cultural sphere dur­ing this period. Consequently, some of the key assumptions underlying Mahdi’s interpretive paradigm are not tenable. To give but one reveal­ing example, the notion that al-Fârâbï adhered in some of his works to Aristotle’s tenet of an eternal world whose existence is uncaused, and thus that he conceived of the Aristotelian God solely in terms of final causality is clearly anachronistic, since the late antique interpreta­tions of Aristotle’s cosmology bequeathed to al-Fârâbï had added to this picture the key theory of efficient causation and the view that God is responsible for the world’s continuing existence. This approach neglects the secular tradition of commentaries on Aristotle that flour­ished in late antiquity and that thoroughly transformed Aristotelian cosmology. As the previous analysis has shown, al-Fârâbï articulates a clear account either of creation or efficient causation in all of his works. This and other similar Neoplatonic elaborations shaped al-Fârâbï’s reading of the Stagirite to such an extent that it becomes difficult to speak of al-Fârâbï’s ‘Aristotelianism’ without these impor­tant qualifications.

As a corollary, the classification of al-Fârâbï’s works proposed by these scholars, and especially the dichotomy between ‘Aristotelian’ and ‘Neoplatonic’ texts, cannot be accepted in its main lines and without drastic readjustments. Together with recent studies on the subject, the previous analysis articulated in this book has shown that al-Fârâbï relied substantially on a cluster of commentaries by Alexander, Themistius, perhaps Simplicius and Syrianus, as well as independent treatises by Proclus, to interpret Aristotle during the various stages of his intellectual career, even in some of his so-called “Aristotelian works,” such as Ihsa ’, Falsafat Aristü ta lis, and Ft l-‘aql.[772]

Moreover, the claim that Neoplatonic ideas, including emanation- ism, appears only in his political or emanationist works, i.e., Ára and Siyasah, seems unfounded. It was argued previously, first, that emana- tionism is not a distinct concept in al-Fârâbï’s philosophy that can be meaningfully distinguished from efficient and final causation, and sec­ond, that one finds a clear exposition of efficient causation in many of the allegedly ‘Aristotelian’ works. In this light, the classification pro­posed by Mahdi appears arbitrary, and it is also on these grounds that one should regard Druart’s otherwise compelling interpretation of al-Fârâbï’s metaphysics with some skepticism.[773]

Given that these interpretive attempts appear ultimately unsatisfac­tory in light of recent studies and criticism, the developmentalist hypothesis seems a more promising line of inquiry. Besides, there are compelling positive reasons to adopt it beyond this negative fact. This positive evidence can be divided into two main categories: doctrinal and bio-bibliographic or historical. To begin with, we have seen that al-Fârâbï holds contradictory views on several fundamental philosoph­ical issues, such as the nature of celestial substance, the separability of form and its relation to intellect, and the question of the creation of the world. Some of these doctrinal contradictions can be found through­out the Fârâbïan corpus and are not by any means restricted to one or two works alone, which could be conveniently rejected on grounds of dubious authenticity. This is true especially of the question of celestial substance, for which one can muster conflicting evidence derived from the entire corpus of the Second Teacher, including works that can be securely attributed to al-Fârâbï. These contradictions are strengthened by independent reports made by later authors, such as Ibn Rushd and Maimonides. As for the tension between creationism and eternalism, it does not appear in Jam’ alone, but also in Jawâbât and Ihsa’, and perhaps also in an implicit manner in Radd. What this means is that al-Fârâbï’s authorship of all these texts, and not just of Jam, would have to be rejected in order to refute the developmentalist hypothesis. But this in turn significantly increases the implausibility of the spurious­ness of Jam, which does not appear to be an isolated case.

Additional doctrinal evidence supporting a creationist phase in al-Fârâbï’s philosophy can be gleaned from his logical treatises, which share numerous features with his early creationist works. A quick glance shows that their tenor and style differ considerably from those of the emanationist works. One of their characteristics is their frequent invocation of divine assistance and their praise of God using a specific vocabulary and honorific titles. For instance, in K. al-‘ibârah al-Fârâbï repeatedly addresses the divinity as “God Most High” (Allahu ta ala) and “God Almighty” (Allahu ‘azza wa-jalla).[774] In his introductory treatise Fl ma yanbaghl, also presumably an early work, one finds a description of God as “the Creator exalted be He” (al-khaliq ta ala).[775]

These statements, which immediately bring to mind the creationist language used in Jam, Jawabat, and Ihsa’, find no parallel in the later emanationist treatises, which speak of God exclusively in philosophical terms and refer to him consistently as “the First” or “the First Cause” (al-awwal, al-sabab al-awwal). But apart from these stylistic peculiari­ties, these logical works also contain certain doctrines that echo in an intriguing manner the views developed in the early creationist works. In K. al-‘ibarah, for instance, al-Fârâbï articulates a logical discussion that is unmistakably in support of the theses of God’s foreknowledge and of His knowledge of particulars.[776] The author’s aim in this passage is to reconcile God’s omniscience with the human freedom to act, and his argument revolves around the idea that God’s knowledge of a per­son’s acts does not entail the predetermination of these acts. This com- patibilist approach rests on the idea that God is omniscient of all the particulars that occur on earth, a view which can easily be compared to the one articulated in Jam, but which on the other hand is severely criticized in the later work Fusül.[777] The link between K. al-‘ibarah and «

Jam’ is further strengthened by an identical citation made by their author.[778] [779]

Furthermore, as M. Rashed himself noted, al-Farabi seems to implic­itly uphold a creationist position in K. al-amkinah al-mughlitah.2&0 In order to avoid the philosophical implications of this passage, which go against his interpretation, Rashed suggests an amendment of the text, which consists in ascribing the key sentence fragment to another author, most likely Ibrahim ibn ‘Adi. Apart from the contrived inter­pretation this requires, it should be noted that the example provided in K. al-amkinah al-mughlitah is not an isolated case. Al-Farabi, in fact, frequently uses creationist examples in his logical corpus to explain particular points of method. In K. al-qiyas al-saghtr, for instance, which according to J. Lameer is a summary of his larger work K. al-qiyas, and according to N. Rescher a short commentary on Prior Analytics, al-Farabi relies on creationist examples throughout the work to illus­trate his explanations.[780] For instance, he refers to the creation of the world in his discussion of naqlah, or analogical transference:

This [transference] occurs, for example, when one knows by sensation that some corporeal substances, like the animals and similar things, are created [muhdathan], and consequently the intellect transfers [yanqulu] the createdness [al-hudüth] from the animals or plants, and thus judges about the sky and stars that they are [also] created [muhdathah].[781]

Similar examples also occur in this work in order to illustrate the affirmative mode of the conjunctive conditional syllogism, as well as the use of the compound syllogism.[782] In the latter case, al-Farabi focuses on an argument based on the composition of bodies and accidents, which is designed to prove the existence of the Creator and the origination of the world.[783] It occupies the most space in this short treatise and is outlined by al-Fârâbï in detail.

At first glance, it would seem that these creationist examples are merely intended to illustrate a particular logical point and therefore cannot be used as evidence indicating al-Fârâbï’s adherence to crea­tionism.[784] But one may question this view, which seems to rest on the a priori notion that since al-Fârâbï rejected creation with time in his emanationist works, he necessarily rejected it in his logical works as well. In fact, many hints seem to point to a different conclusion. First and as mentioned above, the wealth of creationist proofs in K. al-qiyas al-saghir is noteworthy and significant, although it is not by any means a feature peculiar to this treatise alone. Al-Fârâbï employs them in this case on no fewer than four occasions. What is even more significant is that he employs them to illustrate valid logical ideas, such as condi­tional syllogisms, analogy or transfer, and compound syllogisms. Since al-Fârâbï has nothing reprehensible to say about these techniques, it would be extremely odd indeed if he were using examples whose con­clusions he did not endorse to explain these valid logical points. If this were the case, it would defeat the purpose of his logical exposition.

In this connection, al-Fârâbï explains at the beginning of the treatise that he will be using examples that are intelligible to the people of his day: “we shall use for the explanation of these canons [qawanin] only examples that are well known to the people of our time [ahl zamanina] .”[785] Since al-Fârâbï wrote his logical treatises for a philosophical reader- ship—presumably including his own Christian and Muslim disciples— these examples were meant to be intelligible and easily recognizable to this very audience, and not necessarily, as has sometimes been assumed, to an audience of theologians or jurists.[786] There is therefore no reason to suppose that the Second Teacher would have been at odds with this readership or that he did not endorse the examples used in these works. In fact, these creationist examples go hand in hand with the particular style of these logical treatises, all of which point to a creationist per­spective similar to the one adopted in Jam’ and Jawabat.

As further evidence for this hypothesis, it is noteworthy that the creationist example based on composition (taltf) that appears in K. al-qiyas is also discussed in an almost identical form at the very end of Jawabatto illustrate the use of the technique of tamthtl.28 This shows the doctrinal overlap between the creationist treatises, in this case Jawabat, and al-Fârâbï’s logical works. But even more significant is the fact that Jawabat articulates in section 9 a clear defense of the theses of the absolute creation of the world with time and of its temporal finitude and future destruction. This means that the creationist example used by al-Fârâbï in section 43 does not merely possess an illustrative pur­pose, but is rather an expression of his own cosmogonical position, which corresponds on all points with the ideas expressed in section 9. By further implication, this means that al-Fârâbï used these same crea­tionist arguments in K. al-qiyas and K. al-qiyas al-saghtr not only because they expressed a common cosmogonical view that would have been intelligible to a wide audience during his time, but also because they defended the very creationist position al-Fârâbï himself adhered to during this period of his life. In this connection, it is also revealing that al-Ash‘arï in one of his treatises ascribes this proof from com­position “to the philosophers [al-falasifah]” which suggests that al-Fârâbï was not merely reporting the views of the mutakallimün, but that he and other philosophers, such as al-Kindï and Saadia Gaon, had developed their own version of it.[787] [788] Hence, it appears that there are many valid reasons for concluding that al-Fârâbï actually endorsed the creationist proofs that he exposes in some of his logical works, includ­ing K. al-qiyas al-saghtr and K. al-amkinah al-mughlitah.[789]

To sum up, then, one finds the following features in the logical trea­tises: stylistic idiosyncrasies and laudatory formulas extolling God’s glory and even explicit descriptions of God as “the Creator,” which are not found in al-Fârâbï’s mature metaphysical works; several arguments for the creation and contingency of the world, some of which are echoed in other non-logical works by al-Fârâbï and even show a remarkable degree of overlap, as in the cases of Jawabat, K. al-qiyas, and K. al-qiyas al-saghtr; and a clear defense of God’s foreknowledge and knowledge of particulars. These points find striking parallels in Jam, Jawabat, and/or Ihsa’, but they are on the other hand absent from the emanationist treatises.

In his logical works, al-Fârâbï displays a marked concern for the relation between philosophy, logic, and religion. In general, these treatises are characterized by a sensitivity toward the religious implica­tions of philosophical arguments and by a desire to accommodate the orthodox Islamic position on key doctrinal points within a philosophi­cal framework. This general attitude is also echoed in the creationist treatises. Jam’ aims primarily to show the harmony existing between the most famous Greek philosophers, but like these logical works, it also aims to explain why philosophy—and Aristotelian thought in particular—is not contradictory with religion and can in fact benefit religious orthodoxy and practice.[790] Hence, among the commonali­ties of these logical and creationist works is a concern to elucidate Aristotelian philosophy, to expound on some of its potentially prob­lematic aspects vis-à-vis the Islamic orthodoxy (as seen in the case of God’s knowledge or the issue of eternity), and to argue for the genuine complementarity or harmony of both positions. In this connection, al-Fârâbï does not hesitate to cite Quranic verses in support of his phil­osophical explanations in these works. Finally, they display a common concern for the study of language and for the classification of Arabic terms and their philosophical use.[791]

In brief, the style, contents, and overarching aim of these works overlap significantly, and one perceives a common ideological thread that connects them. On these grounds, one may reasonably conclude that the logical treatises mentioned above were most likely written at the same time as al-Fârâbï’s creationist works and during his ‘early Baghdad period,’ when he studied under the supervision of the Christian Peripatetic thinkers or associated with their group.[792] These Christian thinkers were well-versed in the Organon and also displayed a similar concern for the relation between logic, philosophy, and reli­gion. The points enumerated above, when combined with the compar­ative analysis of the cosmologies of Matta ibn Yûnus and al-Fârâbï given in an earlier section, indicate convincingly that this Christian philosopher, and more generally the Christian philosophical milieu of Baghdad, could have played a decisive role in shaping al-Fârâbï’s approach to philosophy during this period.

In contrast to all of these putative early works, al-Fârâbï’s late treatises present very different characteristics in terms of both con­tent and philosophical outlook. By the time of their composition, al-Fârâbï had clearly moved beyond the framework and perspective he adopted in these earlier works. These treatises abandon the curricular Aristotelianism that was prevalent in Mattâ ibn Yûnus’ circle and show a higher degree of intellectual maturity and autonomy. They testify to a profound and thorough assimilation of philosophical material derived from late antique sources and particularly the Proclus arabus, which is interpreted in a new light and with the aim of elaborating a new cos­mological model. Aristotle is not mentioned as an authority in the emanationist works, and full scope is given to al-Fârâbï’s creative syn­thetic abilities. While they also display a concern for the function of religion in society, religion is effectively defined as mere imitation of philosophy and becomes secondary. It is culturally and historically relative and fulfills a purely ad hoc political role.[793]

Moreover, the style and contents of these works are remarkably free of any of the traditional laudatory formulas one encounters in al-Fârâbï’s logical works and in his creationist treatises. The highest metaphysical entity is exclusively called the First (al-awwal), the First Cause (al-sabab al-awwal), and the First Principle (al-mabda’ l-awwal), not Allâh, and It is discussed in purely philosophical terms.[794] The First is never defined as “the Creator,” and the Arabic roots expressing absolute creation (kh-l-q, h-d-th, b-d-‘), which appear regularly in the earlier works, are deliberately avoided. With regard to the issue at stake, namely, creation, these treatises articulate a complex model of eternal causation that is arranged on different cosmological levels and that endows the separate intellects with autonomous demiurgic powers comparable to those of the First. This idiosyncratic metaphysical model differs on virtually every point from the ‘standard’ creationist position of the early treatises and would clearly have been unacceptable to most of al-Fârâbï’s Muslim and Christian contemporaries.

Finally, the desire to reconcile religious tenets with philosophy, while still present, acquires a new form and becomes secondary in these works. Al-Fârâbï’s main concern is to provide a coherent, structured account of the various ontological principles that underlie the universe, of how these principles relate to one another, and of how human socie­ties and individual human beings can benefit from their study and reach happiness or eudaimonia (saadah). This synthesis of the scien­tific knowledge of his time is intended to lay the theoretical founda­tions for a new kind of philosophical curriculum and social education that can help individuals to fully actualize their substance as rational beings. Hence, these treatises differ from the creationist works even with regard to their fundamental motivation and purpose.

In addition to these doctrinal considerations, several bio­bibliographic facts lend additional weight to the developmentalist hypothesis. Indeed, the idea of al-Fârâbï’s intellectual evolution coheres quite strikingly with the little that is known about his life and career. We know with certainty from the bio-bibliographers as well as from al-Fârâbï’s own writings that he studied with Christian thinkers during his early Baghdad phase. It is with these thinkers that al-Fârâbï read the Aristotelian corpus and developed his commentatorial method. For this reason, it is legitimate to infer that most, if not all, of his commen­taries date to this early period.[795] As his understanding of Greek phi­losophy was filtered through the didactic framework established by these Christian Peripatetics, it is reasonable to surmise that they may have influenced some of al-Fârâbï’s cosmological ideas as well.[796]

In contrast, the emanationist works bear no or little connection to this Syriac philosophical milieu. Ára can be securely dated to the last decade of al-Fârâbï’s life, when he left Baghdad for Syria and Egypt in 942 CE.[797] This simple yet crucial chronological fact has been under­valued by critiques of the developmentalist hypothesis, such as T.-A. Druart and M. Rashed. Because of the doctrinal and stylistic par­allels with Ára, the works Siyasah, Fusül, and Tahstl, and possibly Fl l-‘aql, were most likely composed during this late period as well, either shortly before al-Fârâbï’s departure from Baghdad or during his stay in Egypt and Syria.[798] That some of these treatises can be dated to the very end of the Second Teacher’s output definitely supports the idea of an evolution in his thought and coheres with the special cosmological doctrines they articulate. Here at least we seem to have a clear connec­tion or overlap between the biographical and doctrinal data. Hence, what is known with some certainty about the chronology of al-Fârâbï’s works and the main events of his life seems to fully substantiate the notion of various philosophical stages in his thought.

It is, furthermore, possible that al-Fârâbï defended a creationist view in other works that have not survived. One potential hint in this regard is C. Brockelmann’s mention in his recension of al-Fârâbï’s works in GAL of a treatise entitled Risalah flhudüth al-‘alam. While one cannot infer the contents of this work from Brockelmann’s entry alone, its evocative title nevertheless raises the possibility that it defends a crea­tionist position in a manner similar to Jam’ and Jawabat. Indeed, the term hudüth, never used by al-Fârâbï in his mature metaphysical works, reminds one of a passage of Jam’ where the author uses this term to refer to the world’s contingency and creation ex nihilo.[799] This intrigu­ing hypothesis should motivate an analysis of this work in the near future.[800]

Finally, one may propose a historical argument in favour of the developmentalist interpretation. This argument hinges on the simple fact that al-Farabi is the first thinker in Arabic intellectual history to defend an eternalist model of universal efficient and final causation based on the concept of separate intellectual beings. Neither al-Kindi nor al-Razi, the two most important Arabic philosophers who flour­ished before al-Farabi, nor the Jewish thinkers Saadia Gaon and Isaac Israeli, nor as far as we know al-Farabi’s Christian teachers, Ibn H aylan and Matta ibn Yûnus, explicitly articulated this model of eternal causa­tion in their works.

The implication is that al-Farabi did not have an immediate philo­sophical antecedent or model to follow in the Arabic context and there­fore that he must have elaborated this theory over a period of time that was probably quite considerable. Put differently, al-Farabi would first have had to detach and distance himself from the existing cosmological paradigms of his day, i.e., those of al-Kindi, of Abû Bakr al-Razi, and of Matta ibn Yûnus, which he had presumably learned as a young man and to which he initially subscribed. This explains convincingly why al-Farabi articulates his causative cosmological model in detail only in his final and mature works, some of which can be securely dated to the very end of his life. If this model emerged out of al-Farabi’s protracted study and adaptation of a complex body of philosophical literature, as I am inclined to think, and if this process eventually enabled him to outgrow his formative philosophical education, then it could not have occurred over a short period of time.

4. Conclusion

This chapter endeavored to show that al-Farabi’s cosmology should not be regarded as a monolithic system, but rather as an ongoing philo­sophical effort spanning several decades and marked by different stages of development. By focusing on the concepts of matter, celestial sub­stance, and causation, it outlined a developmentalist hypothesis accord­ing to which al-Farabi’s cosmology shifted from a non-eternalist creationist paradigm which combined Philoponian, Arabic Neoplatonic, and Kindian elements to a new model of eternal causation and celestial substance in his later emanationist treatises, which emerged out of his increasing use and adaptation of Proclean metaphysical ideas.[801]

If this hypothesis is correct, then al-Fârâbï’s cosmology can be divided into two main periods: a first one corresponding to an ‘early Baghdad phase’ and another one corresponding to the end of his stay in Baghdad as well as his sojourn in Syria and Egypt, which may be called al-Fârâbï’s ‘late Baghdad and wandering phase.’ From an early creationist model which he adopted partly as a result of his contact with the Baghdadi Christian thinkers, especially Mattâ ibn Yûnus, and the influence of the Philoponian and Kindïan legacies, al-Fârâbï subse­quently and gradually elaborated his own cosmological interpretation of the origin of matter and the world by articulating a complex theory of causality and intellection. This model, apparently for the first time in Arabic philosophy, explicitly posits a level of intellectual beings (uqül mufariqah or thawant) between the First and the corporeal world. Accordingly, Jam, Jawabat, Radd, Ihsa’, Ft mayanbaght, and possibly Aghrad, as well as many of the logical treatises composed by al-Fârâbï, such as K. al-‘ibdrah and K. al-qiyas, would all have been composed during this same period. What these works have in common apart from the doctrinal overlap is a propaedeutic quality either to the study of logic or Aristotelian philosophy, and a clear connection with the Alexandrian school curriculum. In contrast, Ára, Siyasah, Fusül, Tahstl, and Ft l-‘aql would have been composed toward the end of al-Fârâbï’s life, with the hypothetical insertion of Falsafat Aristütalts as a transi­tional work, although the evidence in this case is ambiguous. The most mature expression of this new causative model is to be found in Siyasah, which is similar to Ára in many ways, but which also contains certain elaborations (notably with regard to causality) suggesting that it may have been al-Fârâbï’s last composition. It should be noted that this clas­sification of part of the Fârâbïan corpus agrees in many respects with, and would seem to support, the views of past scholars concerning the late dating of the emanationist works.

All in all, one can not only point to substantial doctrinal evidence supporting this shift, but also partially explain why and how it may have taken place by identifying some of the late antique sources that nourished it and some of the biographical and social factors that trig­gered it. Some of the key stages in al-Fârâbï’s philosophical evolution can therefore be convincingly reconstructed. It is this multi-layered and comprehensive explanatory scheme that, in my opinion, makes the developmentalist hypothesis particularly compelling and well worth investigating in more depth.

But additional concluding remarks are in order, given the length of the previous analysis. The study argued that the evidence concerning celestial matter in the Fârâbïan corpus points to an evolution in al-Fârâbï’s theorizing of this issue, which is closely tied to his views on causation and creation. In contrast to his early works, his mature cos­mological model presents a completely different explanation of how matter and celestial substance relate to the First. While in Jam’ and Jawâbât matter is created by God ex nihilo, absolutely, and with time, in Ára and Siyasah it is the separate intellects that are responsible for the eternal causation of the celestial bodies. And it is these celestial bodies that in turn sustain the continuous existence of prime matter and ena­ble the processes of generation and corruption to perpetually occur in the sublunary world. This model is based on a complex articulation of causality. It introduces a level of immaterial, intellectual entities between the First and the material world that are autonomous causes of existence for the lower existents, but which themselves are inscribed in a movement of reversion expressed by the notion of final causality.

At this point, one is in a better position to assess al-Fârâbï’s interpre­tation of Aristotelian cosmology and particularly his conception of how matter relates to creation. In his putative early Baghdad phase, al-Fârâbï defended an interpretation of Aristotle’s aether theory that was chiefly shaped by his philosophical education at the hands of the Christian thinkers and by the influence of Kindïan and Neoplatonic sources, the latter in the form of the Plotinus arabus and Proclus arabus. One striking feature of this approach is its particular theorization of two central cosmological tenets, aether or the theory of incorruptible celestial matter, and the creation of the world out of nothing and together with time, which remarkably were reconciled in a single and integrated picture. In this respect, al-Fârâbï’s position might have been considerably influenced by al-Kindï, who had already achieved a similar synthesis in his works and who relied to this end on a variety of philosophical sources, many of which also informed al-Fârâbï’s early works. In addition, it would seem from the brief analysis I pro­vided on this subject that al-Fârâbï’s creationist position could have been anticipated by his teacher Matta ibn Yûnus, whose surviving writ­ings also display some of the key features characteristic of this model. Yet more evidence is required to substantiate this hypothesis.

Later on in his life, especially as a result of his deeper engagement with the late antique commentaries and Proclus’ and possibly Syrianus’ theories of intellection and causation, al-Fârâbï abandoned this cosmo­gonical paradigm and articulated a very different cosmological doc­trine. This new doctrine is characterized by an elaborate model of eternal causation grounded in the concept of (self-)intellection and by a new definition of the celestial substance. It is remarkable that al- Fârâbï’s views on celestial matter and its causation seem to have evolved in perfect parallelism, yet in diametrically opposite directions during these stages of philosophical development. The aether-creationist model of his early treatises can be contrasted to the substrate-causative model of the emanationist works. This suggests that al-Fârâbï regarded these two issues as being intimately connected and that they evolved side by side in his cosmological reflection.

The analysis also provided a reinterpretation, or rather a reassess­ment, of the role of the Neoplatonica arabica in this intellectual devel­opment. First, it was shown that although al-Fârâbï already relied on the Neoplatonica arabica when composing his creationist works, as is clear from various terminological and conceptual parallels, it does not seem justified to infer on these grounds that the cosmology these works put forth are in any way similar to, or reconcilable with, the one that appears in the late metaphysical treatises, as some scholars have argued. For the use that al-Fârâbï makes of these Arabic Neoplatonic sources appears idiosyncratic in both cases. With regard to the creationist trea­tises, they are construed through a creationist lens and employed to buttress his cosmogonical thesis. In contrast, the material al-Fârâbï borrows and adapts from them in his emanationist treatises is inte­grated in an eternalist scheme and used to articulate a theory of causa­tion and intellection that finds no trace in the early creationist works. Hence, it would seem that al-Fârâbï’s study of this Neoplatonic corpus, while spread over his entire life, was achieved for different purposes at different times.[802]

Second, the analysis addressed the problem of al-Fârâbï’s cognizance of the authorship of the Neoplatonica arabica. Many scholars have assumed that al-Fârâbï was aware throughout his life that Theology of Aristotle and Mahd al-khayr were not composed by Aristotle and origi­nated in a philosophical milieu distinct from the Peripatetic tradi­tion.[803] We have seen that this view cannot be convincingly upheld with regard to al-Fârâbï’s creationist or early Baghdad phase. But what about the later metaphysical treatises? Even in this case, I believe that al-Fârâbï’s understanding of the Neoplatonica arabica was in fact murk­ier than we think. To begin with, not once in his entire corpus does al-Fârâbï attribute the texts from Neoplatonica arabica to Plotinus or Proclus.[804] This hint is admittedly not decisive, but it is revealing. For why is it that in the emanationist treatises, which rely substantially on Proclean theories, al-Fârâbï never mentions Proclus, nor does he con­sciously inscribe himself in any kind of Neoplatonic tradition—even though he may rightly be defined in many respects as a worthy heir of Proclean metaphysics? In other words, al-Fârâbï never claims an intel­lectual lineage that connects him with this Greek thinker in contradis­tinction to the Aristotelian philosophical tradition. If anything, al-Fârâbï regards himself as building on Aristotle’s philosophical project, which is the foundation of his own approach to metaphysics and cosmology. In that sense, he does not differ from Ibn Sïnâ, who, while seeing himself as a more or less faithful exponent of Aristotelian cosmology and metaphysics, also drew generously from the Proclus arabus—perhaps via al-Fârâbï—when elaborating his theories of intel­lection and causation.

A telling illustration of this phenomenon focuses on these two phi­losophers’ interpretation of Aristotle’s theory of the unmoved movers. Al-Fârâbï provides such a compelling and harmonizing interpretation of the nature, activity, and intellection of these unmoved movers by combining Aristotelian and Neoplatonic theories, that there is a strong reason to believe that in his eyes he was merely synthesizing and bring­ing together the various theories of a single author. This hypothesis is strengthened by the mention of Aristotle’s Metaphysics, Book Lambda, in his account of the separate intellects and the First—including their role as efficient causes—that appears at the end of Ft l-aql.[805] It is also supported by the fact that Ibn Sïnâ, who achieved a similar synthesis of Aristotelian and Neoplatonic material and ascribed both final and effi­cient causation to the separate intellects, believed his cosmological interpretation of the unmoved movers to be fully compatible and aligned with Aristotle’s original doctrine.[806]

In any case, the thorny problem of al-Fârâbï’s conception of the his­tory of Greek Neoplatonism cannot be solved here and calls for addi­tional research. But regardless of the degree of his awareness of this philosophical tradition, and from the perspective of modern source analysis, there can be little doubt that his cosmology and metaphysics are in many respects a genuine continuation of Neoplatonism and served as one of the main channels for the diffusion of this intellectual current in later falsafah. More specifically, the analysis showed that al-Fârâbï was influenced by the Athenian Neoplatonic tradition as embodied in the works of Proclus and his master Syrianus, in addition to the trend of Alexandrian Neoplatonism already discussed by D. Gutas, R. Wisnovsky, A. Bertolacci, and others.

It is chiefly with regard to his theories of causation and intellection that al-Fârâbï reveals both the degree of his reliance on these Neoplatonic sources and the creativity of his philosophical approach. He is the first thinker in the history of Arabic thought to provide a compelling eter- nalist cosmological model grounded in the concepts of efficient and final causation. This model was the fruit of a long and complex philo­sophical maturation and of a gradual development of his understand­ing of ancient Greek cosmology. It enabled him to provide a new explanation of the bonds between the various existents of the cosmos, first between the celestial orbs, souls, and intellects, then between the various separate intellects themselves, and, finally, between the First and the thawânt. Al-Fârâbï’s theory of causation is further connected with the key concept of intellection, or more precisely, self-intellection, through which he explains the existence and subsistence of all the superlunary beings and their rational aspiration to reach the highest perfections of their substance. It is through intellection that efficient and final causality are manifested in al-Fârâbï’s metaphysics, and it is by elaborating on this complex of concepts that he may truly be said to perpetuate a Neoplatonic metaphysical outlook in the early Islamic context.

In this respect, one may venture to conclude that al-Fârâbï’s views on the activity and nature of the separate intellects indicate that he could not emancipate himself completely from the polytheistic worldview of late antiquity, especially as it was embodied in Proclus’ and Syrianus’ metaphysics. But then, there is no convincing reason to think that this was al-Fârâbï’s intention or that his chief motivation was to elaborate an ‘Islamic’ philosophy, as some scholars have claimed. Much of the evidence points to the contrary. In al-Fârâbï’s cosmology, the ways in which God and the separate intellects cause their effects are not clearly distinguished. Both God and the separate intellects are defined as effi­cient and final causes and possess an autonomous power to induce existence in the beings situated below them. In that sense, al-Fârâbï’s cosmology is devoid of a true doctrine of divine creation, in the sense usually understood in medieval Islamic intellectual history. His mature theory of causality contrasts with the creationist ideas that were in wide circulation in many Christian and Muslim circles in Baghdad and to which al-Fârâbï probably adhered in his early phase.


CHAPTER FOUR

THE APORIA OF CELESTIAL MOTION

1. The Various Motions of the Heavenly Bodies

This last chapter will focus on al-Farabi’s views on celestial motion and its underlying causes, a theme which has received little attention in the scholarship on al-Farabi and falsafah in general.[807] Any attempt to construct a viable cosmological system must include an account of how the celestial bodies move through space. The theories of Plato in Timaeus and of the author of Epinomis,[808] Aristotle in On the Heavens, Metaphysics, and Meteorology, and of Ptolemy in Almagest and Planetary Hypotheses, as well as the late antique commentaries written on some of these works, presented medieval philosophers and astronomers with a variety of cosmological ideas and with several compelling kinematic models. The popularity of some of these texts, such as Metaphysics and Planetary Hypotheses, rested partly on their successful synthesis of astronomical theories and physical and/or metaphysical principles and on the fact that they provided a comprehensive picture of the heavens and a clear explanation of the causes of celestial motion.

The reception of some of these seminal texts in the classical Islamic period was enriched and mediated by the commentatorial tradition that flourished in late antiquity. During this time, many interpretations of celestial motion were developed, some of which were basically a reworking of Aristotle’s or Plato’s theories, while others appeared to present innovative solutions to this problem. Depending on the author, celestial motion could be caused by a natural inclination in the heav­enly body, by matter, soul, will, and even, according to Philoponus’ original idea, by a force or impetus that God imparted to the universe at the instant of creation. Consequently, these philosophers disagreed profoundly on the causality and purpose of celestial motion, a debate which had various physical and metaphysical ramifications and occu­pied much space in these commentaries.[809]

While some of these issues continued in the early Arabic context, and while we have an idea of which Greek cosmological sources were translated into Arabic, it is not always easy to trace the textual origin of some of the specific concepts discussed by the falasifah in their works. As we shall see shortly, this problem is acute in the case of al-Fârâbï, because he draws on various kinematic concepts that were discussed at length by the commentators, but he rarely if ever acknowledges their authority. At any rate, the previous remarks define Arabic cosmologists as the heirs of a long tradition of debate with regard to heavenly motion. Al-Fârâbï and Ibn Sïnâ had access not only to the works of Aristotle and Ptolemy, but also to some excerpts of Philoponus’ refutation of Aristotelian dynamics, as well as to various fragmentary texts by Alexander, Themistius, Proclus, and possibly Simplicius. In the case of al-Fârâbï, one may even surmise that he knew elements of the Syriac cosmological tradition due to his association with Nestorian transla­tors and philosophers.[810]

As may be expected of a faylasüf writing in tenth-century Baghdad, that is, during a period of intense astronomical activity, al-Fârâbï’s theory of motion displays a vivid concern for astronomical facts and aims to achieve a synthesis of astronomical and philosophical ideas. He discusses themes that overlap with the science of mathematical astronomy, such as the general and particular motions of the planets. However, he also examines the physical and metaphysical implications of heavenly motion, such as its causes and effects, the relation between circular motion and the perfection of the heavenly bodies, motion and intellection, and differences in spatial relation as a kind of deficiency. It is the juxtaposition of these various elements derived from a variety of philosophical and astronomical sources that makes al-Fârâbï’s cos­mological system a perfect illustration of the cosmopolitanism of medieval Islamic intellectual history.

Considering the richness of this textual background, it is disappoint­ing to realize that al-Fârâbï does not devote much space in his extant works to celestial motion. It should be borne in mind, however, that the works in which extensive analyses of this topic were offered, namely, in his commentaries on On the Heavens and on Almagest, as well as in his treatises Kitab al-nujum and Kitab ft anna harakat al-falak sarmadi- yyah, have not survived.[811] This means that any reconstruction of al-Fârâbï’s kinematic theories is restricted to the few relevant passages that can be gleaned from his extant works and on a certain amount of conjecture.[812]

Two reasons may be given to account for this fact in addition to the loss of many of al-Fârâbï’s works. While al-Fârâbï surely discussed celestial motion in depth in his commentary on Almagest, he might on the other hand have considered that it was not the proper context and aim (skopós) of his philosophical treatises to address this issue. As al-Fârâbï explains in Ihsa ’, investigation into the variations of the heav­enly bodies’ movements is one of the main tasks of mathematical astronomy. But as we have seen, al-Fârâbï’s cosmology extends beyond the astronomical discipline to embrace physics and metaphysics as well. In his metaphysical treatises, al-Fârâbï’s approach to the cosmos does not privilege an in-depth treatment of celestial motion, because he is more concerned with other cosmological problems, such as sub­stance, existence, and intellection, which fall within the purview of physics and metaphysics. Since the substance and existence of the heav­enly orbs are no doubt points of greater interest to al-Fârâbï than the question of motion, at least in these treatises, it is understandable that he would have relegated the latter to a secondary place in his philo­sophical treatises.

The second reason is that al-Fârâbï may not have had a com­pletely worked out theory of celestial motion. Indeed, he may have experienced some difficulty in reconciling the various and often contradictory kinematic doctrines of his predecessors, especially those of Aristotle, Ptolemy, and Alexander of Aphrodisias. If al-Fârâbï was hesitant regarding this issue, it is understandable that he would have been reluctant to discuss it in detail in his works. In spite of this, Ára in particular contains brief but interesting comments on celestial motion, both with regard to its causes and nature. In addition, relevant information can be found in Siyasah, Fl l-aql, and Müslqa, while Uyün and Taltqat are discussed in appendix 1 due to their problematic authorship. In the following paragraphs, I rely on these works to recon­struct al-Fârâbï’s kinematic model as accurately as possible. Apart from providing a general picture of al-Fârâbï’s views on this subject, the analysis will pay particular attention to the relation between the sepa­rate intellects and the orbs and to how Aristotelian, Neoplatonic, and Ptolemaic theories interact in his account of celestial motion.

According to al-Fârâbï, all the heavenly bodies are characterized by circular motion, the most perfect type of motion.[813] To begin with, the ninth, outermost orb, also called the first heaven (al-sama l-üla) and the first body (al-jism al-awwal), possesses a single and regular west­ward motion that elapses in a day and a night and that marks a com­plete revolution of the heaven on itself.[814] This ‘first’ motion is imparted by the ninth orb to all the other orbs that are contained in it, with the result that the heaven as a whole has a common circular movement from east to west.[815] However, these orbs and spheres also have their own particular motions.[816] The orb of the fixed stars shares the motion of the outermost orb and also possesses a second, eastward motion proper to it, the precession. As for the other seven main planetary orbs below the orb of the fixed stars, they also participate in the general westward motion of the ninth orb, but in addition possess other particular east­erly motions that distinguish them. It is these particular motions that explain the unique trajectories of the wandering planets in the firma­ment, namely, Saturn, Jupiter, Mars, Venus, and Mercury, in addition to the sun and moon. It is worth noting that al-Fârâbï believes, like Aristotle, that heavenly motion is eternal and constant and gives the measure of time.[817]

This kinematic account is clearly indebted to Ptolemaic astronomy. The idea that the heavens possess two basic kinds of motion—a univer­sal westward motion (harakat al-kull or al-harakat al-kulliyyah in the Arabic texts) and particular easterly motions—is developed in sections 1.8 and 7.2-3 of Almagest and in Planetary Hypotheses,[818] and it was sub­sequently accepted as a fundamental astronomical tenet by most Arabic and Latin authors.[819] But one point deserves more attention. There is some ambiguity in Ptolemy’s works as to what causes the universal westward motion. In Planetary Hypotheses, Ptolemy describes the heavens as a cosmic animal (hayawan kulli),[820] which suggests that the universal motion may be regarded as a kind of power shared by all the orbs and animating a single organism. But as G. Saliba pointed out, Ptolemy in the same work posits the existence of a ninth orb in order to account for the precession of the orb of the fixed stars, and it is this ninth orb which is also presumably responsible for imparting the universal motion to the other orbs.[821] Al-Fârâbï, in contrast, never com­pares the heavens to a single living organism, and he believes that they are made of several distinct and independent units or groups (sing. jumlah). It is therefore reasonable to surmise that he made the ninth outermost orb the direct cause of the daily westward motion of the lower orbs. This seems substantiated by his statement in Siyasah that “all [the celestial bodies] are connected with the power [quwwah] of the first heaven, which is one, and consequently they all move by virtue of the motion of the first heaven.”[822]

Al-Fârâbï also follows Ptolemy’s view that each planet possesses sev­eral motions that are proper to it and define its particular trajectory in the heavens. In Ára, for example, al-Fârâbï states that while the first heaven has only one motion and the orb of the fixed stars has two motions, the third to ninth orbs possess “motions that are numerous and different” (harakatuha kathtrah mukhtalifah). This view also appears in Siyasah, where the celestial bodies are said to revolve around the earth “with many kinds of motions,” as well as in a short passage of Müstqâ.[823] In addition to having its own particular motion, each orb and sphere also revolves with a different speed. This is explained by al-Fârâbï in two ways. First, he argues that each orb and sphere possesses an “essential” motion and velocity (laha ft anfusiha wa-bi-l-dhat) that dif­fers from that of the other orbs and spheres and whose speed is fixed and does not change. Hence, the speed of each orb is from the outset unique and remains so for all time. The second factor is the varying positions of the spheres and orbs, which create variations in the speed with which the planets travel around the earth.[824]

Al-Fârâbï’s recognition of a variety of planetary motions, each pos­sessing its own qualities and velocity, is a key feature of his cosmology as well as of other ancient and medieval models that rely extensively on Ptolemaic astronomy. In the larger context of his natural philosophy, it helps to explain his view of how the influences coming from the heav­ens can be responsible for causing the diversity of the sublunary existents. According to al-Fârâbï, the plurality of causes coming from the heavens leads to a plurality of effects in the sublunary world. With regard to ontology, the changing relations between the velocities and positions of the planets and orbs are the only accidents that affect the heavenly bodies and make them “the first of the deficient existents,” although it is an insignificant accident that does not pertain to their inner substance.

It should also be stressed that the thesis of multiple planetary motions raised a host of issues for medieval thinkers interested in clari­fying the underlying causes of these phenomena. The reason for this is that a single cause was rightly deemed insufficient to account for this multiplicity, and so a multi-layered account identifying various levels of causes had to be elaborated. Al-Fârâbï’s cosmology is a case in point. Although he is straightforwardly following Ptolemy and other Arabic thinkers in his basic account of the various kinds of heavenly motions, as a physicist and metaphysician he was also interested in the principles behind these phenomena. But the account he provides in his extant works, particularly with respect to the particular planetary motions, is marked by ambiguity. There is no detailed elucidation of how these different motions occur and of the underlying causal process. To say that each celestial body has a motion and velocity that is essential and specific to it does not in any way clarify the nature of its cause. Is it due to soul (nafs) or intellect (‘aql), inclination (mayl), or matter (maddah)? And what is the causal role of the eccentrics and epicycles in this picture? The following section examines these questions and attempts to shed some light on al-Fârâbï’s views on kinematic causality.

2. The Causes of Celestial Motion

2.1. Nature and Motion: An Impasse

I already broached the issue of celestial nature in chapter 2 in connec­tion with the bodies and souls of the orbs. Here I wish to provide addi­tional remarks about its relevance to celestial motion, first by providing a short overview of this question in the late antique context, and sec­ond, by focusing on the information contained in al-Fârâbï’s works.

In the late antique exegetical tradition that developed in an attempt to clarify and explain the works of Plato and Aristotle, there was much disagreement as to what constitutes natural motion in the heavens and how it is caused.[825] Celestial motion was interpreted in light of many different principles such as matter, inclination, soul, or intellect, depending on whether one relied chiefly on Aristotle or Plato and which principle was used to define the nature (^ùorç) of the heavens. Furthermore, even within the Aristotelian corpus, On the Heavens seemed to posit two alternative models depending on whether one made aether (1.2-4) or soul (2.2) the primary cause of motion. These contradictions were magnified when one compared On the Heavens to the evidence contained in Physics 8 and Metaphysics 12.7-8, according to which the heavenly motion is dependent on an infinite power and requires the postulate of a First Unmoved Mover. But the latter text further complexified the problem by introducing the theory of several unmoved movers responsible for moving the various orbs.

The confusion that emerged as a result of these conflicting views is reflected in the works of the late antique thinkers, who struggled to come up with a conciliatory and harmonizing account of these various trends. Philoponus, for example, held different positions throughout his life and his conception of the nature of the heavens evolved accord­ingly. As a young man, he considered heavenly motion to be caused by both matter and soul, while later in his career he turned to a more physical-theological account to explain the revolution of the heavens by developing the impetus theory: it is the power invested in matter by God at the moment of creation that is responsible for the motion of the orbs.[826] In contrast, Alexander equated celestial nature with soul, so that he conceived of celestial motion as a psychological process caused by the will and desire of the heavenly souls to imitate the unmoved mover(s). Simplicius in turn disagreed with Alexander, because he regarded nature chiefly as a potentiality to undergo change, not to cause it, and he therefore posited a distinction between nature and soul, argu­ing that the heavenly bodies move as a result of their soul acting through their nature.[827]

The previous remarks show the semantic flexibility of the concept of ‘nature’ in an ancient cosmological setting and the diversity of opinions held by the commentators on the question of what constitutes natural motion in the heavens.[828] It is possible that this lack of uniformity in the commentatorial tradition impacted negatively on al-Fârâbï, who does not define celestial nature in an adequate manner in his personal trea­tises. In spite of this, however, a few important points can be extracted from his works.

To begin with, al-Fârâbï does not endow the celestial substance or nature with a particular inclination for circular motion in works con­veying his own doctrines. Whenever he does so, it is always in the con­text of his explanatory or apologetic works on Aristotelian philosophy. Perhaps the most striking example occurs in Radd—a treatise aiming to defend Aristotle’s theory of the elements and aether—when the Second Teacher states that “he [Aristotle] begins with that part of the world which, by its nature [bi-tabtatiht], moves with a circular move­ment.”[829] Another similar statement appears in Falsafat Aristütdlts, where al-Fârâbï explains that “he [Aristotle] investigated whether or not the principles that move the bodies moving in a circular motion by nature [li-l-ajsdm allatt tataharraku harakah mustadtrah bi-l-tab‘] are themselves bodies or whether they are nonbodily essences that are, however, in a material and a body.”[830] Al-Fârâbï was thus aware that Aristotle had endowed the celestial element with a propensity for cir­cular motion and that this circular motion was either “according to nature” (bi-l-tab) or “according to its nature” (bi-tabt atiht), i.e., to the special nature of the heavens. But quite surprisingly at first glance, the Second Teacher seems to have completely neglected the correlation Aristotle establishes between the special celestial matter and circular motion.

This appears clearly if we turn to al-Fârâbï’s mature cosmological treatises. The evidence they contain is quite limited, yet worth discuss­ing. Al-Fârâbï states in Ára that the heavenly bodies move “by their nature” (bi-tabtatiha) and that they “have a common nature [tabïah mushtarakah] through which, by virtue of the motion of the first body, they all come to move round in a circular motion in one day and one night, as a result of the motion of the first body among them.” And he adds shortly after: “For this movement of what is below the first heaven is not brought about by compulsion [qasran], since it is impossible that there should be anything in the heaven which takes place by compul­sion.”[831] These passages explicitly connect the celestial nature (ta btah) with the circular motion of the orbs. But in what sense are we to under­stand this concept of nature?

First, it is noteworthy that al-Fârâbï adopts in these passages a well- known ancient Greek cosmological tenet according to which celestial motion is essentially harmonious and natural and devoid of compul­sion or contrition. Al-Fârâbï sets in opposition motion ‘by nature’ and motion ‘by compulsion,’ limiting the latter concept to the rectilinear movements of sublunary bodies. This basic opposition harkens back to Aristotle’s theory of the elements as exposed in On the Heavens 1.2-4, according to which the four primary elements all possess a natural place which they reach through rectilinear motions (such as the down­ward motion of earth and the upward motion of fire). As a result, these elements cannot move in the opposite direction except through com­pulsion. Since the heavens do not possess a rectilinear motion and a natural place, Aristotle concludes On the Heavens 1.2 by positing the existence of a fifth element, aether, which possesses an inherent circu­lar motion.

Second, since al-Fârâbï makes the celestial souls the proximate mov­ers of the orbs and planets, it is likely that he agreed with Alexander in construing celestial nature psychologically, that is, as being reducible to the celestial souls. Support for this hypothesis also comes from Ibn Sïnâ’s cosmology, which is in many ways modelled on that of al-Fârâbï, and which establishes a clear link between the celestial souls and a special celestial nature (ta biah), although it does not conflate these two concepts in the manner that Alexander would have. In Metaphysics of Shifa, Ibn Sïnâ explains that this celestial nature is “an emanation from a soul [tabiatahü fayd ’an nafs] that is renewed in accordance with the soul’s act of acquiring representation.”[832] On this view, the celestial nature is more closely connected with the celestial soul, from which it ultimately derives, than with the inherent circular propensity of aether or celestial matter. The evidence suggests that al-Fârâbï envisaged celes­tial nature in a similar way, since his cosmology emphasizes the impor­tance of soul and downplays or even neglects celestial matter. However, the passage from Ára quoted above that mentions the “common nature” of the orbs is somewhat difficult to reconcile with the concept of soul, for al-Fârâbï believes in the existence of several distinct celestial souls, and not of one single soul pervading the entire heavens. Exactly how this statement should be interpreted in the context of al-Fârâbï’s cos­mology is unclear.

Finally, it is worth pointing out that tabiah also had a more specific astronomical meaning, which rests on the idea of a simple, regular motion from east to west shared by all the orbs. Indeed, Ptolemy in Planetary Hypotheses explains the regularity and harmony of the orbs’ motions by referring to their tabiah.[833] Al-Fârâbï’s mention in Ára’ of a “common nature” (tabiah mushtarakah) of the orbs through which they follow the motion of the outermost orb may definitely be con­strued in this sense and could be based directly on Hypotheses. But here too we are faced with the problem of understanding what Ptolemy means by nature, since he accepts the existence of aether and in addi­tion posits planetary souls.[834] Since ta bi’ah is defined primarily by the regularity of the celestial motions in an astronomical context regard­less of whether soul is taken to be a cause of motion, and since Ptolemy mentions aether several times in Planetary Hypotheses, sometimes even explicitly in connection with the nature of the orbs,[835] it is reasonable to conclude that he made aether at least partly responsible for this natural celestial motion. As for al-Fârâbï, he says nothing about a spe­cial heavenly element. Yet his use of the concept of nature in this par­ticular passage of Ára could stem from the astronomical tradition and could have been intended simply to point to the harmonious, regular motion shared by the orbs, regardless of its ultimate principle. Al-Fârâbï’s mention of nature in connection with celestial motion may also serve to emphasize the notion of cosmic harmony and order: every part of the universe fulfills the particular role that is assigned to it by nature and according to the order of being; nothing occurs through compulsion or randomness.

It is worth raising the question here of whether al-Fârâbï may, like Ibn Sïnâ, have distinguished between motion “by nature” (bi-l-tab‘) and “natural motion” (harakah ta btiyyah). Ibn Sïnâ sometimes opposes the psychological motion of the orbs to the natural motion of sublu­nary bodies, explaining that the revolution of the heavens cannot be due to a nature (tabt ah) or be defined as natural (tabïï). According to this thinker, the celestial motion may be said to be “by nature” (bi-l- ta b‘) in the sense that it is not brought about by compulsion.[836] Al-Fârâbï, in contrast to Ibn Sïnâ, uses both expressions bi-l-tabï’ah and bi-l-tab‘ synonymously with regard to the heavens—the latter term appears once in Falsafat Aristütalïs to describe the doctrine of the Stagirite[837]— and in a way that allows us to connect them with the “common [celes­tial] nature” (tabï’ah mushtarakah) he speaks of in another passage.[838] Al-Fârâbï therefore uses the terms tabï’ah and tabïïindiscriminately in both a superlunary and sublunary context, even though the “common nature” he ascribes to the heavens clearly possesses its own characteris­tics. True, in Ithbat, a work ascribed to the Second Teacher, the author argues that celestial motion is “not natural” (ghayr tabï’iyyah), a view which is reiterated in Da’awa when the author writes that “the motion of the celestial body is spiritual, not natural” (wa-inna harakatahü nafsaniyyah la tabiiyyah)[839] But there is a strong possibility that these two works may have been composed in the Ibn Sïnâ circle.[840]

Overall, then, al-Fârâbï’s mention of a celestial nature is of very little help to understand the causes of celestial motion.[841] The only thing that may be established with some certainty is that al-Fârâbï believes heav­enly motion takes place “by nature” as opposed to “by compulsion.” But it is unfortunately not possible to further determine what meaning this term conveys and what causal efficacy it possesses, due to al-Fârâbï’s laconic style and the absence of more substantial evidence in his works.

2.2.    Quwwah

Quwwah is another key concept that requires clarification. To my knowledge, it is mentioned only twice in al-Fârâbï’s corpus in connec­tion with the motion of the celestial bodies: in K. al-ibarah and in Siyasah[842] Both occurrences will be examined below.

Like the concept of nature (^ùoiç), power (Sùvaqiç in Greek) has a rich history in ancient philosophy. Plato mentions the “powers” of the celestial bodies on numerous occasions in his works, as does the author of the Epinomis[843] In Ptolemy’s Planetary Hypotheses, which may have been influenced by the Platonic tradition in this regard, power (quw­wah in the Arabic translation) refers to the planets’ ability to induce its own circular motion. According to A. Murschel, this power should be associated with the psychological faculty of the planets, although it does not necessarily involve any intellectual activity.[844] Quwwah is also a central philosophical concept in the Arabic translations of Aristotle, where it may be translated as ‘potentiality,’ ‘faculty,’ or ‘power’ depend­ing on the context. More specifically, however, quwwah appears in Aristotle’s discussion of the Unmoved Mover in Physics and Metaphysics, where it serves to designate the continuous power and actuality of God.[845] Finally, it is also used by the author of Mahd al-khayr in connec­tion with the various activities of soul, and in Theology of Aristotle to signify the power emanated from the soul onto the world of nature.[846] Although al-Fârâbï may have derived the notion of quwwah from any of these sources, the cosmological context in which he uses this term establishes a connection with Physics and Metaphysics on the one hand and with Ptolemy’s Planetary Hypotheses on the other.

In al-Fârâbï’s cosmology, quwwah usually does not mean potential­ity, but rather power, since the celestial bodies are always in motion and in a state of actuality.[847] However, in the case of celestial motion, the heavenly bodies may be said to possess both a power and potentiality for only one type of activity, namely, circular motion.[848] Unlike sublu­nary bodies, whose quwwah embraces the opposites of action and inac­tion, the heavenly bodies’ power is only for action. In K. al-‘ibarah, al-Fârâbï writes: “There is another kind of power [quwwah], namely, readiness for one of the opposites alone, such as the power of circular motion, which is in the heavenly bodies.”[849] As al-Tahânawï’s Isti lâhât al-’ulüm al-islamiyyah reveals, this meaning of quwwah as power and its association with the perpetual circular motion of the heavens were widespread in the Arabic cosmological tradition.[850]

But what exactly is the function of quwwah in al-Fârâbï’s kinematics? In order to answer this question, we must look at the other instance in which this term appears. In Siyasah one reads:

All [the celestial bodies] are connected with the power [quwwah] of the first heaven, which is one, and consequently they all move by virtue of the motion of the first heaven. They have other powers [quwan] by virtue of which they are distinct from one another and by virtue of which their motions differ.[851]

The first occurrence of the term quwwah in this passage expresses a ‘force’ or ‘influence’ that is transmitted by the first, outermost orb to the other orbs below it. This power need not be construed as a psychologi­cal one and may simply consist of a mechanical force transmitted as a result of the proximity of the orbs. Indeed, all the heavenly orbs are contained in the outermost orb, whose convex surface constitutes the physical limit of the universe and whose motion is communicated to all the other bodies within it, except the earth. The problem, however, is that, as we shall see shortly, al-Fârâbï considers soul the main principle of celestial motion, so that there is the strong possibility that quwwah should be interpreted in connection with soul. It is probably in this manner that the second reference to the quwan of the celestial bodies should be construed, for it is more difficult in this case to explain these other powers in purely mechanical terms, since they are specific to each orb and do not influence the other orbs around them. But even the first occurrence of quwwah can be reconciled with a psychological account, in the sense that the motive power of the outermost orb could issue from its soul, and this power then be transmitted through its rotating body.

The connection between soul and power in a celestial context will be discussed in the forthcoming section on the principles of motion. Suffice it to say here that it was not an innovation by al-Fârâbï and can be traced to the Arabic version of Planetary Hypotheses, which men­tions the quwwah of the planets on several occasions.[852] Ptolemy defines it as a vital force or psychological faculty or power associated with the celestial bodies, which are described as animated, living beings. As A. Murschel writes, “Ptolemy also claims that the celestial bodies maintain a faculty (quwwa) which may be compared to the human faculties of vision and intelligence, but his use of such a comparison does not imply that he believed that the planets have the ability to see or perform some mental function.”[853] As we shall see shortly, al-Fârâbï and Ibn Sïnâ likely interpreted this power in connection with the con­templative activity of soul, an interpretation that would have seemed all the more natural to them since Ptolemy himself asserts the ensoul- ment of the orbs.[854] Unfortunately, al-Fârâbï does not provide additional insight into this topic, and so it is unclear whether quwwah should be interpreted ultimately as a power emanating from the celestial soul specifically or as a disposition in the celestial body as a whole. Again in this case, we are faced with a dearth of evidence that prevents any deci­sive conclusions.

2.3.    Intellection as a Cause of Motion

2.3.1.    Ára, Siyasah, and Ft l-‘aql

Given that al-Fârâbï does not stress the correlation between celestial matter and motion, it is not surprising that he turned to other princi­ples to explain the phenomena of the planetary motions. When al-Fârâbï writes that the orbs move “by their nature,” he is not thinking of a material principle or a special heavenly element that would possess an inherent circular motion, but rather of more fundamental princi­ples, namely, soul and intellect.

In contradistinction to the correlation made in On the Heavens between aether and circular motion, Plato’s Laws and Timaeus, the Epinomis, and Aristotle’s Metaphysics (I am assuming here that the orbs of Book Lambda 7 and 8 are ensouled) develop a different interpreta­tion of celestial kinematics that focuses on soul. This psychological theory, which was later adopted and developed by other thinkers such as Alexander, Themistius, Simplicius, and Proclus, and which also influenced Ptolemy’s Planetary Hypotheses, emphasizes the role of the heavenly souls as movers of the orbs. In the process of discussing these issues, however, these authors elaborated on more specific concepts, such as desire, will, intellection, and power, which they weaved into their accounts and which often represented substantial departures from the foundational texts of Plato and Aristotle.

The few relevant passages that can be gleaned from al-Fârâbï’s works show that he definitely belongs to this ‘psychological’ trend, which makes soul the main cause of celestial motion. In Siyasah, he writes that the celestial bodies “move in circular fashion by virtue of their [souls]” (wa-anha tataharraku dawran)4 The psychological process that results in motion is not further described by al-Fârâbï in this pas­sage, and the reader may wonder at the role that the celestial souls and separate intellects play respectively in this account. It is notable that this is the only piece of evidence in the emanationist works that explic­itly connects heavenly soul and motion.

Ithbat—whose authenticity, it should be stressed, is uncertain— provides more information on this topic. This short treatise is designed to provide proofs for the existence of the metaphysical beings. Al-Fârâbï begins by discussing the existence of God and the separate intellects, and then lists three proofs for the existence of the celestial souls (al-nufus al-sama iyyah), all of them based on motion. The first one argues that natural motion (al-harakah al-tabt iyyah) occurs only when a thing is in a non-natural state and seeks to return to its natural state, which is rest. But rest does not apply to the heavens, whose motion therefore cannot be natural. The second proof affirms that a body seeks a place of rest according to the shortest and most direct path, which is necessarily rectilinear. The heavens, in contrast, always move in circles, thereby showing that they are different in this respect. The third argu­ment opposes the mechanical motion of the natural elements that can never avoid their goal (unless they are impeded) to the free, volitional motion of the heavens. The author concludes by saying that circular motion is “not natural, but arises from soul and choice” (fa-hiya idhan ghayr tabïiyyah fa-hiya nafsaniyyah ikhtiydriyyah).[855] [856]

It is notable that these proofs are mostly negative. They do not posi­tively show that the celestial souls must exist, but rather infer this from the impossibility of conceiving of celestial motion as a natural phe­nomenon. The rationale is that if celestial motion is not natural, then it must be psychological. Regardless of the philosophical value of these arguments, they stress the author’s belief in the ensoulment of the orbs and in the spiritual cause of celestial motion and thus should be read in conjunction with al-Fârâbï’s emanationist works. In addition, it should be stressed that Ithbat is the only text that explicitly mentions the choice (ikhtiyar) of the heavenly bodies.

So far I have discussed the role of the celestial souls in motion, but what about the separate intellects? Fl l-aql sheds light on this question, although it by no means offers a systematic treatment of it. Toward the end of the treatise, which is primarily devoted to the various definitions of the term ‘intellect’ (aql) formulated by philosophers and theolo­gians, al-Fârâbï states the following:

Every celestial body is set in motion only by a mover [muharrik] that is neither a body nor in a body in any way. [This mover] is the cause of [the celestial body’s] existence [huwa l-sabab fl wujüdihï], inasmuch as it is that by virtue of which [the celestial body] is a substance, but its level, in terms of the existence that is [the celestial body’s] substance, is the same as that body. The mover of the more perfect of [the celestial bodies] is the more perfect in terms of existence, and the more perfect in terms of exist­ence is the mover of the first heaven.

This passage is valuable because it shows that al-Fârâbï adhered to Aristotle’s theory of the unmoved movers. Each one of these movers (sing. muharrik) is immaterial and separate from the orb and responsi­ble for the latter’s motion. Al-Fârâbï then goes on to identify these movers with the separate intellects (thawanl): “Now, since the mover of the first heaven is neither matter nor in matter, it necessarily follows that it is an intellect [‘aql] in its substance.”[857] Al-Fârâbï’s main focus in this entire passage is clearly on noetics and ontology rather than motion per se; he expounds on the role the separate intellects play in causing existence, but says little about their being causes of motion. At any rate, the identification of each mover with a separate intellect in this excerpt is crucial, because it represents the only instance in the Fârâbïan corpus where al-Fârâbï uses the term muharrik explicitly to describe the sepa­rate intellects, even though this equation is implied in his other works. This shows beyond any possible doubt that he perceived his theory of the thawanl as an adaptation of, and as being fully compatible with, Aristotle’s doctrine of the unmoved movers as exposed in Book Lambda 7 and 8.

In contrast to Fï l-‘aql, the description of the relation between the orbs and the separate intellects in Ára and Siyasah is limited to ontol­ogy and intellection and does not directly broach the topic of motion. But these works do not by any means contradict Fï l-aql, and the infor­mation they provide can on the contrary be used to complement it and construct a single and comprehensive cosmological picture. The vari­ous elements discussed in these works can be arranged as follows: each celestial body possesses a rational soul (Ára and Siyasah), which ena­bles it to contemplate its separate intellect (Ára and Siyasah). Since the separate intellects are described as movers (Fïl-‘aql), one may conclude that they act as final causes of motion for the orbs by being an eternal object of thought. Furthermore, since the First is an intelligible and an object of contemplation for the celestial souls (Ára and Siyasah), it also acts as a final cause of motion for the celestial orbs. So far, then, we have identified two main principles of motion: the celestial souls and the separate intellects. The former represent a proximate principle that inheres in the celestial body, the latter a remote principle that is sepa­rate from it. As an additional division, one may distinguish between the thawanï, which are the specific movers of the orbs—each intellect corresponding to a main orb—and the First, which is a universal mover for the entire heaven.

More should be said about this last point. In Ára’ al-Fârâbï mentions the “love” ( ishq) that the heavenly bodies share with the thawanï for the First. In another passage, God is described as the “first object of love and the first object of affection” of the separate intellects.[858] In a similar vein, Siyasah presents God as “the first object of love” (al-mahbüb al-awwal) and “the first thing desired” (al-mashüq al-awwal).[859] All of these passages echo Aristotle’s statement at Metaphysics 12.7.1072b3-4 that the final cause of the heavens “produces motion as being loved.” Although al-Fârâbï does not connect desire, intellection, and motion explicitly in his works, one may easily and justifiably make the link between these various concepts on his behalf. In this picture, the First ignites intellectual love in the celestial souls, which in turn leads them to seek and imitate Its perfections. But since these souls inhere in a substrate and are therefore closely intertwined with the celestial body, they can never attain such perfections and must confine themselves to reproducing at a corporeal level and by means of the most perfect shape, i.e., the circle, the eternal activity of the higher entities. It is as a consequence of this constant search for the higher perfections, which they never attain, that the heavenly bodies perform their eternal revolutions.

In conclusion, then, it is primarily the intellective activity of the celestial souls that is responsible for the revolutions of the orbs, and more precisely, their contemplation of the First and the separate intel­lects, which act as final causes of motion. Although al-Fârâbï does not describe the various stages of this process in detail, he provides hints and some rare statements in his corpus that enable one to recon­struct a fairly convincing picture of his celestial kinematics. This recon­struction is strengthened by the fact that the Second Teacher does not ascribe matter, inclination, or imagination to the orbs, which are other concepts commonly associated with motion in the Greco-Arabic tradi­tion. Conversely, he stresses their purely intellectual nature and defines their main activity as intellection, which is accordingly the primary principle underlying celestial motion. But to what extent is al-Fârâbï following the Arabic versions of Book Lambda on this issue, and to what extent is he following other philosophical and astronomical sources?

2.3.2.    Al-Fârâbï and the Arabic Book Lambda

We know that al-Fârâbï had access to Book Lambda of Metaphysics, Physics, and On the Heavens, and thus that he was in possession of the principal Aristotelian texts dealing with celestial motion. However, al-Fârâbï, unlike Aristotle and many other Greek and Arabic think­ers, does not correlate celestial matter and celestial motion. Despite the ambiguity in On the Heavens as to whether the movements of the orbs are caused by aether or soul, al-Fârâbï unhesitatingly makes soul the main cause of celestial motion. In his cosmology, the concept of soul plays a central role not only at an ontological level with regard to the substantialization (tajawhur) of the heavenly bodies, but also with respect to his theories of motion. Hence, it would seem that On the Heavens exercised relatively little influence on al-Fârâbï’s understanding of Aristotelian celestial kinematics and in the elabora­tion of his own kinematics.

This is definitely not the case of the Arabic version of Book Lambda, which may be seen as one of the foundational texts of al-Fârâbï’s cos­mological system, be it only for the fact that it develops a theory of celestial motion based on the concepts of intellection and desire and that it posits separate unmoved movers in addition to the First Unmoved Mover, two key features that are found in al-Fârâbï’s model as well. I showed in chapter 2 that al-Fârâbï construed this work as positing several separate movers and that in addition he probably relied on vari­ous other cosmological works, such as Themistius’ paraphrase of Book Lambda, Simplicius’ commentary on On the Heavens, and Alexander’s Mabadf, which also discuss these movers. But to what extent is the connection he establishes between intellection and motion foreshad­owed in the Arabic versions of Book Lambda?

The theory that motion is caused by desire and intellection is explic­itly articulated in Mattâ ibn Yûnus’ and Ustâth’s Arabic translations of Book Lambda. In textus 36, one reads that the First Unmoved Mover “imparts motion in the same way as the object of desire and the intel­ligible which is not moved; the first of these are the same”[860]; and in textus 37, that “the principle [of motion] is intellectual representation” and that “it [the Unmoved Mover] imparts motion as object of love.”[861] One finds some departures from the original Greek text in the other translation of Book Lambda published by Badawï, which are even more pertinent to the problem at hand. For example, whereas the Greek text makes a general statement about the identity of the objects of desire and the objects of thought at 12.7.1072a26-28, the Arabic has: “The principle of love is only that which is contemplated from the First Cause” (wa-ibtida l-ishq innama huwa ma yuqal min al-ilah al-üla),[862] thus explicitly identifying the first intelligible with the First, as well as the love It inspires with intellection. Equally significant is the sentence immediately following: “The motion of each intellect is [derived] from the contemplated thing” (fa-kull ‘aql fa-harakatuhü min al-shay’ al-maqül). This passage, which finds no parallel in the original Greek text, is important insofar as it establishes a direct connection between intellection and motion. Although it is not clear which intellect is referred to here, it is easy to imagine that classical Arabic thinkers could construe this passage as applying to the intellects of the orbs. This is especially true in the case of al-Farabi, who defines the celestial souls as intellects. This excerpt may be compared to textus 37 in Ibn Rushd’s Tafstr, especially to the statement that “the principle [of motion] is intellectual representation,” although it states even more emphatically the kinematic implications of intellection.

All in all, then, the Arabic versions of Lambda that have come down to us can account for some of the essential features of al-Farabi’s celes­tial kinematics. Not only can they be read as upholding the existence of several separate unmoved movers—as was shown in chapter 2—but they also present intellection as the principal cause of celestial motion. God and the other movers are objects of desire that inspire the contem­plation and in turn the motion of the celestial souls. The translation of Matta ibn Yûnus and the one edited by Badawi both establish a direct connection between celestial motion and intellection, which is less forcefully conveyed in the original Greek text. These passages provided a general source of inspiration for al-Farabi’s kinematic theory, which he further refined and elaborated by relying on the noetical doctrines articulated in the Proclus arabus. However, other aspects of al-Farabi’s cosmology, such as the radical distinction between the celestial souls and the separate intellects, and the presence of only ten separate intel­lects, are not explicitly articulated in the Arabic versions of Book Lambda and its commentaries and should be regarded as independent cosmological developments.[863]

There is, moreover, a striking astronomical-metaphysical difference between Aristotle’s Book Lambda and al-Farabi’s account. In Aristotle’s cosmology, the outermost orb, which is the orb of the fixed stars, is moved by the First Unmoved Mover, that is, God, who stands at the apex of the hierarchy of movers. At 7.1072a22-24, Aristotle singles out this outermost orb as the first thing moved, which then presumably communicates its motion to the other lower orbs. In contrast, in al-Fârâbï’s cosmology, the outermost starless orb has the first separate intellect or thawânt as a specific mover, not the First. This means that no special relation is established between the First and the outermost orb in the manner achieved by Aristotle in Book Lambda. In al-Fârâbï’s system, in contrast, the First is a universal mover that moves all the orbs by standing as a common object of thought and desire. And it is presumably as a result of their common love and contemplation of It that the celestial bodies derive their basic kinematic impulse and the everlastingness of their motions.[864]

One may thus agree with R. Walzer’s statement that God in al-Fârâbï’s system is not described as the First Unmoved Mover, if by this is under­stood the fact that God is not responsible for moving the outermost orb specifically.[865] However, al-Fârâbï does state that the celestial souls all contemplate and desire God. Since he defines this contemplation as the main principle underlying celestial motion, then God must act as a final cause of motion for the entire heaven according to this model. In this regard God is the First Unmoved Mover, and Walzer’s claim does not hold.

3. The Problem of the Particular Motions of the Planets

The foregoing analysis has clarified al-Fârâbï’s conception of the main principles underlying celestial kinematics, and it has located the source of celestial motion in the contemplative activity of the heavenly souls. However, it has left unanswered the key questions of how the particu­lar motions of the planets occur and of how the diversity of celestial motions can be accounted for from a metaphysical point of view. The crux of the problem can be described as follows. Al-Fârâbï follows Ptolemy in positing a multiplicity of planetary motions from west to east that differ from the diurnal motion of the outermost orb. Each one of these particular motions is performed by a minor orb or sphere associated with the planet. However, al-Fârâbï does not posit one separate intellect or mover per orb and per motion, as Aristotle did, but merely ten separate movers. Hence the question arises: how is this plurality of particular motions possible, and on what grounds is it justified?

This problem is compounded by a cluster of minor, albeit related, issues. First, there is the ambiguity concerning al-Fârâbï’s description of the celestial souls: does each component within a system (planet, eccentric orb, etc.) possess its own distinct soul, or is the planet the only celestial body within its group to be ensouled? Alternatively, is the celestial soul diffused throughout the entire system? In most instances, al-Fârâbï mentions the “souls of the celestial bodies” (anfus al-ajsam al-samawiyyah) without specifying where they should be located. Second, what is the relation between the celestial powers (quwan) and the particular planetary motions? These questions are rendered more difficult by the fact that the existing evidence in al-Fârâbï’s corpus con­cerning the planetary motions is very limited and undermined by much ambiguity. In spite of this, the following paragraphs will provide a hypothetical reconstruction of al-Fârâbï’s views on these various issues by relying on the scant hints in his works and by drawing on the evidence that can be found in Ibn Sïnâ’s corpus. Some of this evidence has been mentioned in chapter 2, but it should be further examined here due to its relevance to the present topic.

3.1. Ibn Sma and the Different Models of Planetary Motion

Ibn Sïnâ provides valuable insight in many of his works not only into his own views on celestial motion, but also into those of previous and contemporary thinkers. Whenever he addresses this topic, Ibn Sïnâ usually describes two different kinematic models. As I have analyzed these two models as well as Ibn Sïnâ’s views in depth in a recent article, I will restrict the following discussion to the key elements that are relevant to al-Fârâbï’s system.[866] The crucial passage that constitutes the starting point of the analysis appears in Metaphysics of Shifa in the context of a discussion of the number of immaterial principles under­lying celestial motion. Ibn Sïnâ writes:

If, in the case of the planetary orbs [aflak al-mutahayyirah], the principle [mabda] of the movement of the spheres [kurat] of each planet therein is a power emanating from the planets [quwwah tafldu min al-kawakib], then it would not be unlikely that the separate intellects would have the same number as the number of these planets—not the spheres—and their number would be ten, after the First. Of these, the first would be the unmoved mover that moves the sphere of the outermost body, then the one similar to it [that moves] the sphere of the fixed stars, then the one that is like it [that moves] the sphere of Saturn, and so on, terminating in the intellect that emanates on us [i.e., the Agent Intellect]. If, however, this is not the case, but each moving sphere has a rule governing its own motion and every planet, then these separate [intellects] would be of a greater number. It would follow, according to the doctrine of the First Teacher, that there would be something close to fifty and over, the last being the Agent Intellect. But you have known, from what we have said in Mathematics, what we have attained in ascertaining their number.[867]

In the ‘first kinematic model’ outlined by Ibn Sïnâ, the planets are responsible for causing the various motions of the subordinate orbs and spheres attached to them by sending motive powers that are pro­duced by the planetary souls. In this first model, only ten separate intel­lects are posited, which means that one intellect is ascribed to each one of the nine planetary groups, while the tenth intellect is the Agent Intellect governing the sublunary world. In contrast, in the ‘second kin­ematic model,’ each celestial body, including the subordinate orbs and spheres, i.e., the eccentrics and epicycles, possesses a principle respon­sible for its own autonomous motion. This model implies that each cor­poreal component is ensouled and contemplates its own, specific unmoved mover. Consequently, one must posit, like Aristotle, one sep­arate intellect per orb and per motion, with a total of fifty orbs or more.[868] These two models may be represented schematically as follows:

 

Figure 5A: Representation of the first kinematic model described in Ibn Sinas K. al-Shifa: the planetary soul moves the various physical components of its system through emanating powers (quwan)

 

Figure 5B: Representation of the second kinematic model described in Ibn Sinas K. al-Shifa: an unmoved mover is attributed to each corporeal component within a main orb

I wish to highlight a few important points with regard to this compli­cated excerpt. First, this passages occurs in an almost similar form in other works by Ibn Sïnâ, such as Mabda’ and Najah, and it also finds an echo in his K. al-sama .6 This shows that Ibn Sïnâ paid considerable attention to the problems of the number of the separate intellects and how the intellects relate to the orbs. The recurrence of this passage in his corpus also says much about the order of composition of his works and his approach to philosophical writing.[869] [870] [871] [872]

Second, and as I showed in my article on Ibn Sïnâ, the ‘first kine­matic model’ can best be described as a synthesis of Aristotelian and Ptolemaic theories. It is indebted to Aristotle in the sense that it posits separate intellects that act as unmoved movers—even though only ten such intellects are mentioned—and it is indebted to Ptolemy’s Planetary Hypotheses in its adoption of powers that emanate from the planetary souls and are responsible for moving the eccentrics and epicycles asso­ciated with the planet. In contrast, the second kinematic model is more straightforwardly Aristotelian and based on the doctrines of Book Lambda 7 and 8, even though Ibn Sïnâ introduces minor modifications in his account. In view of the importance of the ‘first kinematic model’ to properly understand al-Fârâbï’s cosmology, additional comments on its relation to Ptolemy’s astronomical theories are called for.

A comparison between Planetary Hypotheses and the works of the falasifah yields several important points. To begin with, Ptolemy rejects Aristotle’s unmoved movers as they are defined by the Arabic philo­sophical tradition. The movers (sing. muharrik) mentioned in the Arabic version of Hypotheses refer instead to the main celestial orbs of the planets and not to the immaterial principles first formulated by Aristotle in Book Lambda and endorsed later on by the falasifah .6 This represents a crucial difference between our authors. While for al-Fârâbï and Ibn Sïnâ, the movers are both the celestial souls (the proximate movers) and the immaterial intellects (the remote movers), the latter acting as final causes and objects of contemplation and desire for the celestial souls, for Ptolemy a “mover” is a main orb that carries the planet around.[873]

Moreover—and this point is of crucial importance for the upcoming discussion—Ptolemy explains the particular motions of the planets through the concept of a “vital power” or “psychological power or fac­ulty” (quwwah nafsaniyyah) inherent in the planets. Ptolemy’s theory of planetary power is exposed in Book 2 of Planetary Hypotheses, where the term quwwah appears repeatedly in his discussion.[874] Ptolemy regards the planets as ensouled beings, each operating independently from the other by virtue of its respective psychological powers. In one passage, Ptolemy compares the relation between the planetary soul and the orbs and spheres to the relation between the soul of a bird and its various bodily parts. Just as the animal soul transmits an emission (inbiath) to the various limbs and muscles that make up the body of the animal, so the soul of each planet sends emissions that move the various corporeal parts attached to this planet.[875]

While it is unclear to what extent Ptolemy wants us to construe this analogy literally, it adequately reflects his theory of celestial kine­matics, which presupposes the existence of motive powers inherent in each planet that can be distributed to the corporeal devices associated with it. As Murschel explains, “Each planet ... has the power to direct its own motions and the motions of the adjacent celestial bodies within its own system. ... The planet’s psychic faculty sends motive emissions to the epicycle, then to the deferent, then to the outermost of that plan­et’s celestial bodies, which is concentric with the earth.”[876] What this means is that the kinematic model involving ten unmoved movers described by Ibn Sïnâ, which is in essence an adaptation of the Aristotelian theory of the unmoved movers as exposed in Book Lambda 7 and 8, is combined with the Ptolemaic doctrine of the planetary pow­ers. Hence, the kinematic model described by Ibn Sïnâ is a synthesis of various theories stemming from two very different cosmological tra­ditions, the Peripatetic and the Ptolemaic.

It is noteworthy that this kinematic model is described in other clas­sical Arabic sources. Talkhts ma bada l-tabtah, a treatise which can be attributed to Ibn Rushd only hypothetically, discusses a very similar theory, which indicates that this view was known in other parts of the Islamic world, at least in those circles that cultivated the study of Greek cosmology. Ibn Rushd writes:

As to [the question of] whether it is possible to posit fewer movers than the number [which we have indicated, i.e., 47 or 55], as some of them think [i.e., some of the philosophers of the past], this is because they assign to each [main] orb only one mover which moves the planet only, from which [i.e., the planet] then emanates powers [quwan] that coordi­nate the other motions which characterize this planet and which occur due to it.[877]

And Ibn Rushd defends a more Aristotelian approach by adding: “but we have shown this to be impossible.”[878] The position criticized by Ibn Rushd shows obvious parallels with the one described by Ibn Sina in his Shifa. In both cases, the planet is made the chief of its cosmologi­cal ‘system’ and is responsible for moving the corporeal devices associ­ated with it. Powers are transmitted from the planetary soul to the spheres and orbs, in a way similar to the manner in which the animal soul moves the various limbs of the animal body.[879] Finally, the later astronomer and philosopher Nasir al-Din al-Tu si also alludes to a simi­lar kinematic model in his commentary on Ibn Sinas K. al-isharat wa-l- tanbthât.[880]

Ibn Sina, Ibn Rushd, and al-Tusi therefore describe an identical model of celestial motion, which seems to have been quite popular during the classical period. It departs from the Peripatetic one both in positing fewer unmoved movers than the number recommended by Aristotle and in combining this revised theory with the Ptolemaic con­cept of planetary powers. Here, however, we reach a set of difficult questions: which kinematic model was endorsed by al-Farabi? Does this theory of emanating planetary powers find any parallel in his works? And how are the various and at first glance eclectic theories of the separate intellects, celestial souls, and emanating powers reconciled with the planetary models he inherited from Ptolemy?

3.2. A Hypothetical Reconstruction of al-Farabi’s Kinematic Model

The question of which model al-Farabi adopted is highly significant, since it concerns the fundamental structure of his cosmology and has an impact on his theories of celestial causation and motion. I already had the opportunity of analyzing this question with respect to Ibn Sinas cosmology in my article and concluded that in spite of what is fre­quently asserted in the secondary literature, Ibn Sina upheld the sec­ond kinematic model, which assumes an identical number of unmoved movers/separate intellects and celestial bodies and motions. It thus fol­lows that Ibn Sina adhered to a revised version of Aristotle’s model, although the total number of orbs and movers in his system may be higher due to Ibn Sinas uncertainty as to whether the fixed stars are attached to one or several different orbs.[881]

What is significant for our purposes is that Ibn Sina describes these two kinematic models primarily for the sake of comprehensiveness and deliberately seeks to distance himself from the first kinematic model, which he ascribes to other Arabic thinkers. In this regard, however, neither Ibn Sina, nor Ibn Rushd, nor even al-Tû si mentions by name those thinkers who endorsed the ten-intellect model. Yet there can be little doubt that they primarily had al-Farabi’s cosmology in mind, or that they associated this model chiefly with the Farabian philosophical tradition, perhaps in the form in which it was later adapted by al-Kirmani.[882] This is because al-Farabi is the only thinker we know of in the early Arabic context who explicitly upheld the ten-intellect theory and discussed it in detail in his cosmology. Indeed, he states explicitly that there are only ten separate intellects, so that the number of sepa­rate movers cannot exceed this number.[883] More specifically, he con­nects each ‘celestial group’ or system (jumlah) with a separate intellect, establishing a parallel hierarchy of nine celestial groups and nine sepa­rate intellects, excluding the Agent Intellect. This aspect of al-Farabi’s cosmology directly influenced Ibn Sina, who reproduces this celestial structure, even though it was substantially adapted and transformed by the shaykh al-rais.

This indicates that Ibn Sina was almost certainly referring to his predecessor’s views in this passage of Shifa. Since Ibn Rushd and espe­cially al-Tûsï—whose report appears in his commentary on Isharat— studied Ibn Sinas works carefully, it is probably through a knowledge of these Avicennan works—if not by reading al-Farabi’s treatises directly—that they reproduced the same exposition of celestial kine­matics. Hence, it would appear that al-Farabi was known in the later Arabic philosophical tradition as one of the main exponents of this ten-intellect kinematic model.

But here further difficulties arise. How are we to explain the relation between the intellect and the multiple corporeal bodies and motions associated with its system? The first point concerns the ensoulment of each component in a group. Since al-Farabi endorsed the ten-intellect theory and ascribed only one separate mover to each planetary ‘sys­tem,’ it is possible by the same token that he would have posited only one soul as well per ‘system’ and considered the planet to be the only ensouled entity of its group. For as both Ibn Sina and al-Thsi explain, the exponents of this model regard each planetary group as a single entity animated by one soul, which is located in the planet. And they compare this cosmological arrangement to the sublunary animal, whose various limbs and muscles are moved by the soul located in the heart. Although al-Farabi never specifies which celestial bodies are ensouled and which are not, it is reasonable to conclude that he may very well have endorsed this view, which locates each one of the nine celestial souls in the planets and, in the case of the orb of the fixed stars and the outermost orb, which is planetless, in the orb itself.[884]

An even more delicate issue pertains to al-Farabi’s conception of the interplay between the celestial souls and the celestial bodies and how his views relate to Ptolemy’s Planetary Hypotheses. Is there any evidence in Farabi’s corpus concerning the emanating powers (quwan) described by Ibn Sina in connection with the first kinematic model of ten sepa­rate intellects? And how is the transition from contemplation to physi­cal motion explained by al-Farabi?

The first question of how the theories of planetary powers developed by Ptolemy in Planetary Hypotheses and later described by Ibn Sina in his works apply to al-Fârâbï’s cosmology is a difficult one, first because al-Fârâbï provides barely any information on this subject, and second because no thorough edition of the entire Planetary Hypotheses exists.[885] At first glance, al-Fârâbï’s position seems to allow for the possibility that these powers are transmitted mechanically from orb to orb. This could be the case with the primary universal motion, which, al-Fârâbï says, is communicated by the first outermost orb to all the other orbs, and which is presumably how Aristotle understood this process.[886] However, I have already expressed my reluctance to ascribe a mecha­nistic model of motion to al-Fârâbï, for the main reason that soul and intellect are the main principles of his cosmology and do not coexist harmoniously with a mechanistic model. Although al-Fârâbï does not explain from which source the celestial powers originate, his use of the term and concept of quwwah in connection with the particular celestial motions in Siyâsah establishes a strong link with Ptolemy’s Planetary Hypotheses. Indeed, his statement that “they [the celestial bodies] pos­sess other powers [quwan] by virtue of which ... their motions differ” seems close to the meaning conveyed in the Ptolemaic texts.[887]

But assuming for a moment that al-Fârâbï follows Ptolemy on this issue and that the planetary souls are responsible for emitting these powers, where is one to locate the soul and powers of the outermost orb and of the orb of the fixed stars, which do not contain a wandering planet? In the case of the outermost orb, this power would be emitted by a soul that inheres in the entire orb, since it is planetless, and it would then be communicated through its body to the other orbs it sur­rounds. In the case of the orb of the fixed stars, the soul would again inhere in the entire orb, since the stars are fixed on the orb and do not possess a specific motion of their own. Hence, the power emitted by this soul would be responsible solely for the precessional movement of this orb. Finally, in the case of the planetary orbs, the soul would be located in the planet specifically, from which powers (quwan) would be transmitted to the various corporeal devices or components associated with this planet and responsible for its particular motions.

This model, including the idiosyncratic distribution of the celestial souls and their powers, is described in detail by Ibn Sïnâ and al-Tûsï in their works.[888] As Ibn Sïnâ writes in Mabda,

a group among the learned [qawman min al-afadil] consider the planet [kawkab] in its main orb [ft kuratiht kulliyyah] to be like the heart [in the animal]. They make the [power of the] soul emanate from it [taftdu minhu] [i.e., the planet] onto the particular [or minor] orbs [al-kurat al-juziyyah] and cause the various motions by analogy with the motions of an animal, except for the orb of the fixed stars [falak al-thawabit], for indeed they claim that its motive power [al-quwwah al-muharrikah] is emitted to the stars [kawakib] from their orbs [kuratiha].[889] And [in this case] the orb [kurah] will be the heart and the stars in them will be like the limbs [of the animal].

And Ibn Sïnâ continues:

So according to them, each main orb has only one soul, which has a loca­tion [i.e., in the planet], and this approach also necessitates that the desired principles [i.e., the separate intellects] correspond not to the number of the minor [or subordinate orbs] [al-kurat al-juz’iyyah], but rather to that of the main orbs [al-kurat al-kulliyyah].[890] [891]

This description evokes the model outlined in Ptolemy’s Planetary Hypotheses and is a more complete account of the ‘first kine­matic model’ than the one found in Metaphysics of Shifa. Ibn Sïnâ ascribes this more elaborate position to “a group among the learned,” and in another passage of the same work, to “the moderns” (al-muta’akhkhirüri)8 These attributions suggest that Arabic thinkers either shortly before or during Ibn Sïnâ’s own time had endorsed this model, and they could very well refer implicitly to al-Fârâbï. When one realizes that al-Fârâbï’s cosmology includes a) the theory of the ten separate intellects, b) possibly an equal number of celestial souls, and c) celestial powers (quwan), which are explicitly connected with the par­ticular celestial motions (if not with the planets specifically), then it becomes not only possible, but highly probable that al-Fârâbï was one of the main exponents of this cosmological model.[892] Although it is unclear whether al-Fârâbï located the celestial souls specifically in the planets, the existing evidence nevertheless seems to support his endorsement of this model.[893]

Finally, a last point has to be addressed. It pertains to the question of how the planetary powers are transmitted from the planetary souls to the various corporeal components of its group and actualize the plan­etary motions. In other words, how is the planetary souls’ intellectual contemplation of the separate intellects transformed into motion in a physical body? In the kinematic picture described above, this point remains ambiguous, and al-Fârâbï fails to explain it adequately. This is all the more problematic, since he defines the celestial souls as being devoid of the inner senses of imagination (takhayyul) and estimation (wahm) and as possessing only rational thought. In spite of this, and in light of the testimony adduced by Ibn Sïnâ and al-Tûsï, it is reasonable to think that al-Fârâbï would have modelled his account of how motion is produced in the celestial body on his theory of animal motion. Al-Tûsï and Ibn Sïnâ both intimate in their report that the ten-intellect kinematic model rests on a close analogy with animal motion. For on their account, the thinkers who upheld this model compared the plan­etary soul to the animal soul located in the heart, and they compared the other corporeal devices attached to the planet—i.e., the eccentric orbs and epicycle spheres—to the various limbs of the animal.

Now, we know that al-Fârâbï located the animal soul chiefly in the heart, as Aristotle had—as opposed to Ibn Sïnâ, who located it chiefly in the brain and whose view was thus indebted to the Galenic tradition. The few remarks al-Fârâbï makes concerning animal motion in his works are easily compatible with this kinematic model and with the theory of emanating powers. He describes the presence of powers (quwan) that are diffused throughout the limbs and muscles of the animal body and that are connected to the central seat of the soul in the heart.[894] The animal heart also diffuses innate heat (al-hararah al-gharlzah) throughout the body. It is the ruling organ (al- ’udw al-ra’ts) to which the other organs and the bodily parts are subordinated.[895]

These key physiological points go hand in hand with the other ele­ments mentioned above and strongly support the hypothesis of al-Fârâbï’s adherence to the ten-intellect kinematic model. According to this view, al-Fârâbï would have applied a similar explanatory frame­work to sublunary and superlunary motion, which relies on the anal­ogy of the heart in the animal body and its role as ruling organ. The heart as seat of the animal soul corresponds to the planetary soul, while the organs and limbs correspond to the orbs and spheres. Powers are transmitted from the heart/planetary soul to the bodily parts, which enable motion to take place. In the case of the planetary souls, these powers are generated as a result of their ongoing attempt to imitate the perfection of the immaterial principles. The planetary souls strive to acquire these perfections, but due to their corporeal nature and their close association with the celestial body, they can only perform con­stantly renewed acts of will and desire that translate into particular and renewed powers and motions.

In spite of this, al-Fârâbï does not provide a detailed explanation of the issue of how motion is actualized in the celestial body. It is probably this shortcoming in al-Fârâbï’s cosmological accounts that can explain why Ibn Sïnâ addresses this difficult issue in depth in Mabda, in Metaphysics of Shifa, and in other works, and why he endows the celes­tial souls with the faculties of imagination and estimation. According to Ibn Sïnâ, the celestial soul is primarily engaged in the conceptualiza­tion of particulars and changing things. It is corporeal and inextricably linked to the celestial body whose form it constitutes.[896] Ibn Sïnâ’s artic­ulation of the theory of the inner senses (hawass batinah) had a direct impact on his celestial kinematics, for it helped him to bridge the gap between the immaterial and material principles involved in causing motion, even though his account is not without its own limitations.[897] Ibn Sïnâ compares the activity of the celestial soul and its relation to the celestial body to the human soul and body and adopts a similar frame­work for explaining motion in both cases, which relies on these psy­chological elaborations.

I will conclude by saying that al-Fârâbï most likely adhered to the ‘first kinematic model’ described by Ibn Sïnâ. His theory of the particu­lar motions of the planets probably included powers emanating from the planetary souls, even though it is grounded primarily in the con­cepts of intellection and final causality. Only limited insight can be given as to how exactly this theory worked in its details, but in what precedes I provided a hypothetical reconstruction of al-Fârâbï’s views that has the merit of incorporating all the hints that can be gleaned from his corpus as well as the evidence that can be drawn from later reports. The foregoing analysis enables us to conclude that al-Fârâbï’s account of celestial kinematics appears as an original and idiosyn­cratic adaptation of Book Lambda, which adapts the Aristotelian the­ory of the unmoved movers and combines it with Neoplatonic noetical theories and Ptolemaic kinematic material drawn from Planetary Hypotheses. Although al-Fârâbï’s method of synthesizing these philo­sophical and astronomical theories is inscribed in the late antique philosophical tradition, the kinematic model that resulted from it was innovative and does not have a clear precedent in the Greek and early Arabic contexts.

3.3. Celestial Kinematics and the Classification of the Sciences in falsafah

The study has shown on the one hand that al-Fârâbï adopts the Ptolemaic theories of eccentrics and epicycles, which he views as sub­ordinate corporeal components encompassed by a main orb and belonging to a celestial ‘group’ or ‘system,’ and on the other hand that he develops a theory of motion that synthesizes information from the Arabic versions of Book Lambda and from Ptolemaic and Neoplatonic sources. The fundamental idea that emerges from al-Fârâbï’s model is that soul, and more precisely, the intellectual activity of the celestial souls, is the primary principle underlying celestial motion.

The juxtaposition of these various features and theories in al-Fârâbï’s cosmology raises the question of their compatibility. What is the explanatory function of the eccentrics and epicycles, which according to al-Fârâbï have a corporeal existence, if motion is ultimately caused by the heavenly souls? In other words, to what extent can these eccen­trics and epicycles also be called causes of motion? This issue is par­ticularly relevant when it comes to the systems of medieval philosophers, many of whom practiced physics, metaphysics, and astronomy at the same time. With regard to the Second Teacher, this problem is encap­sulated in a passage of Müstqâ, where, following a Greek custom, he defines the eccentrics and epicycles as “causes” (asbab) of motion.[898] Al-Fârâbï does not provide any clue as to how one should understand this statement and construe the juxtaposition of the astronomical and (meta-)physical principles in his account. The answer sketched below is an attempt to make sense of this difficult issue and may be fruitfully applied to other thinkers, such as Ibn Sïnâ, who also combine a psycho­logical theory of motion with an eccentric-epicyclic model derived from the Ptolemaic tradition.

Whether the term sabab is translated as “explanation” or “cause,” calling eccentrics and epicycles asbab clearly betrays on the part of a medieval thinker like al-Fârâbï a concern for the fundamental principles that underlie celestial motion, and more specifically, the par­ticular motions of the planets. From the viewpoint of a human observer, these planetary motions seem to diverge from the universal westward motion of the heavens, a fact which had to be accounted for. One notices in this respect that this concern is inscribed within, and pre­supposes, a more general theory of kinematics, since the eccentrics and epicycles were devices used to explain the specific planetary motions and therefore the more subtle and difficult observations of the celestial phenomena. But of greater priority or importance was the need to explain, first, the causes of celestial motion in general, and second, the universal westward motion, which is common to all the orbs. In other words, the theories of the eccentrics and epicycles do not and cannot address the fundamental questions: Why do the celestial orbs move? And why is the heavenly motion circular?

To these questions, as we have seen, Arabic thinkers answered by postulating physical and metaphysical principles such as aether, soul, and intellect, which were at once philosophically more basic and endowed with a greater interpretive potential than the mere devices of epicycles and eccentrics. These principles were intended to explain not only the regularity and perpetuity of the heavenly motion, but also its circularity. For example, the physical proposition of aether implied an inherent inclination for circular motion within the celestial body, whereas the mathematical-metaphysical interpretation of the circle qua most perfect shape made it the formal equivalent of the eternal intellection and self-reflexivity of the orbs.

And indeed, it is precisely to this type of physical argumentation that al-Fârâbï alludes in Müstqâ, where he explains that the astronomer must rely on principles derived from natural philosophy in order to account for the basic motion of the orbs. While physics and the aether theory in particular proved helpful in this respect, the most fundamen­tal explanation of celestial motion provided by the falasifah rested on metaphysics and more specifically on the concepts of soul and intel­lect. Hence, to the basic question: Why do the celestial bodies move? The philosopher could answer by arguing that they are animated, rational beings that move by choice (ikhtiyar), will (iradah), and intel­lectual desire (shawq), as well as by virtue of their contemplation (ta'aqqul). Ultimately, it is their contemplation of, and desire for, the separate movers and their act of reversion toward these principles that induces their heavenly revolutions. It is to this type of meta­physical model that al-Fârâbï alludes fleetingly in Siyasah, when he

states that “they [the celestial bodies] move in circular fashion by virtue of them [i.e., their souls].”[899]

But there is no obvious reason why the physical and metaphysical explanations of celestial motion should be in any way incompatible with the subordinate and more specifically astronomical question of why the planets possess particular motions. To perceive an incompati­bility between these questions and the solutions proposed by the Arabic philosophers is, I think, to misconstrue modes of argumentation that were seen as complementary. Thus, when al-Fârâbï presents intellec­tion, and Ibn Sïnâ intellection and imagination, as the main principles underlying celestial motion in their philosophical treatises, they are approaching the question of celestial kinematics from a physical and metaphysical perspective, i.e., with the intention of clarifying the fun­damental causes of celestial motion per se, a question whose answer requires investigation into the essence of the celestial bodies and the immaterial causes that govern them.

And indeed, it is no coincidence that such an analysis appears in the metaphysical sections of their works, as is attested, for instance, by Ára, Siyasah, and Fll-aqlin the case of al-Fârâbï, and by the Metaphysics of Shifa in the case of Ibn Sïnâ. If then asked why the planets each possess trajectories that are proper to them, they could give a metaphysical explanation for this phenomenon, namely, by resorting to the kind of intellection proper to each celestial soul and to the existence of a specific immaterial mover corresponding to it.[900] In addition, they could refer the inquirer to their astronomical writings, which provided an astronomical-physical explanation based on the devices of the eccen­trics and epicycles. Moreover, they could have argued that the ques­tion of the particular planetary motions falls primarily within the purview of the astronomical discipline and that it is the skopós of astronomy, rather than metaphysics or natural philosophy, to address it. Indeed, according to their classification of the sciences, astronomy is the discipline that studies the various celestial movements.[901] Yet the fact remains that both metaphysics and astronomy—here construed as a combination of mathematical astronomy and celestial physics—could contribute to solving this problem. The issue of the planetary motions is therefore a perfect illustration of the kind of philosophical problem which overlapped various disciplines, which could be interpreted from different angles, and for which different causes or explanations could be mustered.

This general assumption concerning the compatibility of astronomy and the other sciences such as physics and the reliance of the former on the latter was already upheld in antiquity, Geminus being a notable example. We saw that the Arabic falasifah adopted a similar approach and that many hints in their works indicate that they aimed to achieve some kind of reconciliation between the physical and astronomical disciplines. In that sense, they were continuing a trend that had its roots in antiquity. But what is remarkable in the works of the falasifah is the willingness to extend this approach to the subject of celestial motion in particular, whose difficulty they, especially Ibn Sïnâ, were highly aware of.

In spite of this, al-Fârâbï and Ibn Sïnâ, and the other falasifah for that matter, do not provide a unified and integrated account of the astro­nomical, physical, and metaphysical causes of celestial motion within the same work, except somewhat briefly (as the passage of Metaphysics of Shifa discussed in the previous section shows). One may surmise that their adherence to Aristotle’s Posterior Analytics and to the hierar­chy of proofs and compartmentalization of the philosophical disci­plines it advocates was too strong for an independent literary genre combining these various approaches to be fully realized within falsa- fah. While providing a basic framework for their philosophy as a whole, the authority in which the Arabic philosophers held this work might have simultaneously impeded a real breakthrough with regard to their theorization of certain issues, such as celestial motion.

Moreover, al-Fârâbï and Ibn Sïnâ might also have been influenced to some extent by Ptolemy’s perception of the sciences. Ptolemy not only criticized the cosmological value of physics and metaphysics in Almagest, but also provided in this same work an account of planetary motion that relies lightly on physical considerations and that is virtu­ally free of any metaphysical assumptions. Although Ptolemy’s ideas at first glance fitted awkwardly with the falâsifah’s more inclusive approach and their belief in the interrelatedness of the sciences, they might none­theless have had an impact on the Arabic thinkers. Even al-Tusï’s Tadhkirah, which is closer to this ideal philosophical synthesis, men­tions some key physical concepts, but says virtually nothing about the role of the metaphysical principles of soul and intellect in connection with motion—a topic which is however discussed at length in some of al-Tu si’s other works, such as his commentary on Ibn Sinas Ishârât.[902] This indicates that al-Tusi and some of the hayah authors, though in some ways more successful in their synthetic approach than the earlier falasifah, also experienced difficulty accommodating the different dis­ciplinary accounts on celestial motion in a single work.[903]

Another potential impediment may have been the distinct textual traditions from which these theories were derived. Even though they are to some extent combined in the works of the Arabic falasifah, and even though some of the late antique commentaries had anticipated the Arabic works in integrating astronomical and more specifically Ptolemaic theories into the mainstream philosophical discourse—a prime example is Simplicius’ commentary on On the Heavens—it should be stressed that the falasifah would have had to engage with what was virtually two distinct intellectual traditions: the astronomical one and the philosophical one. This holds both with regard to the early Islamic social and cultural context, where thinkers could practice both astronomy and philosophy, but where the majority were either known as astronomers or philosophers, and with regard to the Greek to Arabic translation movement, whose output may be partially, albeit clearly, divided into a philosophical part and an astronomical part. Indeed, the translators who specialized in astronomy were not necessarily well versed in philosophical matters and vice versa.

Consequently, it is surely not because the falasifah considered the various principles underlying celestial motion and their interpretation as paradoxical or irreconcilable, but rather because they regarded them as belonging to different disciplines and as requiring a different kind of analytical treatment, that these were addressed in different works. The problem pertains more to issues of method, philosophical skopós, and to these thinkers’ classification of the sciences than to any inherent incompatibility between the various scientific disciplines. These com­ments give us a measure of the originality, difficulty, and scope of the falâsifah’s project to combine astronomy, physics, and metaphysics in a more or less systematic way, even if their endeavour was not fully successful or appears incomplete from the viewpoint of a modern scholar.

There remains the thorny question of what type of proofs the various sciences provide with respect to celestial kinematics. Here we are in murkier waters. I already tried to address this question in chapter 1 with respect to al-Fârâbï’s method of astronomy and can only add a few remarks here. Al-Fârâbï makes it clear in Burhan that the various sciences—and he mentions physics and astronomy explicitly—can identify different causes to explain the same thing.[904] In the context of astronomy, he even gives the sphericity of the world and the planets as an example. This question can be treated by astronomy and physics, which both use a different method and examine different causes: the formal cause in the case of the mathematical disciplines, the four causes in the case of physics.[905]

In the case of celestial motion, al-Fârâbï does not provide any hints as to whether the same interdisciplinary approach applies, and how it applies, although one may surmise that it does. Physics, by examining the celestial substance, can yield knowledge of the material cause of celestial motion; aether is after all regarded as an element or body pos­sessing its own qualities in the Peripatetic tradition. Building on the insights of physics and relying on observations, astronomy then posits geometric devices (epicycles and eccentrics) to explain the particular motions of the planets. These devices, it should be stressed, are also conceived of as bodies (ajsam) and are meant to correspond to physical reality, that is to say, to the way that the heavens are actually struc- tured.[906] Consequently, the eccentrics and epicycles, as well as the main orbs, may be regarded as possessing a causal or at least an instrumen­tal function in the process of heavenly motion, in the sense that they literally carry the planets around, in the same way that the hand carries an object.

At another level removed from the corporeality of the celestial orbs and spheres, metaphysics posits soul and especially intellect as another set of causes, this time of a final kind. The planetary soul is a proximate cause of motion, and indeed Ibn Sïnâ defines it as the “proximate mover” (muharrik qartb) of the planets and orbs.[907] The celestial souls contemplate the separate intellects and the First, and it is this contem­plation which in turn produces celestial motion in the celestial bodies. In addition to the celestial souls, the separate intellects themselves, as well as the First, are final causes that act upon the souls as objects of desire. These various, separate intellects are remote causes of motion, since they are not attached to matter or connected with the celestial bodies in any way, but they entice the celestial bodies to move through the perfection of their existence. They are, like the First, final causes, since they represent the telos which the celestial souls strive to reach.

If this interpretation is correct, then al-Fârâbï, and later Ibn Sïnâ, posited a whole array of kinematic causes superimposed on one another. These causes are at once distinct and intricately connected. They are organized in a hierarchical fashion, in that some are more fundamental than others. This hierarchical explanatory scheme clearly relies on these philosophers’ conception of the interrelatedness and cooperation of the sciences, as well as on the concept of final causality they inherited from Aristotle. But it also has important ramifications insofar as the various types of proofs are concerned. For it shows that the falasifah recognized various orders of causality and accepted vari­ous levels of explanation and perhaps demonstration with regard to celestial motion.[908]

Given the foregoing, al-Fârâbï’s works represent an important link in the scholarly effort to reconstruct a history of Arabic celestial kinemat­ics, and this even though he did not articulate an explicit and detailed theory of celestial motion. Be it only for the conceptual questions that his works raise and for the fascinating yet tantalizing hints he provides, the Second Teacher’s views on the topic deserved an extensive treat­ment. The fact that al-Fârâbï juxtaposes physical orbs and spheres, celestial souls, and intellects, generates a number of problems, a central one being the causality of celestial motion and the way in which it may be studied from an epistemological perspective. While al-Fârâbï may not have been aware of all the various issues and tensions underlying his cosmological account and discussed in the previous analysis, it had the merit of stimulating Ibn Sïnâ to further reflect on them and find more sophisticated and convincing solutions. Retrospectively, one may say that the falasifah played an important role in the history of medie­val cosmology in general and of Arabic cosmology in particular, for they developed their own approach to defining the relation between astronomy and the other philosophical disciplines. In that sense, they stand at a crucial stage between the cosmological developments of late antiquity and the golden age of the post-classical hay’ah tradition.

4. Conclusion

This chapter provided a hypothetical reconstruction of al-Fârâbï’s views on celestial kinematics by relying on the sparse evidence in the Second Teacher’s corpus as well as on the reports of later thinkers. Certain key issues, such as the causes underlying celestial motion, the relation between the separate intellects, the celestial soul, and the celestial body, and how the transition from abstract contemplation to corporeal motion is achieved, were examined in light of the Greek and Arabic sources. It emerged from the analysis that al-Fârâbï’s celestial kinemat­ics, like the other fundamental doctrines of his cosmology, are charac­terized by a complex and subtle synthesis of various intellectual traditions. In comparison to al-Kindi, who did not provide any com­pelling explanation of heavenly motion, and who regarded it merely as a sign of the heavens’ obedience to God,[909] al-Farabi is the first thinker to introduce some of the key kinematic concepts that were later elabo­rated by Ibn Sina, al-Tusi, and others. Perhaps the most noteworthy feature of his works in this respect is their attempt to harmoniously integrate astronomical material within a physical and metaphysical framework, an endeavour which not only perpetuated a well-defined late antique trend in the Islamic context, but in addition influenced generations of subsequent Arabic thinkers who flourished after al-Farabi.


The aim of this study was to analyze some of the key concepts of al-Fârâbï’s cosmology and to reconstruct the various stages of his phil­osophical development in light of the Greek and Arabic sources and the early Islamic intellectual milieu in which he flourished. Al-Fârâbï’s approach to cosmology can be defined chiefly in terms of the complex exegetical method he elaborated and his creative use of the late antique Greek and early Arabic sources. This approach, however, underwent various stages, which the study endeavoured to reconstruct, and which can be broadly divided into two periods: an ‘early Baghdad phase,’ characterized chiefly by al-Fârâbï’s endorsement of a creationist para­digm, and a ‘late Baghdad and wandering phase,’ which corresponds chronologically to the last ten years or so of his life, and which wit­nessed the development of al-Fârâbï’s mature cosmological theories. Both phases were marked by an interpretation of Aristotelian cosmol­ogy in light of late antique philosophical material and the Neoplatonica arabica, whose contents were nevertheless construed in a different way. This developmentalist hypothesis relies on substantial doctrinal evi­dence, and it also has the merit of including the few certain biographi­cal facts in our possession. It enables a new organization of part of the Fârâbïan corpus and a reassessment of many works of uncertain authenticity.

The study emphasized the crucial role that late antique Greek com­mentaries played in shaping al-Fârâbï’s cosmological project, which in many ways can be regarded as a continuation of this intellectual tradi­tion. Through extensive terminological and doctrinal analysis, the study confirmed the importance of several works already identified by previous scholars and discussed other philosophical and astronomical sources liable to have influenced al-Fârâbï’s cosmological outlook, notably by Alexander, Simplicius, Geminus, Themistius, Proclus, and Syrianus. In addition, the analysis provided several case studies of how al-Fârâbï’s theories relate to those of Proclus and the Proclus arabus, and it showed that his particular interpretation of these sources should be regarded as a crucial factor underlying the development of his cos­mology. The Proclean legacy in particular provided al-Fârâbï with the conceptual means to elaborate a new cosmological paradigm grounded


in the concepts of eternal causation and intellection. In the process, the concepts of emanationism and divine creationism were re-examined in light of al-Fârâbï’s theories of eternal causality. Finally, in trying to pro­vide a seamless cosmological model that integrates Aristotelian and Neoplatonic physics and metaphysics and Ptolemaic astronomy, it appears that al-Fârâbï was continuing a practice already discernible in the works of Ammonius, Simplicius, and other Neoplatonists. In so doing, he was also elaborating a clear and systematic synthesis of the philosophical knowledge available in his time, which was used as a model by later Arabic thinkers.

With regard to certain specific cosmological doctrines, al-Fârâbï must be credited with remarkable exegetical resourcefulness and crea­tivity and for developing interpretations of ancient cosmological prob­lems which, while they clearly draw on late antique sources, appear innovative in the early Islamic context. This is the case notably with his theories of the causation of the separate intellects and its relation to celestial intellection, the concept of celestial substance, and to a lesser extent his views on celestial motion—which require a greater degree of hypothesizing. Al-Fârâbï’s theory of the separate intellects marks an important shift in early Arabic thought, both because it introduces explicitly for the first time an entire hierarchy of intellectual beings between God and the corporeal world, and second, because the corol­lary theories of the causative powers of these intellects and their auton­omy as demiurges constitute a new metaphysical paradigm, which departs clearly from the prevalent Islamic views on creation. This met­aphysical elaboration significantly complexifies al-Fârâbï’s position vis- à-vis the mainstream Islamic beliefs of his time and defines him in many ways as a continuator of late antique pagan metaphysics.

Finally, al-Fârâbï’s eagerness to adapt his philosophical outlook to incoming influences and ideas is visible also with regard to his method, which reflects a special awareness of the scientific developments that took place in early Islamic society and that set new epistemological standards for subsequent Arabic thinkers. He is one of the firstfalasifah, together with al-Kindï, to develop a genuine interest in the method of the particular sciences, such as mathematical astronomy and music, but in addition he develops a complex epistemic scheme grounded in the notions of the cooperation and subordination of the sciences, which also makes ample use of a range of philosophical techniques, such as experience, observation, and analogy.

The result of this study should lead to a partial reassessment of al-Fârâbï’s intellectual legacy in Islam. On the one hand, al-Fârâbï’s introduction of a level of intellectual beings between God and the cor­poreal world and his multi-layered theory of eternal causation, as well as his attempt at harmonizing physics, metaphysics, and astronomy both in terms of methodology and doctrine, had a profound impact on subsequent Arabic thought. This can be seen by comparing his cosmol­ogy to that of al-Kirmânï, Ibn Sïnâ, and others. But on the other hand, this model, and especially al-Fârâbï’s idiosyncratic theory of the thawânt and their causative powers, was never wholly embraced by subsequent thinkers. One may say that, like a musical pattern, it served as a model for future variations on the same theme, but it was to my knowledge never reproduced in its details.[CMX]

This fact can be partly explained by al-Fârâbï’s highly particular interpretation of the separate intellects and their causal role, which would have seemed philosophically unacceptable or religiously pro­vocative to later thinkers, including Ibn Sïnâ, whose own doctrine of secondary causation differs considerably from that of his predecessor. This might also explain to some extent why al-Fârâbï’s mature meta­physics and cosmology do not seem to have had a strong impact on his immediate followers. In that sense, while solidly grounded in late antique sources, his cosmology and metaphysics are essentially unique and should be regarded as the product of a particular time and philo­sophical culture, a view emphasized by the historical perspective advocated in this book.


APPENDIX ONE

COSMOLOGY AND THE AUTHORSHIP
OF TA'LlQÀT, 'UYÜN, AND DAÂWÀ

Introduction

Taltqat, 'Uyün, and Da awa are treatises ascribed to al-Fârâbi in the Arabic tradition, but to this day these attributions remain uncertain. One reason to study these texts is that they contain interesting and sometimes original cos­mological theories, which are in many ways akin to those of al-Fârâbi and Ibn Sinâ, but which have not been examined critically before. Only a detailed examination of the contents of these works will enable the question of their authorship to be definitively settled. In what follows, I offer a comparative analysis of certain key cosmological themes with the hope that it will shed some light on this issue and contribute to future research on these works.[911]

1.   The Nature and Causation of the Celestial Substance

Taltqat

As its name indicates, this is a somewhat random collection of notes on vari­ous philosophical issues, although it displays a clear interest in cosmology and in the motion and contemplation of the celestial bodies in particular. With regard to the subject of celestial substance, however, the author says rela­tively little. He explains that the orbs and planets are composite and possess a hylomorphic constitution: ftha tarktb min maddah wa-sürah.[912] [913] In spite of this, the celestial bodies are the noblest of “material things” (al-maddiyyat):' In addition, he says that the forms of the celestial bodies are “fixed in their matters” (mawqüfah 'ala mawâddihâ).[914] On the other hand, the author says nothing about the causation of the celestial bodies. These brief remarks suffice to show the gap between this work and al-Fârâbi’s emanationist treatises, since the latter do not describe the celestial bodies as hylomorphic beings and omit the term maddah.

Daawa

In Da awa, one finds a wealth of comments on the celestial bodies, a fact which testifies to the author’s interest in cosmology.[915] Da'awa puts forth a cosmologi­cal model based on the concept of emanation that closely resembles both al-Fârâbi’s and Ibn Sina’s emanationist schemes. More specifically, the process through which the heavenly bodies are produced is reminiscent of their meta­physics: it is the separate intellects, which, by contemplating their essence and God, cause a lower separate intellect and a heavenly body to exist. The author writes:

and it [i.e., the first separate intellect caused by God] is also one and free of mul­tiplicity, except in the sense [previously] mentioned. From it is produced the highest heaven [i.e., the outermost orb] and its matter and form, which is its soul, insofar as it [the intellect] is possible of existence and contemplating its own essence. And from this second [i.e., the first separate intellect after God] is pro­duced another intellect.[916]

What is immediately noticeable in this passage is the technical vocabulary used to describe the separate intellects, a vocabulary which is found through­out the treatise and which is usually associated with Ibn Sina and his circle. This is obvious, for instance, from the author’s extensive use of such terms as “necessary of existence” (wajib al-wujüd) and “possible of existence” (mumkin al-wujüd).[917] For our purpose, however, the most important feature of this excerpt consists in the reference to the composition of the celestial orb. The outermost orb, which is produced by the intellection of the first emanated being, is composed of form (surah) and matter (maddah). The reference to heavenly matter reappears in another passage, where the author explains that the heavenly bodies cannot have the same matter as sublunary elements, nor can they have the same form, or else they would be perishable. Hence, they possess an essentially different kind of matter, which represents a “fifth nature” (tabiah khamisah),s a formula which relies on Aristotle’s theory of aether as expounded in On the Heavens. Hence, Daawa ascribes a hylomorphic consti­tution to the heavens and refers explicitly to its matter (maddah) in a manner congruent with Taliqat.

‘Uyün

This treatise shares Tallqats and Daawa’s views on celestial substance. The celestial bodies are described as hylomorphic beings that consist of form and matter, the former principle being equated with soul. In addition, and as in Da awa, the author of ‘Uyün explains that both the celestial form and matter are different from their sublunary counterpart and represent a “fifth nature” (tab‘ khamis).[918] [919] The cause responsible for this form and matter is a separate intellect. It is noteworthy that the intellects produce both the form and matter of the orbs by intellecting their own essence. Thus, one cause is given to account for the dual principles of form and matter, a view also found in al-Fârâbi’s cosmological treatises.

This brief overview shows that Taliqat, Da awa, and 'Uyün present an over­lapping theory of celestial substance. These three works stress the hylomor- phic composition of the celestial bodies and repeatedly refer to the celestial matter (maddah), which they explicitly define as a ‘fifth nature,’ while none of them mentions the concept of celestial substrate (mawdü). These views show a marked similarity to Ibn Sinâ’s doctrine of celestial substance, but they are on the other hand irreconcilable with al-Fârâbi’s emanationist treatises.

2.    Intellection and Imagination

Taliqat

The following paragraphs provide an overview of several topics, especially celestial intellection and imagination, the relation between human and celes­tial imagination, and the impact of the latter on the sublunary world. Like Àra and Siyasah, Taliqat describes the heavenly bodies as ensouled beings that possess rational thought. The celestial bodies are composed of form and matter, the former principle being identified with their soul (nafs) or intellect ('aql), while the latter principle introduces an element of multiplicity that makes the heavenly souls deficient and imperfect compared to the separate intellects and the First.[920] These souls, and the heavens as a whole, strive to attain their highest perfection by contemplating God, the noblest object of thought.[921] The circular motion of the heavens results from this intellection and from the orbs’ desire to imitate the higher principles. Apart from the celestial souls, there are also “efficient intellects” (al-‘uqül al-fa‘alah), which differ from the heavenly souls by having simple and completely immaterial essences.[922]

Up to now, the cosmological picture that emerges from Talïqât contains a First Cause, separate intellects, and heavenly souls, and it thus bears a marked resemblance to al-Fârâbi’s works. However, the author of Talïqât seems to have been preoccupied by issues that did not interest al-Fârâbi much. It was noted before that al-Fârâbi provides little information about the nature of the intellection of the celestial souls, for example, whether their intellection is dis­cursive or non-discursive, how it differs from the intellection of the separate intellects, and whether it is potential or actual. Talïqât, on the other hand, provides more insight into these noetical issues. One reads that the “intellects of the planets are in potency, not in actuality, and contemplate [things] not all at once, but rather one thing after another.”[923] According to the author, then, the thought of the celestial bodies is discursive, which means that it moves from one object of thought to another, because it cannot encompass all the intelligibles at once. This creates a notion of multiplicity that makes the heav­enly souls deficient, for as the author writes, “wherever there is plurality, there is deficiency.”[924] Moreover, the celestial souls are potential. Whether this potency is due to the discursive nature of the celestial souls’ thought or to their composite hylomorphic nature is not specified. In any case, this view goes against the more common Aristotelian idea that everything above the orb of the moon is in a perpetual state of actuality.

It is notable that the themes discussed in Talïqât, such as the notions of discursive thought vs. non-discursive thought and potency vs. actuality, also figure prominently in the Neoplatonica arabica. But these works provide dif­ferent answers to these problems. In Theology of Aristotle, for example, discur­sive thought is associated with actuality, and non-discursive thought (a higher intellective mode) with potency. Hence, potency is considered to be more per­fect than actuality. As the Adaptor writes, potency “manifests and perfects activity.”[925] In contrast, Talïqât associates discursive thought with potency, not actuality. This potency is described as a source of imperfection and deficiency in the heavenly bodies. The two works therefore adopt a different view on the potency-actuality question. Whereas potency corresponds to a higher form of (non-discursive) intellection for the Adaptor, it entails discursiveness, plural­ity, and deficiency for the author of Talïqât.[926]

Al-Fârâbi would have disagreed with many of the ideas developed in Taltqat. As we have seen, he considers that the heavenly souls have non- discursive thought, since their intellection occurs “all at once” (dafatan). Al-Fârâbi would also have rejected the notion that they are affected by potency; according to him, they are eternally in actuality, and actuality is a higher prin­ciple than potency. Their only deficiency derives from the plurality of their intellection, which introduces complexity in their essence and sets them apart from the First (who is absolutely simple) and the intellects (which have a lesser degree of complexity). Unlike the author of Taltqat, then, al-Fârâbi combines non-discursive thought with actuality in his theory of celestial intellection. Another significant difference between Taltqat and al-Fârâbi’s emanationist works concerns the number of the contemplated objects. Whereas the heav­enly souls in Àra and Siyasah are said to have three objects of thought (God, the separate intellects, and their own essence), those of Taltqat seem to limit their contemplation solely to the First. This appears clearly in section 56, which states that the “heavens and stars contemplate the First,” and in section 58, when the author notes that it is sufficient to posit a single mover to explain the various heavenly motions.[927]

One of the fundamental cosmological doctrines of Taltqat is the ascription of imagination to the celestial bodies. Whereas al-Fârâbi explicitly asserts in his emanationist works that the souls are devoid of the faculty of imagination, Taltqat devotes several paragraphs to this topic and its implications for the celestial and sublunary realms.[928] It defines imagination as an essential aspect of the activity and knowledge of the heavenly souls. According to the author, the souls “first intellect things and then imagine them.”[929] In humans, this pat­tern is inverted and intellection is said to follow imagination. The dual nature of celestial thought (intellection and imagination), and especially the fact that imagination is said to follow intellection, are intriguing ideas, which may have their origin in some passages of the Neoplatonica arabica, but which I was not able to identify with any precision.

But what is the benefit of having celestial souls that possess imagination in addition to intellection? The answer to this question lies in the special powers conferred to the heavenly bodies as a result of their imagination. The peculiar­ity of Taltqat in this respect is that heavenly imagination acquires a demiurgic quality that intellection alone does not have. Thanks to their imagination, the heavenly bodies become key agents and causes in the generation of beings in the sublunary world. The author writes: “the planets imagine things, and their imagination becomes a cause for the creation of things.” For example, when the heavenly bodies imagine heat in the air, then heat is produced in the air.[930]

Furthermore, the author explains that the creation that occurs through the celestial bodies’ imagination is different from the one that results from their motion: “their imagination can become a cause for the production of things, just as their motions are a cause for the production of other things.” And shortly after, he adds that “they [the celestial bodies] can imagine [something] and create this thing either without the mediation of motion or with the medi­ation of motion.”[931] The celestial bodies have, therefore, a dual demiurgic power that can be expressed either through motion or through imagination. The idea that the movements of the heavenly bodies have a direct influence on sublu­nary beings harkens back to Aristotle, according to whom the sun is an effi­cient cause that plays a crucial role in sublunary generation and corruption.[932] Many subsequent thinkers, including al-Kindi and al-Fârâbi, generalized this principle and made all the celestial bodies causes of change in the sublunary world. But the claim that celestial imagination itself is endowed with a causal efficacy that operates in isolation from heavenly motion appears unprece­dented and testifies to the original reworking of cosmological ideas achieved by the author of Ta liqat.

Even more striking is the author’s assertion that the imagination of the heavenly bodies is a cause for the generation of “imaginables” (takhayyulat) in the human soul.[933] This means that the heavenly bodies’ imagination can act on human reflection in addition to natural phenomena. This theory establishes a direct epistemological link between the human and heavenly souls, a role which is traditionally reserved in Arabic philosophy for the Agent Intellect. Here it appears that the heavenly souls have partially appropriated the role played by the Agent Intellect as an agent of human thought, although they presumably act primarily on the human imaginative faculty, whereas the Agent Intellect is responsible for actualizing the intelligibles in the human mind.[934] This significant development suggests that the psychology and episte­mology elaborated by the author of Taliqat bears some connection to Ibn Sinâ’s philosophy, which also includes a theory of celestial imagination and of its impact on human thought.[935]

One cannot refrain from comparing the theory of imagination put forth in Taliqat to al-Fârâbi’s theory of human imagination. It is well known that this concept plays a key role in al-Fârâbi’s epistemology, psychology, and prophet- ology. Among other things, imagination is what enables the prophet to trans­form intelligibles and demonstrative knowledge into a metaphorical language accessible to the masses. However, the differences between these theories seem greater than their similarities. In al-Fârâbi’s philosophy, the Agent Intellect is the only superlunary entity that can act directly on human reflection; the other heavenly bodies are not instrumental in this process. At any rate, al-Fârâbi himself says nothing about it. The Agent Intellect is responsible for transmit­ting intelligibles (maqülat), not imaginables (takhayyulat), to the human rational soul. As a corollary, imagination is a faculty developed only in humans and has no place in the heavens. In comparison, what is particularly compel­ling about the account in Taltqat is that it provides a link between human and celestial imagination, arguing that the imagination of the celestial bodies is directly responsible for the ‘imaginables’ in the human mind.

This brief analysis shows that the theory of celestial intellection developed in Taltqat is significantly different from the one that can be found in al-Fârâbi’s Àra and Siyasah, or, for that matter, in the rest of the Fârâbian corpus. In par­ticular, the ascription of imagination to the heavenly bodies and the emphasis on its causative power, as well as the primacy of potency over actuality, consti­tute sufficient grounds for rejecting the attribution of this treatise to al-Fârâbi. On the other hand, the theories developed in Taltqat are reminiscent of Ibn Sinâ’s cosmology, so that Y. Michot may be correct in attaching this work to the Avicennan corpus.[936] This being said, its doctrines do not completely over­lap with the Avicennan works. Ibn Sinâ upholds the theory of celestial imagi­nation, but he does not overtly ascribe such pervasive causative powers to the imaginative faculty of the celestial beings. For this reason, it would perhaps be precocious to attribute this version of Taltqat to Ibn Sinâ himself, since it could very well have been composed by one of his disciples or a member of his extended circle. Only future research will be able to settle this question decisively.

‘Uyün

That the author of ‘Uyün was also interested in cosmology is reflected in his protracted discussions of various key issues, especially the causation and motion of the celestial bodies and their influence on the sublunary world. It would not be an exaggeration to describe ‘Uyün as a cosmological- metaphysical treatise, which also contains interesting digressions on other physical and psychological topics. Like al-Fârâbi and the author of Taltqat, the author of ‘Uyün takes it for granted that the celestial bodies are ensouled beings that possess intellection as their principal activity and rotate in a per­fect circular motion. Moreover, in sections 7 and 8, the creation of the orbs is explained in the same manner as in the other treatises examined thus far: it is the intellection of the separate intellects that causes the existence of the orbs and the other lower intellects. It is notable, however, that the author of ‘Uyün does not indicate the total number of separate intellects and orbs; he claims not to be able to answer this question precisely, but only in a general manner (‘ala tartq al-jumlah).[937]

There are several other features in ‘Uyün that deserve attention. First, it is notable that the separate intellects possess a twofold intellection, which is described using Avicennan metaphysical terminology. The author writes: “Multiplicity is produced in the first created being (al-mubda al-awwal) acci­dentally, because it is possible of existence in itself and necessary of existence through the First, because it knows its essence and it knows the First.”[938] Again in section 8, it is said that “another intellect is produced by the first intellect as a result of its being necessary of existence and cognizant of the First ... and the first intellect in its being possible of existence and cognizant of its own essence produces the highest orb with its matter and form, which is its soul.”[939] Several features connect these passages to al-Fârâbi’s cosmology, such as the fact that only one cause is responsible for the form and matter of the orbs. This corre­sponds precisely to al-Fârâbi’s account in Àra and Siyasah, where by thinking about God, the first separate intellect produces the second intellect, and by thinking its own essence, it produces both the immaterial and corporeal com­ponents of the first heaven.[940] On the other hand, it differs from Ibn Sinâ’s tri­adic theory, which posits a cause for each one of these principles, one for intellect, one for matter, and one for form. Like al-Fârâbi’s treatises, ‘Uyün explains that the twofold intellection of the separate intellects results in their having multiplicity (kathrah), albeit by accident (bi-l-arad).[941]

Second, the ‘Uyün provides interesting information about the nature of the souls’ cognitive faculties. In the first place, the celestial bodies are said to have knowledge of both universals and particulars: wa-li-l-ajram al-samawat ma'lümüt kulliyyah wa-ma'lümát juziyyah. It is then specified that this dual knowledge entails that the celestial bodies undergo a kind of change or transi­tion (intiqal), since they must pass from one cognitive state to another, from the particular to the universal or more likely from one particular object to another. This transition occurs through or “by way of imagination” (‘ala sabll al-takhayyul). Furthermore, this intellectual imagination produces a corpo­real imagination (al-takhayyul al-jismünï), which is defined as the cause of celestial motion, itself a cause of sublunary change.[942] These ideas are quite original and find no parallel in the other Arabic cosmological texts analyzed thus far, although the digression on celestial imagination fits well in the con­text of Avicennan cosmology.

This section of ‘Uyün, which contains most of the information on the souls’ knowledge, is condensed and leaves many questions unanswered. For exam­ple, the mention of a transition (intiqal) with respect to the celestial beings’ intellection is problematic, because it would seem to imply potency, a fact that is not accounted for by the author. Moreover, knowledge of particulars suggests a discursive mode of thought, whereas knowledge of universals could be non-discursive. No clarifications are given concerning this point either. It should be stressed that the author of Taltqat in contrast addresses these issues expressly and defines the celestial bodies’ thought as discursive and potential.[943] Since ‘Uyün attributes particular objects of thought to the celestial bodies, one assumes that their intellection is also discursive and affected by potentiality. Finally, no precise information is given in ‘Uyün concerning the universal objects intellected by the celestial souls. Although these intelligibles may consist of the separate intellects or the First, they could just as well be the universal principles of sciences or Platonic ideas like ‘human’ or ‘horse.’ The author’s lack of precision on this point contrasts with the accounts of al-Fârâbi and Ibn Sina, which clearly identify the objects of the celestial souls’ intellec­tion. It also deviates from Taltqat, which specifies that “the orbs and planets intellect the First.”[944]

From the overview provided above, it appears that ‘Uyün and Taltqat share several cosmological doctrines, but also develop unique theories. For exam­ple, like Taltqat, ‘Uyün ascribes imagination to the celestial souls. In ‘Uyün, however, this imagination is not described so much as a faculty that can be clearly distinguished from rational thought, as a process of transition between two cognitive states; it is the means (tartq) between two kinds of thought, the universal and particular. Imagination fulfills no such function in Taltqat, although the assertion that “the [souls of the] orbs think these things [particu­lars?], and then imagine them”[945] definitely indicates a change or transition as well. In any case, Taltqat distinguishes imagination from intellection and clearly presents them as two different faculties. The theory of imagination as a demiurgic power, which is fully developed in Ta‘lïqat, finds no counterpart in ‘Uyün. Whereas Ta‘lïqat stresses the direct impact of celestial imagination on sublunary things and on human thought, Uyün describes this imagination merely as one of the principles underlying celestial motion.

The conclusion, then, is that although the celestial noetics in Ta‘lïqat and Uyün overlaps to a certain extent, these treatises essentially present two different cosmologies. They discuss common themes, such as celestial imagi­nation, but also contain substantial differences that likely point to a different authorship. Overall, it may be said that their contents are closer to Ibn Sina’s cosmology than to that of al-Farabi. From a cosmological perspective and on grounds of a doctrinal comparison, they should not be attributed to the Second Teacher and seem rather to belong to the Avicennan circle. This being said, a closer examination between these works and Ibn Sina’s cosmology is required in order to settle the question of their authorship in a definitive manner.

3. Celestial Motion

Talïqât

Taltqat provides a particular account of celestial motion that focuses not only on the contemplation of the heavenly intellects, but also on their will (iradah) and imagination (takhayyul). The author writes that “the orb[s] and planets contemplate the First Principle, such that this intellection generates pleasure and that motion follows out of this pleasure.” In addition, one reads that the “orb[s] conceive of the end along with their motions.”[946] These passages indi­cate that it is the intellection and mental conception of the heavenly bodies that causes their motion, although this is not achieved directly, but through the intermediary of pleasure (iltidhadh). This notion, which recalls Aristotle’s comments in Book Lambda 7 on the pleasure that accompanies contempla­tion, is here defined as an intermediary stage in the process leading to heav­enly motion. Motion is not the cause of pleasure or even synchronic with the pleasure that results from the intellection of the celestial souls; rather, motion is an outcome of their pleasure and blissful state.

In another passage, we read that “the cause of the constant circular motions [of the orbs] is their constant [acts of] willing, for which it is sufficient to posit only one mover that acts through love.”[947] Mention of the celestial will is reiter­ated in section 63, together with the concept of imitatio dei: “the will of [each] orb and planet is to perfect itself and imitate the One.”[948] Here it is will rather than intellection proper that is described as the main cause of motion, but these two concepts are not in any way opposed and usually go hand in hand in Arabic cosmology, as can be seen in the case of Ibn Sina.[949] The clarity and forcefulness with which these ideas are articulated greatly contrast with the fragmentary and ambiguous information provided by al-Farabi’s treatises. Although the views exposed in Ta'liqat are by no means incompatible with these treatises, al-Farabi does not elaborate on the concepts of pleasure and volition in his account of celestial kinematics.

On the other hand, Taltqat also establishes a connection between motion and imagination, an idea which is completely absent in al-Farabi’s cosmology, since the Second Teacher rejects the existence of this celestial faculty. As we have seen before, Taltqat states that the heavenly bodies possess intellects in potency, not in actuality, which means that their intellection is discursive and must progress from one object to another. Closely linked to this idea is the author’s claim that the celestial bodies can only “imagine [takhayyala] their individual motions one at a time and not all at once.” Hence, the imagination of the celestial bodies is subjected to the same limitation and follows the same pattern as their intellection. “If that were not the case,” the author continues, “then the planets would be able to perform the movements all at once, but this is impossible”[950] What is noteworthy in these passages is not the fact that the author ascribes imagination to the heavenly bodies—for as should be clear by now, this is typical of works composed in Ibn Sinâ’s circle—but rather that he seems to make imagination the primary principle or cause of heavenly motion. In other words, a motion that is imagined actually occurs, and this is why the planets cannot imagine all movements at once. Finally, it should be noted that Taltqat displays other interesting features about the heavens that do not find any parallel in al-Fârâbi’s works. These include the use of the term shakhs/ ashkhas to refer to the heavenly intellects and the strong connection between motion, imagination, and causation.[951]

‘Uyün

Compared to Taltqat, ‘Uyün contains limited information on the causes of celestial motion, but the theories it develops are nevertheless worth examin­ing. Like the other treatises under discussion, ‘Uyün describes heavenly motion as circular and regular and establishes a direct connection between the heavenly bodies’ imagination and motion: the former is the cause of the latter. More specifically, however, motion occurs when the souls’ “intellectual imagi­nation” becomes a “corporeal imagination” (al-takhayyul al-jismam). It is these particular, corporeal “imaginings” (takhayyulat) that translate into the continuously renewed corporeal movements of the orbs. Furthermore, heav­enly motion is a motion “in position” (wad'iyyaK), which is opposed to the motion “in place” (makaniyyah) of the sublunary bodies.[952] It should be noted that the concept of motion “in position” is typically Avicennan and is not mentioned by al-Fârâbi in the works attributed to him.[953] As in Taltqat, then, the concept of celestial motion in ‘Uyün is grounded chiefly in the concept of imagination. But here a further refinement and a special concept, “corporeal imagination,” is introduced and defined as an intermediary stage between the souls’ psychological activity and the physical motion of the orbs. This notion of corporeal imagination seems to be idiosyncratic to this treatise and does not have any equivalent in the other Arabic cosmological works I have examined.

Apart from imagination, ‘Uyün contains other notable kinematic features. In section 13, the necessity of a First Unmoved Mover is introduced on the basis of the impossibility of an infinite regress of movers and things moved. This fundamentally Aristotelian argument shows that the author of ‘Uyün was familiar with Physics and the Greek tradition of natural philosophy. The exist­ence of a First Unmoved Mover suggests, as in Aristotle’s cosmological system, that planetary motion occurs as a result of the orbs’ desire for the First Principle. Furthermore, the author follows the Arabic Peripatetics in making the souls desire other separate principles, which act as unmoved movers. This appears clearly when he writes that the motion of the orbs is “psychological, not natural [nafsaniyyah la tabiiyyah], and is due not to appetite [shahwah] or irascibility [ghadab], but to their desire [shawq] to imitate the intellects sepa­rated from matter.”[954]

If the celestial kinematics of ‘Uyün harkens back to Book Lambda and fol­lows al-Fârâbi’s cosmology in some respects, it also differs from it in a number of ways. First, it is notable that the author distinguishes between appetite (shahwah) and desire or love (shawq). Al-Fârâbi does not make this distinc­tion, but it is well-known that Ibn Sinâ did.[955] The basic idea is to elevate the heavenly bodies beyond the passions of sublunary beings and stress their nobleness and rational nature. It is an intellectual form of love that they expe­rience for the unmoved movers. Second, the opposition between natural and psychological motion is noteworthy. The author of ‘Uyün contrasts the purely psychological motion of the heavens with the natural motion of sublu­nary bodies. This connects with the definition of nature he provides as “the principle of motion and rest when these are not caused by an exterior thing or through will.”[956] Al-Fârâbi does not compare natural motion and spiritual motion in his works, except in Ithbat, whose authenticity is questionable. The view put forth in‘Uyün can in any case be attached more easily to Ibn Sinâ, who argues in many passages of his works that celestial motion is not natural and primarily caused by soul.[957]

The connection with Ibn Sinâ is further reinforced by a crucial concept that appears in ‘Uyün: mayl or inclination. To my knowledge, al-Fârâbi does not mention this concept in any of his works. Having explained that the uni­verse has a physical limit and a center and that void does not exist (these are well-known Aristotelian theses), the author then introduces the concept of natural inclination (al-mayl al-tabi'i), which he contrasts to compulsive or forced inclination (al-mayl al-qasri). The celestial orbs, he says, have “circular inclination by nature” (wa-l-falak bi-tab'ihl al-mayl al-mustadir).[958] This means that unlike the sublunary bodies, which are characterized by rectilinear incli­nation and whose motions may be governed by compulsion, circular motion is free of any kind of compulsion.

Finally, the concept of imitation (tashabbuh) should be mentioned here, since it plays an important role in the Arabic tradition. Al-Fârâbi does not elaborate on this concept in his works, although it probably underlies his gen­eral theory of celestial kinematics. On the other hand, it is discussed at length in the cosmology of such thinkers as Ibn Sina and Abu Sulayman al-Sijistani.[959] In ‘Uyün, tashabbuh is presented as the main activity and aim of the celestial bodies, which seek to attain the perfection of the higher immaterial principles through contemplation. The orbs desire and choose to contemplate the beauty of the separate intellects, and this contemplation is translated at the physical level into the eternal circular motions they perform.

As in many other cosmological adaptations derived from Aristotle’s Book Lambda, the author of this treatise also addresses the question of the object of the souls’ love. In this respect, the author writes that

each celestial body has a special separate intellect that it desires to imitate, and it is not fitting that the love of the entire system be directed at one thing of a single genus. Rather, each celestial body has a special beloved that is different from the object of the other orbs.

This implies that each separate intellect acts as an unmoved mover for its respective orb. However, immediately after this statement, the author adds that “the totality (al-kull) shares a single object of love, which is “the first object of desire” (al-mashüq al-awwal)”[960] This dual thesis that the celestial bodies share a single and universal object of love (God), which is responsible for inspiring their continuous circular motion, and at the same time that each one possesses a specific separate mover, is typical of Ibn Sina’s cosmology.[961]

To conclude, the celestial kinematics found in 'Uyün constitutes an eclectic system made up of various theories mostly drawn from the Greek and Arabic Peripatetic tradition. Noteworthy are the theories of imagination and inclina­tion, which are grafted on a basic Aristotelian cosmological scheme. Generally speaking, 'Uyüns theories of celestial motion are much closer to those of Ibn Sina than to those of al-Farabi. In fact, several points suggest that the author was active in Ibn Sina’s circle or that he was particularly influenced by the shaykh al-ra’is. The recognizable Avicennan features include: the ascription of imagination to the celestial bodies; the distinction between shahwah, ghadab, and shawq; a clear articulation of tashabbuh; and the concept of mayl. When added to the Avicennan terminology used in this work (“necessary” and “pos­sible of existence,” etc.), the accumulated cosmological evidence definitely points to Ibn Sina or one of his disciples as the author of this treatise.

Conclusion

‘Uyün, Taliqat, and Daawa contain cosmological ideas that are at odds with al-Fârâbi’s treatises. Whether with respect to celestial substance, intellection, imagination, or motion, these treatises generally elaborate theories that are absent from his works or contradict well-known Fârâbian positions, with only a few exceptions of doctrinal overlap. Why they became associated with his corpus at a certain point in time is a difficult question to answer, but one may hypothesize that the juxtaposition of cosmological treatises by al-Fârâbi and Ibn Sinâ in the same compilations could have led to this confusion. The other­wise many structural parallels between their cosmological systems would no doubt have contributed to this phenomenon.

On the other hand, it is unclear how much of the material contained in these works should be ascribed to Ibn Sinâ himself. While there are numerous parallels between his cosmology and these treatises, there are also certain elaborations that may best be interpreted as later developments brought about by thinkers who were deeply imbued with his teaching. Whether these works belong to a particular period of Ibn Sinâ’s output or were written by one of his disciples or by a later author inspired by his thought is a question for future research.


APPENDIX TWO

SUBSTANTIALIZATION (TAJAWHUR) AND THE
CELESTIAL AND HUMAN INTELLECTS

Tajawhur, together with its verbal form tajawhara, is a term encountered in al-Fârâbi’s and Ibn Sinâ’s philosophies and whose basic meaning is “substan- tialization” or “to become a substance.” Although tajawhur may be compared to the Greek terms oùoiôrnç (“substantiality”) and oùmômç (“substantifica- tion”) that appear in several late antique Neoplatonic texts, these references provide little help for understanding the way in which al-Fârâbi uses it.[962] As A. M. Goichon noted in her Lexique de la langue philosophique d’Ibn Sind, the meaning of this concept is difficult to pinpoint, and it seems at first glance to have been used more consistently by al-Fârâbi than by Ibn Sinâ.[963] The following paragraphs will attempt to shed light on these issues and to clarify the mean­ing and function of this concept in al-Fârâbi’s cosmological system.

It should be noted from the outset that tajawhur is a ubiquitous concept. Al-Fârâbi uses it in both a sublunary and superlunary context and applies it to entities as varied as the human soul, the celestial bodies, the separate intel­lects, and the First Itself. As a result, tajawhur overlaps the physical and meta­physical disciplines. In spite of this, one notices that al-Fârâbi applies this concept primarily to things that are already substances (sing. jawhar), and, what is more, to substances that either have attained their highest state of per­fection, such as the separate intellects, or which strive to attain them through motion and actualization, such as human beings. Tajawhur therefore relates to both immaterial entities and bodies. But here an important distinction applies, for while the intellects are from the outset (min awwal al-amr) in their highest state of perfection and always in actuality, other substances, such as the human soul, need to engage in change or motion to fully actualize their nature. It would seem, then, that tajawhur can be envisaged both as a process and as a state, depending on which beings it is applied to.

There are several passages in the Fârâbian corpus that are liable to shed more light on the concept of tajawhur. One of them appears in Ara, where al-Fârâbi explains that human beings are substantialized (tajawhara) by virtue of their rationality or rational speech (nutq), and where he furthermore distin­guishes this mode of substantialization from God’s unity and perfection.[964] This statement should be interpreted in the context of al-Fârâbi’s anthropology, according to which humans are distinguished from the other sublunary existents due to their capacity for rational thought. This difference enables humans to reach a state of perfection that is inaccessible to the non-rational animals. By virtue of their intellect, humans are connected with, and share an aspect of, the supernal, divine world, and it is only by fully engaging in its contemplation and study that they can hope to actualize their potential for wisdom and happiness.

In both the human and celestial contexts, tajawhur seems to be used prima­rily to indicate the role of the rational soul in actualizing the potentialities inherent in a being and in bringing this being to its utmost existential perfec­tion. But al-Fârâbi contrasts human perfection and divine perfection, or human substantialization and divine substantialization, on the grounds that human thought or speech is a discursive activity. Consequently, it is clear that the substantialization of human beings consists of a process that unfolds in time and involves change. More specifically, it is a process which requires the cultivation of the intellect and the ratiocinative faculties by means of study or reflection. From an Aristotelian perspective, one could say that tajawhur occurs when humans actualize their potentiality for knowledge.

Whereas human intellection is constantly shifting from potentiality to actuality, thereby implying a gradual and chronological substantialization, celestial intellection is in contrast eternally actual and unchanging, which means that the celestial substance itself is always actualized and in a state of utter perfection. As al-Fârâbi asserts in Siyasah, “the celestial bodies are, in their substances, always in a state of final perfection.” As a result, the planets have motions that “come out of their final perfections” and that are “never interrupted, not even for an instant.”[965] [966] According to al-Fârâbi, all the superlu­nary beings are in a state of actuality and utter perfection ‘from the outset’ and do not suffer from potentiality, except the celestial bodies which have only a potentiality for circular motion. Thus, al-Fârâbi opposes the changing and temporal substantialization of humans to the immutable, atemporal, and eternally perfect essence of the divine beings. In the latter case, substantializa­tion is co-extensive with their constant and non-discursive contemplative activity.

Al-Fârâbi provides additional information on the substantialization of the celestial bodies in Àra, when he explains that they become “substantialized” (tajawhara) by virtue of their souls. The celestial bodies are said to have “things [intellects] that are like forms and through which they [the celestial bodies] become substantialized [wa-ashya hiya laha ka-l-suwar bi-ha tatajawharu]” a statement which is mirrored in Siyasah.[967] Finally, al-Fârâbi says something quite similar in Ft l-‘aql, but the emphasis this time is on the agency of the separate intellects rather than on the activity of the souls:

Every celestial body is set in motion only by a mover that is neither a body nor in a body in any way. [This mover] is the cause of [the celestial body’s] existence, inasmuch as it is that by virtue of which [the celestial body] is a substance [tajawhara].[968]

This passage clearly defines the thawam as the main causes for the substan- tialization of the celestial bodies, here understood in terms of both efficient and final causality. The thawam cause the substances of the orbs and planets to exist, but they also inspire the contemplation and the movement of reversion of these entities toward their originative source, which allows their full actu­alization to take place. But since this act of reversion is eternal and continuous, the substantialization of the heavenly bodies is necessarily eternal as well, which means that they are in an unchanging state. At the heavenly level, then, the verb tajawhara refers not to a process involving change, but rather to the state of actualization of the heavenly bodies’ substance that results from the contemplative activity of their soul and, more precisely, from their intellection (taaqqul) of the higher principles. This in turn indicates that tajawhur is essentially connected with the concept of final causality.

In On the Soul 2.1, Aristotle had established an identity between soul and actuality when he wrote that the soul “is the first grade of actuality of a body.”[969] While al-Fârâbi’s concept of tajawhur may be construed as the actualization of the soul in an Aristotelian sense, it is more likely that it was informed by late antique Neoplatonic trends, which gradually came to see the soul as a source of perfection for the body by interpreting actuality (entelekheia) as perfection (teleiotês).[970] More specifically, al-Fârâbi seems to be following Proclus’ distinc­tion between various grades of perfections and applying these notions to his cosmology, although there are differences in the way in which these two think­ers defined them, which have been discussed by R. Wisnovsky.[971]

Yet, and this seems contradictory, al-Fârâbi’s concept of substantializa- tion is also connected at another level with deficiency and imperfection (nuqsan). The substantialization of the heavenly bodies is a result not just of their intellection, but more specifically of their contemplating a diversity of intelligibles: the First, the separate intellects, and their own essence. In Siyasah, al-Fârâbi explains that the heavenly bodies are more deficient than the sepa­rate intellects, because the “plurality by which they substantialize themselves is greater than that of the thawânï”[972] The celestial bodies share the concept of tajawhur with the separate intellects, and in both cases this concept is attached to complexity or multiplicity (kathrah), but it is associated with a different degree of multiplicity in each case. As for the First, in contrast to both the thawânï and the celestial souls, Its substantialization does not rely on any exte­rior thing to be complete—including an intelligible outside of Its essence— and therefore it does not suffer from any degree of complexity. Al-Fârâbi uses the verb tajawhara negatively when speaking about the First in order to stress that It does not need any exterior agent for its substance to be complete, one, and perfect.[973] In the separate intellects and celestial souls, however, the two concepts of tajawhur and nuqsan are intricately connected. Substantialization can refer simultaneously to the state of perfection and actuality reached by a substance and to the complexity and deficiency which underlies its nature as a caused existent.

Finally, the concept of substantialization also represents a convenient tool al-Fârâbi uses to compare human and celestial psychology. In Ft l-aql, he explains that when a person reaches the stage of the acquired intellect, “the substance of man, or man by virtue of what constitutes his substance, becomes the closest thing possible to the Agent Intellect.”[974] Like the celestial bodies, human beings become substantialized through intellection, and more specifi­cally by cultivating their rational soul until it becomes an acquired intellect (aql mustafad). But this is rendered possible only by connecting with the Agent Intellect, which explains why the more human beings substantialize themselves through contemplation, the more their substance—here defined as their rational soul—resembles the Agent Intellect, which is the source of their rationality. In both cases, then, the full realization of the substance that are the human and celestial souls is brought about through the contemplation of higher principles that are identical for both, namely, the immaterial existents. This connection between al-Fârâbi’s cosmology and psychology is further fle­shed out in Tahstl, when he writes that

This inquiry into the rational animal will thus lead him [the philosopher] to a similar conclusion as the inquiry into the heavenly bodies. Now he acquaints himself with incorporeal principles that are to the beings below the heavenly bodies as those incorporeal principles (with which he became acquainted when investigating the heavenly bodies) are to the heavenly bodies. He will acquaint himself with the principles for the sake of which the soul and the intellect are made, and with the ends and the ultimate perfection for the sake of which man is made.[975]

What is interesting in this passage is al-Fârâbi’s emphasis on intellection as the perfection and end for both human and heavenly beings. What unites human and heavenly souls in a harmonious and universal scheme is the possession of a rational faculty that enables them to fulfill a common nature and complete their perfection. This helps to explain why al-Fârâbi applies tajawhur to both the human and celestial intellects.[976]

The affinity between human and celestial psychology in al-Fârâbi’s works is furthermore illustrated by the principles of form and substrate, which are applied to both types of souls. For example, Fl l-‘aql compares the various stages or faculties of the human intellect to form and substrate, thereby estab­lishing a pendant to the emanationist treatises, where these same concepts are applied to the celestial bodies. This practice with regard to human psychology, as well as part of its terminology, can ultimately be traced to Aristotle’s On the Soul 3.4-5, but unlike the Stagirite al-Fârâbi applies this terminology to the heavenly souls as well. Accordingly, both the celestial and human rational souls can be defined as forms (sing. sürah) that inhere in a substrate. The use of a common terminological and conceptual framework in these two contexts explains why al-Fârâbi discusses human and celestial psychology in the same works and even in the same passages.[977]

The foregoing comments, and in particular the common application of tajawhur to the celestial and human contexts, raise the question of the exact relation between these various kinds of souls. In al-Fârâbi’s ontological hierar­chy, human beings are the only sublunary existents to possess reason, and it is by virtue of their rational soul that they are connected with the higher levels of the universe. This commonality appears clearly when al-Fârâbi says that heav­enly and human souls are “similar” or “congeneric” (mujanisah).[978] This state­ment suggests that both types of souls belong to a common genus, although they may not be exactly of the same nature.

This point is further refined when al-Fârâbi explains in this same passage that the heavenly souls differ from the human souls “in species” ( fl l-naw1) and that the former are detached and separated from the latter “in their sub­stances.” This difference can be explained by the fact that the heavenly intel­lects are “always actual” (daman bi-l-fi‘l), whereas the human souls pass from a state of potency to one of actuality. Both types of souls contemplate different intelligibles: the celestial souls, al-Fârâbi writes, “definitely do not contemplate the majority of the intelligibles that humans contemplate from things in mat­ter because they are too far in rank by virtue of their substance to intellect the intelligibles that are below them.”[979] Finally, whereas human intellects need to abstract forms from their material substrates before they can be apprehended as intelligibles, the celestial souls do not need to perform this process of abstraction.

These points highlight the important epistemological and cognitive differ­ences between the celestial and human souls and suggest that it is not possible for the human intellect to fully assimilate the knowledge of the celestial beings, at least during one’s earthly life. In spite of this, the human souls can, by revert­ing to the higher or prior ontic principles and by cultivating contemplation and theoretical knowledge, bring their substance to its fullest degree of actu­alization and perfection and experience eudaimonia (sa'ddah). In that sense, tajawhur is a concept that is also intimately linked to the possibility of human happiness in this life.


Primary Sources in Greek and in Translation

Alexander of Aphrodisias. 1992a. On Aristotle’s Metaphysics. 5 vols. Translated by W E. Dooley and A. Madigan. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

-- . 1992b. Quaestiones. Translated by R. W Sharples. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

-- . 1980. The De anima of Alexander of Aphrodisias: A Translation and Commentary. By A. P. Fotinis. Washington, D.C.: University Press of America.

Aristotle. 2001 [1941]. The Basic Works of Aristotle. Edited by R. McKeon. New York: The Modern Library.

-- . 2000. On the Heavens. English translation by W K. C. Guthrie. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.

-- . 1992 [1970]. Aristotle Physics Books I and II. Translated with introduction, com­mentary, note on recent work, and revised bibliography by W. Charlton. Oxford: University Press.

-- . 1975. Aristotle’s Posterior Analytics. Translated with notes by Jonathan Barnes. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

--- . 1965. Du ciel. Texte établi et traduit par P. Moraux. Paris: Les Belles Lettres.

Commentaria in Aristotelem graeca. 1881-. Ed. consilio et auctoritate Academiae Litterarum Regiae Borussicae. Preusische Akademie der Wissenschaften Berlin: Reimer.

Philoponus, John. 2005a. Against Procluss ‘On the Eternity of the World 1-5’ Translated by M. Share. Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press.

-- . 2005b. Against Procluss ‘On the Eternity of the World, 6-8’ Translated by M. Share. Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press.

-- . 1994. Philoponus On Aristotle’s Physics 5-8 with Simplicius On Aristotle on the Void. Translated by P. Lettinck and J. O. Urmson. Ithaca, New York: Cornell University Press.

-- . 1987. Philoponus: Against Aristotle, on the Eternity of the World. Translated by C. Wildberg. London: Duckworth.

Plato. 1997. Complete Works. Edited, with introduction and notes, by John M. Cooper; associate editor, D.S. Hutchinson. Indianapolis, Ind.: Hackett Pub.

Plotinus. 1966-88. Enneads. Trans. A.H. Armstrong, Loeb Classical Library. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press/London: Heinemann.

Proclus. 2001. On the Eternity of the World (De aeternitate mundi). Greek text with introduction, translation, and commentary by H. S. Lang and A. D. Macro; argu­ment translated from the Arabic by J. McGinnis. Berkeley, Calif.; London: University of California Press.

-- . 1966-. Commentaire sur le Timée. Translated by A. J. Festugière. Paris: Vrin.

-- . 1963. 2nd edition. Elements of Theology. Translation, introduction, and com­mentary by E. R. Dodds. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

Ptolemy, Claudius. 1987. Las hipótesis de los planetas. Introduction and notes by E. Pérez Sedeño. Translated by J. García Blanco and A. Cano Ledesma. Madrid: Alianza.

-- . 1984. Ptolemy’s Almagest. Translated and annotated by G. J. Toomer. London: Duckworth.

Simplicius. 2006. On Aristotle’s ‘On the Heavens 1.10-12’ Translated by R. J. Hankinson. Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press.


- . 2005. On Aristotle’s ‘On the Heavens 2.10-14’ Translated by I. Mueller. Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press.

- . 2004a. On Aristotle on the Heavens 2.1-9. Translated by I. Mueller. London: Duckworth.

- . 2004b. On Aristotle on the Heavens 1.5-9. Translated by R. J. Hankinson. London: Duckworth.

- . 2002. On Aristotle on the Heavens 1.1-4. Translated by R. J. Hankinson. London: Duckworth.

- . 1997. On Aristotle Physics 2. Translated by B. Fleet. London: Duckworth.

Syrianus. 2008. Syrianus on Aristotle Metaphysics 3-4. Translated by D. O’Meara and J. Dillon. London: Duckworth.

- . 2006. On Aristotle Metaphysics 13-14. Translated by J. Dillon and D. O’Meara. London: Duckworth.

Primary Sources in Arabic and in Translation

Alexander of Aphrodisias. 2003. Traité de la providence=Peri pronoias. Version arabe de Abu Bisr Matta ibn Yünus; introduction, edition, et traduction de Pierre Thillet. Lagrasse: Verdier.

- . 2001. Alexander of Aphrodisias on the Cosmos. Translation and commentary by C. Genequand. Leiden: Brill.

Aristiitalis. 1964. Al-tabi'ah. Edited by A. Badawi. 2 vols. Cairo: Al-Dar al-Qawmiyyah li-Tibaah wa-l-Nashr.

Al-Ashari, Abu l-Hasan. 1987. Usul ahl al-sunnah wa-l-jamaah al-musamma bi-risalah ahl al-thaghr. Edited by M. Julaynad. Cairo: Kulliyyah Dar al-Ulum, Jamiah al-Qahirah.

Al-Bayhaqi, Ali ibn Zayd. 1935-. Kitab tatimmat si wan al-hikmah. Lahore: L. Ishwar Das, Registrar, University of the Panjab.

Al-Farabi, Abu Nasr. 2008. Larmonia delle opinioni dei due sapienti il divino Platone e Aristotele. Introduzione, testo arabo, traduzione e commento di C. Martini Bonadeo. Prefazione di G. Endress. Pisa: Edizioni Plus, Pisa University Press.

- . 2001a. Alfarabi, the Political Writings: Selected Aphorisms and Other Texts. Translated and annotated by C. E. Butterworth. Ithaca, N.Y., and London: Cornell University Press.

- . 2001b. Lépître sur l’intellect (Al-Risâla fî-l-‘aql, li-Abû Nasr Al-Fârâbî). Traduit de l’arabe, annoté et présenté par Dyala Hamzah. Paris: L’Harmattan.

- . 2001c [1962]. Alfarabi: Philosophy of Plato and Aristotle. Translated, with an introduction by M. Mahdi. Ithaca, New York: Cornell University Press.

- . 1999a. ‘Uyun al-masail. Edited by F. Dieterici. Reprinted in Islamic Philosophy, vol. 12, Bad rasa il al-Farabi fi l-falsafah. Frankfurt am Main, Federal Republic of Germany: Institute for the History of Arabic-Islamic Science at the Johann Wolfgang Goethe University, 56-65.

- . 1999b. Risalah fi ma yanbaghi an yuqaddama qabla taallum al-falsafah. Reprinted in Islamic Philosophy, vol. 12, Bad rasa il al-Farabi fi l-falsafah. Frankfurt am Main, Federal Republic of Germany: Institute for the History of Arabic-Islamic Science at the Johann Wolfgang Goethe University, 49-55.

- . 1999c. Fi aghrad al-hakim fi kull maqalah min al-kitab al-mawsum bi-l-huruf. Reprinted in Islamic Philosophy, vol. 12, Bad rasa il al-Farabi fi l-falsafah. Frankfurt am Main, Federal Republic of Germany: Institute for the History of Arabic-Islamic Science at the Johann Wolfgang Goethe University, 34-38.

- . 1999d. Ithbat al-mufariqat. Reprinted in Islamic Philosophy, vol. 12, Bad rasa il al-Farabi fi l-falsafah. Frankfurt am Main, Federal Republic of Germany: Institute for the History of Arabic-Islamic Science at the Johann Wolfgang Goethe University, 41-48.

- . 1999e. L’harmonie entre les opinions de Platon et d’Aristote. Texte arabe et traduc­tion par F. M. Najjar et D. Mallet. Institut Français de Damas.

- . 1992. Al-a‘mal al-falsafiyyah. Includes Kitab tahsil al-sa‘adah; Kitab al-tanbih ‘ala sabil al-sa‘adah; Risalatan falsafiyyatan. Al-risalah 1: Maqalah Abi Nasr fima yasihhu wa-ma la yasihhu min ahkam al-nujum; al-risalah 2: Jawabat li-masail suila ‘anha, edited by J. Àl Yasin. Bayrüt: Dar al-Manahil.

- . 1989. Kitab al-wahid wa-l-wahdah. Edited by M. Mahdi. Casablanca: Les Editions Toubkal.

- . 1987. Al-mantiqiyyat li-l-Farabi. Vol. 1. Haqqaqaha wa-qaddama la-ha M. Taqï Danish pazhüh. Qum: Manshurat Maktabat Àyat Allah al-Thzmâ al-Marashï al-Najafï.

- . 1985a. Al-Farabi on the Perfect State: Abu Nasr al-Farabis Mabadiaraahl al-madïna al-fadila. A revised text with introduction, translation, and commentary by R. Walzer. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

- . 1985b. Kitab ara’ ahl al-madinah al-fadilah. Edited by A. N. Nadir. Beirut: Dar al-Mashriq.

- . 1985c-. Al-mantiq ‘inda l-Farabi. 4 vols. Edited by R. al-Ajam and M. Fakhry. Beirut: Dar al-Mashriq.

- . 1981a. Al-Farabi’s Commentary and Short Treatise on Aristotle’s De interpreta­tione. Translated with an introduction and notes by F.W. Zimmermann. London: Published for the British Academy by Oxford University Press.

--- . 1981b. Kitab tahsil al-sa‘adah. Edited by J. Àl Yasïn. Beirut: Dar al-Andalus.

- . 1976. Maqalah li-Abi Nasr al-Farabi fi l-jihah allati yasihhu ‘alayha l-qawl fi ahkam al-nujum. In Nusus falsafiyyah mihdah ila l-duktur Ibrahim Madkur, 69-74. Cairo: Al-hayah al-Misriyyah al-Àmmah li-l-Kitab.

- . 1974. Epistola sull’intelletto. Traduzione, introduzione, e note a cura di F. Lucchetta. Padova: Antenore.

- . 1972. Al-radd ‘ala Yahya l-Nahwi. The Arabic Text of Alfarabi’s Against John the Grammarian. Edited by M. Mahdi. In Medieval and Middle Eastern Studies: In Honor of Aziz Suryal Atiya, edited by Sami A. Hanna, 268-285. Leiden: Brill.

- . 1971a. Deux ouvrages sur la rhétorique. Edited by J. Langhade and M. Grignaschi. Beyrouth: Dar el-Machreq.

- . 1971b. Fusul muntazaah. Edited by F. M. Najjar. Beirut: Dar al-Mashriq.

- . 1970. Kitab al-huruf. Edited by M. Mahdi. Beirut: Dar al-Mashriq.

- . 1968. Kitab al-millah wa-nusus ukhra. Edited by M. Mahdi. Beirut: Dar al-Mashriq.

- . 1964. Kitab al-siyasah al-madaniyyah al-mulaqqab bi-mabadi l-mawjudat. Edited by F. M. Najjar. Beirut: Al-Matbaah al-Kathulikiyyah.

- . 1963. Short Commentary on Aristotle’s Prior Analytics. Translated from the origi­nal Arabic with introduction and notes by N. Rescher. [Pittsburgh]: University of Pittsburgh Press.

--- . 1961a. Falsafat Aristutalis. Edited by M. Mahdi. Bayrut: Dar Majallat Shir.

- . 1961b. Fusul al-madani. Aphorisms of the Statesman. Edited with an English translation, introduction and notes by D. M. Dunlop. Cambridge: University Press.

- . 1960a. Kitab al-musiqa l-kabir. Edited by Ghattas Abd al-Malik Khashabah. Cairo: Dar al-Katib al-Arabi li-l-Tibaah wa-l-Nashr.

- . 1960b. Al-Farabi’s Commentary on Aristotle’s Peri ermeneias (De interpreta­tione). Edited with an introduction by W Kutsch and S. Marrow. Beirut: Imprimerie catholique.

- . 1957. Al-Farabi’s Introductory Risalah on Logic. Edited by D. M. Dunlop. The Islamic Quaterly 3/4: 224-236.

-- . 1955. Introductory Sections on Logic [Fustil tashtamilu ‘ala jami' ma yudtarru ila ma'rifatihi man arada l-shuru fi sinaat al-mantiq; text and translation by D. M. Dunlop]. The Islamic Quaterly 2: 264-282.

-- . 1951. Risalah fi l-khala: Farabi’s Article on Vacuum. Edited and translated by N. Lugal and A. Sayili. Ankara, Türk Tarih Kurumu Basimevi: 1-16, 21-36.

-- . 1949. Second Edition. Ihsa’ l-‘ulum li-l-Farabi. Edited by Osman Amine. Cairo [n. p.].

-- . 1938. Risalah fi l-‘aql. Edited by M. Bouyges. Beirut: Bibliotheca arabica scholas­ticorum, série arabe, tome VIII, fasc. 1, XXIV.

-- . 1930. Tajrid risalat al-daawa l-qalbiyyah. Haydarabad: Matbaal-Majlis Dairat al-Maarif al-Uthmaniyyah.

Al-Farghani, Ahmad ibn Muhammad ibn Kathir 1986. Jawami' ‘ilm al-nujum wa-usul al-harakat al-samawiyyah. Edited and translated by Jacob Golius. Frankfurt am Main: Institut für Geschichte der Arabisch-Islamischen Wissenschaften an der Johann Wolfgang Goethe Universitat.

Al-Ghazali. 1997. The Incoherence of the Philosophers (Tahafut al-falasifah). Translated by M. Marmura. Provo, Utah: Brigham Young University Press.

Ibn Abi Usaybiah. 1965. Uyun al-anba‘ fi tabaqat al-atibba. Edited by N. Rida. Beirut: Dar Maktabat al-Hayah.

Ibn Khalliqan. 1977-1978 [v. 1, 1978]. Wafayat al-ayan wa-anba abna’ l-zaman.

8 vols. Edited by I. Abbas. Beirut: Dar Sadir.

Ibn al-Nadim, Muhammad ibn Ishaq. 1970. The Fihrist of al-Nadim: A Tenth-Century Survey of Muslim Culture. Edited and translated by B. Dodge. New York: Columbia University Press.

Ibn Qurra, Thabit. 1987. Œuvres d’astronomie. Texte établi et traduit par R. Morelon. Paris: Société dédition Les Belles Lettres.

Ibn Rushd. 1997. Grand commentaire sur le Traité de l’Âme d’Aristote. Texte latin établi par F. Crawford. [Tunis]: Académie tunisienne des sciences des lettres et des arts Beït al-Hikma.

-- . 1986. Averroes’ de substantia orbis. Critical edition, with English translation and commentary by A. Hyman. Cambridge; Jerusalem: Medieval Academy of America.

-- . 1984a. Talkhis al-sama wa-l-‘alam. Taqdim wa-tahqiq J. al-Alawi. Fez: Jamiat Sidi Muhammad ibn Abd Allah, Kulliyat al-Âdab wa-l-Ulum al-Insaniyyah bi-Fas.

-- . 1984b. Ibn Rushd’s Metaphysics: A Translation with Introduction of Ibn Rushd’s Commentary on Aristotle’s Metaphysics, Book Lam, by C. Genequand. Leiden: Brill.

-- . 1984c. Grand commentaire de la Métaphysique d’Aristote (Tafsir Ma bad at- tabi'at): livre Lam-Lambda. Traduit de l’arabe et annoté [par] Aubert Martin. Paris: Belles lettres.

-- . 1983. Kitab al-sama' al-tabi‘i. Edited by J. Puig. Madrid: Instituto Hispano-Arabe de Cultura: Consejo Superior de Investigaciones Científicas.

-- . 1958. Talkhis ma ba'da l-tabi‘ah. Edited by U. Amin. Al-Qahirah: Wizarat al- Tatbiyyah wa-l-Talim.

Ibn Sina. 2005. The Metaphysics of The Healing: A Parallel English-Arabic Text. Translated, introduced, and annotated by M. E. Marmura. Provo, UT: Brigham Young University Press.

-- . 1999. Risalah fi aqsam al-‘ulum al-‘aqliyyah. Edited by A. Hundih, reprinted in Islamic Philosophy, vol. 42, Abu Ali al-Husayn ibn ‘Abdallah ibn Sina, Philosophical Treatises. Institute for the History of Arabic-Islamic Science at the Johann Wolfgang Goethe University, Frankfurt am Main, 114-129.

-- . 1986. Le livre de science (Danesh-nameh). Traduit par M. Achena et H. Massé. Paris: Les Belles Lettres: Unesco.

--- . 1985. Kitab al-najah fl l-hikmah al-mantiqiyyah wa-l-tabiiyyah wa-l-ilahiyyah.

Edited by M. Fakhry. Beyrut: Dar al-Afaq al-Jadidah.

--- . 1984. Al-mabda‘ wa-l-maad. Edited by A. Nurani. Tehran.

-- . 1983-1986. Kitab al-shifa. Tasdir T. Husayn; murajaat I. Madkur; tahqiq al-Ab Qanawati, M. al-Khudayri, F. al-Ahwani. Qum, Iran: Maktabat Àyat Allah al-Uzma al-Marashi al-Najafi.

-- . 1957-60. Al-isharat wa-l-tanbihat, maa sharh Nasir al-Din al-Tusi. 4 vols., edited by S. Dunya. Egypt: Dar al-Maarif.

-- . 1951. Livre des directives et remarques (Kitab al-isharat wa-l-tanbihat). Traduction avec introduction et notes par A.-M. Goichon. Beyrouth: Commission internation­ale pour la traduction des chefs-d’œuvre. Paris: Vrin (Collection d’oeuvres arabes de l’UNESCO).

-- . 1908. Risalah fi l-ajram al-‘ulwiyyah. In Tis' rasa il fi l-hikmah wa-l-tabi'iyyat. Misr: Matba ah Hindiyyah bi-l-Müsiki.

Ikhwan al-Safa. 1957. Rasa il Ikhwan al-SaJa'' wa-Khillan al-Wafa. 4 vols. Bayrüt; Dar Sadir.

Al-Khwarizmi. 1968. Kitab mafatih al-‘ulüm. Edited by G. van Volten. Lugduni- Batavorum.

Al-Kindi, Abu Yüsuf Yaqub ibn Ishaq. 1998. Œuvres philosophiques et scientifiques d‘al-Kindi. Métaphysique et cosmologie, vol. 2, par R. Rashed et J. Jolivet. Leiden; New York: Brill.

-- . 1950-53. Rasai al-Kindi l-falsafiyyah. 2 vols. Edited by M. A. Abu Ridah. Egypt: Dar al-Fikr al-Arabi.

Al-Kirmani, Hamid al-Din. 1967. Rahat al-‘aql. Bayrut: Dar al-Andalus li-l-Tibaah wa-l-Nashr wa-l-Tawzi.

Maimonides. 1963. The Guide of the Perplexed. 2 vols. Translated with an introduction and notes by S. Pines; with an introductory essay by L. Strauss. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

Al-Qabisi, Abu l-Saqr Abd al-Aziz ibn Uthman. 2004. The Introduction to Astrology. Editions of the Arabic and Latin texts and an English translation by C. Burnett, K. Yamamoto, and M. Yano. London: Warburg Institute.

Al-Qifti, Ali ibn Yusuf. 1903. Ta’rikh al-hukama. Edited by J. Lippert. Leipzig: Dieterichsche Verlagsbuchhandlung.

Al-Razi, Abu Bakr Muhammad ibn Zakariyya. 1939. Rasa il falsafiyyah. Edited by Paul Kraus. Cairo: Matbaat Bul Barbih. ■

Al-Razi, Abu Hatim Ahmad ibn Hamdan. 1998. Kitab al-islah. Tehran: Muassasah-i Mutalaat-i Islami, Danishgah-i Tihran, Danishgah-i Makgil.

Al-Razi, Fakhr al-Din. 1999. Al-matalib al-‘aliyyah min al-ilm al-ilahi. Bayrut: Dar al- Kutub al-Ilmiyyah.

--- . 1980. Al-tafsir al-kabir. Bayrut: Dar Ihyal-Turath al-Arabi.

-- . 1966. Kitab al-mabahith al-mashriqiyyah fi ilm al-ilahiyyat wa-l-tabi‘iyyat. Tehran: Maktabat al-Asadi.

Saadia Gaon. 1976. The Book of Beliefs and Opinions. Translated from the Arabic and the Hebrew by S. Rosenblatt. New Haven: Yale University Press.

-- . 1891. Commentaire sur le Séfer Yesira ou livre de la création. Traduit par M. Lambert. Paris: Bouillon.

Al-Sijistani, Abu Sulayman. 1974a. Maqalah fi anna l-ajram al-‘ulwiyyah dhawat anfus natiqah. In Siwan al-hikmah wa-thalath rasa''il. Edited by A. Badawi. Tehran: Bunyad-i Farhang-i Iran.

-- . 1974b. Maqalah fi al-muharrik al-awwal. In Siwan al-hikmah wa-thalath rasa''il. Edited by A. Badawi. Tehran: Bunyad-i Farhang-i Iran.

Themistius. 1999. Paraphrase de la Métaphysique d’Aristote (livre lambda). Traduit de l’hébreu et de l’arabe; introduction, notes et indices par R. Brague. Paris: Vrin.

Secondary Sources

Abed, Shukri B. 1991. Aristotelian Logic and the Arabic Language in Alfarabi. New York: SUNY.

Acar, Rahim. 2005. Talking about God and Talking about Creation: Avicenna’s and 'Thomas Aquinas’ Positions. Leiden; Boston: Brill.

Adamson, Peter (ed.). 2008a. In the Age of al-Farabi: Arabic Philosophy in the Fourth/ Tenth Century. London: The Warburg Institute/ Turin: Nino Aragno Editore.

- . 2008b. “The Theology of Aristotle.” In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2010 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = <http://plato.stanford.edu/ archives/sum2010/entries/theology-aristotle/>.

--- . 2007a. Al-Kindi. Oxford: University Press.

- . 2007b. The Kindian Tradition: The Structure of Philosophy in Arabic Neoplatonism. In The Libraries of the Neoplatonists, edited by C. DAncona. Leiden; Boston: Brill, 351-371.

- . 2006. The Arabic Sea Battle: al-Farabi on the Problem of Future Contingents. Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 88: 163-188.

- . 2003. Al-Kindi and the Mutazila: Divine Attributes, Creation and Freedom. Arabic Sciences and Philosophy 13/1: 45-77.

- . 2002a. The Arabic Plotinus: A Philosophical Study of the Theology of Aristotle. London: Duckworth.

- . 2002b. Abu Mashar, al-Kindi and the Philosophical Defense of Astrology. Recherches de théologie et philosophie médiévales 69/2: 245-270.

Afnan, Soheil. 1964. Philosophical Terminology in Arabic and Persian. Leiden: Brill.

Alami, Ahmed. 2001. Lontologie modale: étude de la theorie des modes dAbu Hasim al-Gubbai. Paris: Vrin.

Alon, Ilai. 2002. Al-Farabi’s Philosophical Lexicon. 2 vols. [Cambridge]: E. J. W Gibb Memorial Trust.

Alonso Alonso, Manuel. 1959. Los “ Uyün al-masâil” de al-Farabi (tesis fundamen­tales). Al-Andalus 24: 251-273.

Âlusi, Husam Muhyi al-Din. 1968. The Problem of Creation in Islamic Thought: Qur’an, Hadith, Commentaries, and Kalam. [Bagdad] National Print and Pub. Co.

Altmann, Alexander. 1979. Creation and Emanation in Isaac Israeli: A Reappraisal. In Studies in Medieval Jewish History and Literature, edited by I. Twersky. Harvard: University Press, 1-16.

Altmann, Alexander, and S. M. Stern. 1958. Isaac Israeli: A Neoplatonic Philosopher of the Early Tenth Century, His Works Translated with Comments and an Outline of His Philosophy. [London] Oxford University Press.

Aouad, Maroun. 1992. Les fondements de la Rhétorique dAristote reconsidérés par Fârâbi, ou le concept de point de vue immédiat et commun. Arabic Sciences and Philosophy 2/1: 133-180.

- . 1989-. “La Théologie d’Aristote et autres textes du Plotinus arabus” In Dictionnaire des philosophes antiques. Paris: Éditions du Centre national de la recherche scienti­fique, vol. 1, 541-590.

Arnaldez, Roger. 1976. L’âme et le monde dans le système philosophique de Farabi. Studia islamica 43: 53-63.

Asín Palacios, Miguel. 1914. Abenmasarra y su escuela: orígenes de la filosofía his- panomusulmana. [Madrid: s.n.].

Atiyeh, George N. 1966. Al-Kindi: The Philosopher of the Arabs. Rawalpindi: Islamic Research Institute.

Badawi, Abd al-Rahman. 1987. 2nd edition. La transmission de la philosophie grecque au monde arabe. Paris: Vrin.

- (ed.). 1977a. Al-aflatuniyyah al-muhdathah ‘inda l-‘arab. Kuwait: Wikalat al-Matbuat.

--- (ed.). 1977b [1955]. Aflütin 'inda l-Arab. Kuwait: Wikalat al-Matbuat.

-- (ed.). 1971. Commentaires sur Aristote perdus en grec et autres épîtres. Bayrut: Dar el-Mashreq.

-- (ed.). 1961. Aristü ta lis fi l-sama wa-l-athar al-‘ulwiyyah. Translated by Yahya ibn al-Bitriq. Cairo: Maktabat al-Nahdah al-Misriyyah.

-- (ed.). 1947. Aristü ‘inda l-‘arab: dirasah wa-nusüs ghayr manshürah. Kuwayt: Wakalat al-Matbu at.

Baltussen, Han. 2010. Simplicius of Cilicia. In The Cambridge History of Philosophy in Late Antiquity, 2 vols., edited by L. P. Gerson. Cambridge: University Press, vol. 2, 711-733.

Barthold, W [B. Spuler]. “Farab.” Encyclopaedia of Islam, Second Edition. Leiden: Brill, 1960-.

Beaney, Michael. 2007. “Analysis.” In the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy online: http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/analysis/

Beere, Jonathan. 2003. Counting the Unmoved Movers: Astronomy and Explanation in Aristotle’s Metaphysics XII.8. Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 85/1: 1-20.

Bellosta, Hélène. 1991. Ibrâhîm ibn Sinan: On Analysis and Synthesis. Arabic Sciences and Philosophy 1/2: 211-233.

Bertolacci, Amos. 2006. The Reception of Aristotle’s Metaphysics in Avicenna’s Kitab al-Shifa: A Milestone of Western Metaphysical Thought. Leiden; Boston: Brill.

-- . 2005a. Ammonius and al-Farabî: The Sources of Avicenna’s Concept of Metaphysics. Quaestio 2: 287-305.

-- . 2005b. On the Arabic Translations of Aristotle’s Metaphysics. Arabic Sciences and Philosophy 15: 241-275.

-- . 2001. From al-Kindî to al-Farabî: Avicenna’s Progressive Knowledge of Aristotle’s Metaphysics according to his Autobiography. Arabic Sciences and Philosophy 11: 257-295.

Birkenmajer, Alexander. 1935. Eine wiedergefundene Übersetzung Gerhards von Cremona. Beitrage zur Geschichte der Philosophie und Theologie des Mittelalters (Suppl. 3.1): 472-481.

Black, Deborah L. 2006. Knowledge film) and Certitude (yaqin) in al-Farabî’s Epistemology. Arabic Sciences and Philosophy 16: 11-45.

-- . 1996. “Al-Farabî.” In History of Islamic philosophy, 2 vols., edited by S. H. Nasr and O. Leaman. London; New York: Routledge, vol. 1, 178-198.

-- . 1990. Logic and Aristotle’s Rhetoric and Poetics in Medieval Arabic Philosophy. Leiden: Brill.

-- . 1982-. “Logic.” In “Farabî,” Encyclopaedia Iranica, edited by E. Yarshater. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, vol. 9, 213-216.

Blumenthal, H. J. 1996. Aristotle and Neoplatonism in Late Antiquity: Interpretations of the De anima. Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press.

Bodnár, István M. 1997. Alexander of Aphrodisias on Celestial Motions. Phronesis 17/2: 190-205.

Boer, Tjitze de. “Kuwwa.” Encyclopaedia of Islam, Second Edition. Leiden: Brill, 1960-.

Booth, Edward. 1983. Aristotelian Aporetic Ontology in Islamic and Christian Thinkers. Cambridge [Cambridgeshire]; New York: Cambridge University Press.

Bosworth, C. E. 1963. A Pioneer Arabic Encyclopedia of the Sciences: Al-Khwarizmî’s Keys of the Sciences. Isis 54/1: 97-111.

Bowen, Alan C. 2007. The Demarcation of Physical Theory and Astronomy by Geminus and Ptolemy. Perspectives on Science 15/3: 327-358.

-- . 2002. Simplicius and the Early History of Greek Planetary Theory. Perspectives on Science 10/2: 155-167.

Broadie, Sarah. 1993. Que fait le premier moteur d’Aristote? Revue philosophique de la France et de l’étranger 183 : 375-411.

Brockelmann, Carl. 1996 [1943-49]. Geschichte der arabischen Litteratur. 2 vols. Leiden: Brill.

Brown, H. V. B. 1972. Avicenna and the Christian Philosophers in Baghdad. In Islamic Philosophy and the Classical Tradition: Essays to Richard Walzer, edited by S. M. Stern, Albert Hourani, and Vivian Brown. Oxford: Cassirer, 35-48.

Burnett, Charles. 2002. The Certitude of Astrology: The Scientific Methodology of al-Qabisi and Abu Mashar. Early Science and Medicine 7/3: 198-213.

Buschmann, Elisabeth. 1979. Untersuchungen zum Problem der Materie bei Ibn Sina. Europaische Hochschulschriften. Reihe XX, Philosophie, Bd. 38. Frankfurt am Main: P. Lang.

Carmody, Francis J. 1952. The Planetary Theory of Ibn Rushd. Osiris 10: 556-586.

Clay, J. S. 2003. Hesiod’s Cosmos. Cambridge; New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.

Collins, Adela Yarbro. 1996. Cosmology and Eschatology in Jewish and Christian Apocalypticism. Leiden: Brill.

Colmo, Christopher A. 2005. Breaking with Athens: Alfarabi as Founder. Lanham, etc.: Lexington Books.

Corbin, Henri. 1971-72. En islam iranien. 4 vols. [Paris:] Gallimard.

Crone, Patricia. 2004. Al-Farabi’s Imperfect Constitutions. Mélanges de l’Université Saint-Joseph 57: 191-229.

- . 2003. What was al-Farabi’s ‘Imamic’ Constitution? Arabica 50/3: 306-321.

Cruz Hernández, Miguel. 1950-1951. El “Fontes quaestionum” (Uyün al-masâil) de Abu Nasr al-Fârâbi. Archives d’histoire doctrinale et littéraire du Moyen Age 18: 303-323.

Daiber, Hans. 2004. The Limitations of Knowledge According to Ibn Sina: Epistemological and Theological Aspects and the Consequences. In Erkenntnis und Wissenschaft: Probleme der Epistemologie in der Philosophie des Mittelalters (Knowledge and Science: Problems of Epistemology in Medieval Philosophy), edited by M. Lutz-Bachmann, A. Fidora und P. Antolic. Berlin: Akademie Verlag, 25-35.

- . 1991. The Ismaili Background of Farabi’s Political Philosophy. Abu H atim ar-Razi as a Forerunner of Farabi. In Gottes ist der Orient - Gottes ist der Okzident: Festschrift für Abdoldjavad Falaturi zum 65. Geburstag, edited by U. Tworuschka. Koln-Wien: Bohlau, 143-150.

- . 1986. The Ruler as Philosopher: A New Interpretation of al-Farabi’s View. Amsterdam; New York: North-Holland Pub. Co.

- . 1980. Aetius Arabus: die Vorsokratiker in arabischer Überlieferung. Wiesbaden: F. Steiner.

D’Ancona, Cristina. 2010. The Origins of Islamic Philosophy. In The Cambridge History of Philosophy in Late Antiquity, 2 vols., edited by L. P. Gerson. Cambridge: University Press, vol. 2, 869-894.

- . 2006. The Topic of the “Harmony between Plato and Aristotle”: Some Examples in Early Arabic Philosophy. In Wissen über Grenzen: Arabisches Wissen und Lateinisches Mittelalter, edited by Andreas Speer and Lydia Wegener. Berlin; New York: De Gruyter, 379-406.

- . 2005. Greek into Arabic: Neoplatonism in Translation. In The Cambridge Companion to Arabic Philosophy, edited by P. Adamson and R. C. Taylor. Cambridge University Press, 10-32.

- . 2003. Plotino: La discesa dell’anima nei corpi; Plotiniana arabica. Edited by C. D’Anconca. Padova: Il Poligrafo.

- . 2000. Avicenna and the Liber de Causis: A Contribution to the Dossier. Revista Española de Filosofía Medieval 7: 95-114.

- . 1995. Recherches sur le Liber de causis. Paris: Vrin.

D’Ancona, Cristina, and R. C. Taylor. 2003. “Liber de causis.” In Dictionnaire des phi­losophes antiques. Paris: Éditions du Centre national de la recherche scientifique, Supplément, 599-647.

Davidson, H. A. 1992. Alfarabi, Avicenna, and Averroes on Intellect: 'Their Cosmologies, Theories of the Active Intellect, and Theories of Human Intellect. New York; Oxford: Oxford University Press.

-- . 1987. Proofs for Eternity, Creation and the Existence of God in Medieval Islamic and Jewish Philosophy. New York: Oxford University Press.

--- . 1972. Alfarabi and Avicenna on the Active Intellect. Viator 3: 109-178.

-- . 1969. John Philoponus as a Source of Medieval Islamic and Jewish Proofs of Creation. JAOS 89/2: 357-391.

Demidcik. V. P. 1975. Kosmologiya al-Farabi i iyo osnovnie istocniki. In Al-Farabi, Naucnoe tvorcestvo. Moscow, 13-30.

De Smet, Daniel. 2008. Al-Farabi’s Influence on H amid al-Dïn al-Kirmani’s Theory of Intellect and Soul. In In the Age of al-Farabi: Arabic Philosophy in the Fourth/Tenth Century, edited by P. Adamson, London: The Warburg Institute/Turin: Nino Aragno Editore, 131-151.

-- . 2007. Les bibliothèques ismaéliennes et la question du néoplatonisme ismaélien. In The Libraries of the Neoplatonists, edited by C. D’Ancona. Leiden; Boston: Brill, 481-493.

-- . 1998. Empedocles arabus: une lecture néoplatonicienne tardive. Brussel, Paleis der Academien: KAWLSK.

-- . 1995. La quiétude de l’intellect: néoplatonisme et gnose ismaélienne dans l’œuvre de Hamid al-Din al-Kirmani (Xe/XIe s.). Leuven: Uitgeverij Peeters en Departement Oosterse Studies.

Dhanani, Alnoor. 2007. “Farabi.” In The Biographical Encyclopedia of Astronomers, edited by T. Hockey et al. New York: Springer.

-- . 1994. The Physical Theory of Kalam: Atoms, Space, and Void in Basrian Mutazili Cosmology. Leiden: Brill.

Dicks, D. R. 1970. Early Greek Astronomy to Aristotle. Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press.

Di Giovanni, Matteo. 2006. Averroes on the Species of the Celestial Bodies. In Wissen über Grenzen: Arabischen Wissen und Lateinisches Mittelalter, edited by A. Speer and L. Wegener. Berlin; New York: De Gruyter, 438-467.

Dillon John. 2000. The Role of the Demiurge in the Platonic Theology. In Proclus et la théologie platonicienne: actes du Colloque international de Louvain, 13-16 mai 1998, en l’honneur de H.D. Saffrey et L.G. Westerink, edited by A. Ph. Segonds and C. Steel, with the help of C. Luna and A. F. Mettraux. Leuven: Leuven University Press, 339-349.

Dreyer, J. L. E. 1953. A History of Astronomy from Thales to Kepler. Second edition. USA: Dover Publications [Originally published in 1906 under the title History of the Planetary Systems: from Thales to Kepler. Cambridge: University Press].

Druart, T.-A. 1998. Le sommaire du livre des lois de Platon. Bulletin d’études orientales 50: 109-155.

-- . 1992. Al-Farabi, Emanation, and Metaphysics. In Neoplatonism and Islamic Thought, edited by P. Morewedge. New York: State University of New York Press, 127-149.

-- . 1987a. Al-Farabi and Emanationism. Studies in Medieval Philosophy 17: 23-43.

-- . 1987b. Substance in Arabic Philosophy: Al-Farabi’s Discussion. In Substance. Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association 61: 88-97.

-- . 1982a-. “Metaphysics.” In “Farabi,” Encyclopaedia Iranica, edited by E. Yarshater. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, vol. 9, 216-219.

-- . 1982b. Le traité dal-Farabi sur les buts de la Métaphysique d’Aristote. Translated by Th.-A. Druart. Bulletin de philosophie médiévale 24: 38-43.

-- . 1981. Al-Farabi’s Causation of the Heavenly Bodies. In Islamic Philosophy and Mysticism, edited by P. Morewedge. New York: Caravan Books, 35-47.

-- . 1979. Le second traité de Farabi sur la validité des affirmations basées sur la posi­tion des étoiles. Bulletin de philosophie médiévale 21: 47-51.

- . 1978. Astronomie et astrologie selon Farabï. Bulletin de philosophie médiévale 20: 43-47.

- . 1977. Un sommaire du sommaire Farabien des « Lois » de Platon. Bulletin de philosophie médiévale 19: 43-45.

Duhem, Pierre. 1990 [1908]. Sozein ta phainomena: essai sur la notion de théorie phy­sique de Platon à Galilée. Paris: Vrin.

- . 1913-59. Le système du monde: histoire des doctrines cosmologiques de Platon à Copernic. 10 vols. Paris: A. Hermann.

Eastwood, Bruce. 2007. Ordering the Heavens: Roman Astronomy and Cosmology in the Carolingian Renaissance. Leiden [The Netherlands]; Boston, MA: Brill.

Elamrani-Jamal, Abdelali. 1996. Ibn al-Sïd al-Batalyüsï et l’enseignement d’al-Farabi. Bulletin d’études orientales 48: 155-164.

Endress, Gerhard. 2007. Building the Library of Arabic Philosophy. Platonism and Aristotelianism in the Sources of al-Kindï. In The Libraries of the Neoplatonists, edited by C. D’Ancona. Leiden; Boston: Brill, 319-351.

- . 2003. Mathematics and Philosophy in Medieval Islam. In The Enterprise of Science in Islam: New Perspectives, edited by J. P. Hogendijk and A. I. Sabra. Cambridge, Mass.; London: MIT Press, 121-177.

- . 2002. Alexander Arabus on the First Cause: Aristotle’s First Mover in an Arabic Treatise Attributed to Alexander of Aphrodisias. In Aristotele e Alessandro di Afrodisia nella tradizione araba: atti del Colloquio La ricezione araba ed ebraica della filosofia e della scienza greche, Padova, 14-15 Maggio 1999. Edited by C. d’Ancona and G. Serra. Padova: Il poligrafo, 19-75.

- . 1997a. The Circle of al-Kindï. Early Arabic Translations from the Greek and the Rise of Islamic Philosophy. In The Ancient Tradition in Christian and Islamic Hellenism, edited by G. Endress and R. Kruk. Leiden: Research School CNWS, 43-76.

- . 1997b. L’aristote arabe. Réception, autorité, et transformation du Premier Maître. Medioevo 23: 1-42.

- . 1995. Averroes’ De caelo: Ibn Rushd’s Cosmology in his Commentaries on Aristotle’s On the Heavens. Arabic Sciences and Philosophy 5: 9-49.

- . 1991. La <Concordance entre Platon et Aristote>, l’Aristote arabe et l’émancipation de la philosophie en Islam médiéval. In Historia Philosophiae Medii Aevi. Studien zur Geschichte der Philosophie des Mittelaters, hrsg. B. Mojsisch and O. Pluta. Amsterdam; Philadelphia: Grüner, 237-257.

- . 1977. The Works of Yahya ibn ‘Adi: An Analytical Inventory. Wiesbaden: Dr. Ludwig Reichert Verlag.

- . 1973. Proclus Arabus: zwanzig Abschnitte aus der Institutio theologica in ara- bischer Übersetzung. Beirut: Orient-Institut der Deutschen Morgenlandischen Gesellschaft, in Kommission bei F. Steiner, Wiesbaden.

- . 1966. “Die arabischen Ubersetzungen von Aristoteles’ Schrift De caelo” Inaug. Diss. Frankfurt am Main: Bildstelle der J.W. Goethe-Universitat.

- . “Matta b. Yünus al-Kunnâï, Abu Bishr.” Encyclopaedia of Islam, Second Edition. Leiden: Brill, 1960-.

Ess, Josef van. 1991. Theologie und Gesellschaft im 2. und 3. Jahrhundert Hidschra: eine Geschichte des religiosen Denkens im frühen Islam. Berlin; New York: de Gruyter.

--- . 1980. Al-Farabï and Ibn al-Rëwandï. Hamdard Islamicus 3/4: 3-15.

Evans, James. 2003. The Origins of Ptolemy’s Cosmos. In Cosmology through Time: Ancient and Modern Cosmologies in the Mediterranean Area, Conference proceed­ings, Astronomical Observatory of Rome, Monteporzio Catone, June 17-20, 2001, edited by S. Colafrancesco and G. Giobbi, Milano: Mimesis, 123-135.

Evans, James and J. Lennart Berggren. 2006. Geminos’ Introduction to the Phenomena: A Translation and Study of a Hellenistic Survey of Astronomy. Princeton; Oxford: Princeton University Press.

Fakhry, Majid. 2002. Al-Farabi: Founder of Islamic Neoplatonism. Oxford: Oneworld.

- . 1968. A Tenth-Century Arabic Interpretation of Plato’s Cosmology. Journal of the History of Philosophy 6: 15-22.

- . 1965. Al-Farabi and the Reconciliation of Plato and Aristotle. Journal of the History of Ideas 26/4: 469-478.

Fattal, Michel. 2008. Aristote et Plotin dans la philosophie arabe. Paris: L’Harmattan.

Fazzo, Sylvia. 2002. Aporia e sistema: la materia, la forma, il divino nelle Quaestiones di Alessandro di Afrodisia. Pisa: ETS.

Fazzo, Silvia, and Hillary Wiesner. 1993. Alexander of Aphrodisias in the Kindï-circle and in al-Kindï’s Cosmology. Arabic Sciences and Philosophy 3: 119-153.

Ferrari, Cleophea. 2005. “La scuola aristotelica di Bagdad.” In Storia della filosofa nell’Islam medievale, 2 vols., a cura di C. D’Ancona. Torino: Piccola Biblioteca Einaudi, vol. 1, 352-380.

Finnegan, James. 1957. Al-Fârâbî et le nepi voE d’Alexandre d’Aphrodise. In Alexander of Aphrodisias in the Arabic Tradition, collected and reprinted by F. Sezgin. Frankfurt am Main: Institute for the History of Arabic-Islamic Science at the Johann Wolfgang Goethe University, 2000, 139-159.

Freudenthal, Gad. 1990. Al-Fârâbï on the Foundations of Geometry. In Knowledge and the Sciences in Medieval Philosophy, Proceedings of the Eighth International Congress of Medieval Philosophy (S.I.E.P.M.), Helsinki 24-29 August 1987, edited by M. Asztalos, J. E. Murdoch, and I. Niiniluoto. Helsinki: Acta Philosophica Fennica, vol. 1, 54-61.

- . 1988. La philosophie de la géométrie d’al-Fârâbï. Jerusalem Studies in Arabic and Islam 11: 104-220.

Galston, Miriam. 1990. Politics and Excellence: The Political Philosophy of Alfarabi. Princeton: University Press.

- . 1981. Al-Fârâbï on Aristotle’s Theory of Demonstration. In Islamic Philosophy and Mysticism, edited by P. Morewedge. New York: Caravan Books, 23-35.

- . 1977. A Re-examination of al-Fârâbï’s Neoplatonism. Journal of the History of Philosophy 15: 1-33.

Gannagé, Emma. 2004. Y a-t-il une pensée politique dans le Kitab al-Huruf dal- Fârâbï? Mélanges de l’Université Saint-Joseph 57: 229-259.

Gardet, Louis. “Hayulâ.” Encyclopaedia of Islam, Second Edition. Leiden: Brill, 1960-.

- . “Ibda.” Encyclopaedia of Islam, Second Edition. Leiden: Brill, 1960-.

Gâtje, Helmut. 1982. Simplikios in der arabischen Überlieferung. Islam 59: 6-31.

- . 1971. Studien zur Überlieferung der aristotelischen Psychologie im Islam. Heidelberg: C. Winter.

Gaudefroy-Demombynes, Maurice. 1941. Er-Razi philosophe d’après des ouvrages récents. Revue de l’histoire des religions 124: 142-190.

Geoffroy, Marc. 2003. Remarques sur la traduction Ustât du livre Lambda de la « Métaphysique », chapitre 6. Recherches de théologie et philosophie médiévale 70/2: 417-437.

- . 2002. La tradition arabe du Hepi voü d’Alexandre d’Aphrodise et les origines de la doctrine farabienne des quatre degrés de l’intellect. In Aristotele e Alessandro di Afrodisia nella tradizione araba, edited by C. D’Ancona and G. Serra. Padova: Il poli- grafo, 191-231.

Gerson, L. P. 1993. Plotinus’ Metaphysics: Emanation or Creation? The Review of Metaphysics 46/3: 559-574.

Gill, M. L. 1994. Aristotle on Self-Motion. In Self-Motion from Aristotle to Newton, edited by M. L. Gill and J. G. Lennox. Princeton: University Press, 15-34.

Gilson, Étienne. 1929. Les sources gréco-arabes de l’augustinisme avicennisant. Archives d’histoire doctrinale et littéraire du moyen âge 4: 5-149.

Gimaret, Daniel. 1990. La doctrine d‘al-Ash‘ari. Paris: Cerf.

Glasner, Ruth. 2000. The Question of Celestial Matter in the Hebrew Encyclopedias. The Medieval Hebrew Encyclopedias of Science and Philosophy, edited by Steven Harvey. Dordrecht; Boston; London: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 313-335.

Gobillot, Genevieve. 2002. Quelques stéréotypes cosmologiques d’origine pythagorici­enne chez les penseurs musulmans au Moyen Age. Revue de l’histoire des religions 219/1: 55-87.

Goichon, A. M. 1938. Lexique de la langue philosophique d’Ibn Sina. Paris : Desclée de Brouwer.

- . 1935. La distinction de l’essence et de l’existence d’après Ibn Sina. Paris: Desclée De Brouwer.

- . “Huwiyya.” Encyclopaedia of Islam, Second Edition. Leiden: Brill, 1960-.

Goldstein, Bernard R. 1997. Saving the Phenomena: The Background to Ptolemy’s Planetary Theory. Journal for the History of Astronomy 28/1: 1-12.

- . 1980. Book Review of F. Sezgin’s Geschichte des arabischen Schrifttums, vol. VI, Astronomie bis ca. 430 H. Isis 71/2: 341-342.

- . 1972. Theory and Observation in Medieval Astronomy. Isis 63: 39-47.

- . 1967. The Arabic Version of Ptolemy’s Planetary Hypotheses. Transactions of the American Philosophical Society 57/4: 3-55.

Goulet, Richard, and Maroun Aouad. 1989-. “Alexandras d’Aphrodisias.” In Dictionnaire des philosophes antiques. Paris: Éditions du Centre national de la recherche scientifique, vol. 1, 125-139.

Grant, Edward. 2004. Science and Religion, 400 B.C. to A.D. 1550: From Aristotle to Copernicus. Westport, Conn.: Greenwood Press.

- . 1994. Planets, Stars, and Orbs: The Medieval Cosmos, 1200-1687. Cambridge: University Press.

- . 1978. “Cosmology.” In Science in the Middle Ages, edited by D. C. Lindberg. Chicago; London: University of Chicago Press, 265-303.

Griffel, Frank. 2009. Al-Ghazali’s Philosophical Theology. Oxford: University Press.

- . 2005. Taqlid of the Philosophers. Al-Ghazali’s Initial Accusation in his Tahafut. In Ideas, Images, and Methods of Portrayal. Insights into Classical Arabic Literature and Islam, edited by S. Günther. Leiden: Brill, 273-296.

Griffith, Sydney. 2008. The Church in the Shadow of the Mosque: Christians and Muslims in theWorld of Islam. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

- . 2007. From Patriarch Timothy I to H unayn ibn Ishaq: Philosophy and Christian Apology in Abbasid Times; Reason, Ethics, and Public Policy. In Christians and Muslims in Dialogue in the Islamic Orient of the Middle Ages. Christlich-muslimische Gesprache im Mittelalter, edited by M. Tamcke. Beiruter Texte und Studien 117. Beirut: Orient-Institut/Würzburg: Ergon Verlag, 75-99.

Grignaschi, Mario. 1969. Al-Farabi et « L’Epître sur les connaissances à acquérir avant d’entreprendre létude de la philosophie. » Turkiyat Mecmuasi XV den Ayri Basim Istanbul 15: 175-210.

Gutas, Dimitri. 2006a. Intellect without Limits: The Absence of Mysticism in Avicenna. In Intellect and Imagination in Medieval Philosophy, 3 vols., edited by M. C. Pacheco and J. F. Merinhos. Turnhout: Brepols, vol. 1, 351-372.

- . 2006b. Imagination and Transcendental Knowledge in Avicenna. In Arabic Theology, Arabic Philosophy. From the Many to the One: Essays in Celebration of Richard M. Frank, edited by J. E. Montgomery. Leuven; Paris; Dudley: Peeters, 337-355.

- . 2004a. Geometry and the Rebirth of Philosophy in Arabic with al-Kindi. In Words, Texts, and Concepts Cruising the Mediterranean Sea, edited by R. Arnzen and J. Thielmann. Leuven; Paris; Dudley, MA.: Peeters, 195-211.

- . 2004b. The Meaning of madani in al-Farabi’s “Political” Philosophy. Mélanges de l’Université Saint-Joseph 57: 259-283.

- . 2003. Review of M. Mahdi’s Alfarabi and the Foundation of Islamic Political Philosophy. IJMES 35: 145-147.

- . 2002. The Study of Arabic Philosophy in the Twentieth Century: An Essay on the Historiography of Arabic Philosophy. British Journal of Middle Eastern Studies 29/1: 5-25.

- . 2001. Intuition and Thinking: The Evolving Structure of Avicenna’s Epistemology. In Aspects of Avicenna, edited by R. Wisnovsky. Princeton: Markus Wiener, 1-39.

- . 1999. The Alexandria to Baghdad’ Complex of Narratives. Documenti e studi sulla tradizione filosofica medievale 10: 155-193.

- . 1998. Greek Thought, Arabic Culture: The Graeco-Arabic Translation Movement in Baghdad and Early Abbasid Society (2nd-4th/8th-10th Centuries). London: Routledge.

- . 1997. Galen’s Synopsis of Plato’s Laws and Farabi’s Talhis. In The Ancient Tradition in Christian and Islamic Hellenism, edited by G. Endress and R. Kruk. Leiden: Research School CNWS, 101-121.

- . 1993. Aspects of Literary Form and Genre in Arabic Logical Works. In Glosses and Commentaries on Aristotelian Logical Texts: The Syriac, Arabic, and Medieval Latin Traditions, edited by C. Burnett. London: The Warburg Institute, 29-77.

- . 1988. Avicenna and the Aristotelian Tradition. Leiden: Brill.

- . 1983. Paul the Persian on the Classification of the Parts of Aristotle’s Philosophy: A Milestone between Alexandria and Bagdâd. Der Islam 60: 231-267.

- . 1982a-. “Biography.” In “Farabi,” Encyclopaedia Iranica, edited by E. Yarshater. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, vol. 9, 208-213.

- . 1982b-. “Farabi and Greek Philosophy.” In “Farabi,” Encyclopaedia Iranica, edited by E.Yarshater. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, vol. 9, 219-223.

Gutman, Oliver. 2003. Pseudo-Avicenna: Liber celi et mundi: A Critical Edition with Introduction. Leiden; Boston: Brill.

Gyekye, Kwame. 1989. Al-Farabi on the Logic of the Arguments of the Muslim Philosophical Theologians. Journal of the History of Philosophy 27/1: 135-145.

--- . 1972. Al-Farabi on Analysis’ and Synthesis.’ Apeiron 6: 33-38.

Haas, Frans A. J. de. 1997. John Philoponus’ New Definition of Prime Matter: Aspects of its Background in Neoplatonism and the Ancient Commentary Tradition. New York: Brill.

Habby, Joseph. 1997. Yulianna ibn Haylan, maestro di al-Farabi e l’Organon di Aristotele. In La diffusione dell’ eredità classica nell’ età tardoantica e medievale, edited by A. Valvo. Torino: Edizioni dell’ Orso, 95-109.

Hall, Robert E. 2004. Intellect, Soul, and Body in Ibn Sina: Systematic Synthesis and Development of the Aristotelian, Neoplatonic, and Galenic Theories. In Interpreting Avicenna: Science and Philosophy in Medieval Islam. Proceedings of the Second Conference of the Avicenna Study Group, edited by J. McGinnis, with the assistance of D. C. Reisman. Ledein; Boston: Brill, 62-86.

Haq, Syed Nomanul. 1994. Names, Natures and Things: The Alchemist Jabir ibn Hayyan and his Kitab al-Ahjar (Book of Stones). Dordrecht; Boston: Kluwer.

Hartner, Willy. “Falak.” Encyclopaedia of Islam, Second Edition. Leiden: Brill, 1960-.

--- . 1964. Medieval Views on Cosmic Dimensions and Ptolemy’s Kitab al-Manshurat.

In Mélanges Alexandre Koyré. Paris: Hermann, vol. 1, 254-282.

Hasnawi, Ahmad. 2001. La définition du mouvement dans la Physique du Sifa’ dAvicenne. Arabic Sciences and Philosophy 11: 219-255.

- . 1996. Un élève d’Abü Bisr Matta b. Yünus: Abu Amr al-Tabari. Bulletin d’études orientales 48: 35-55.

- . 1994. Alexandre d’Aphrodise et Jean Philopon: notes sur quelques traités dAlexandre “perdus” en grec, conservés en arabe. Arabic Sciences and Philosophy 4: 53-109.

- . 1990. “Fayd.” In Encyclopédie philosophique universelle, Les notions philos­ophiques, 2 vols., dirigé par S. Auroux. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France, vol. 2, t. 1, 966-72.

-- . 1985. Fârâbï et la pratique de l’exégèse philosophique. Revue de synthèse 117: 27-59.

-- . 1984. La dynamique d’Ibn Sina. In Etudes sur Avicenne, edited by J. Jolivet and R. Rashed. Paris: Les Belles Lettres, 103-123.

Heinen, Anton M. 1982. Islamic Cosmology: A Study of as-Suyüti’s Al-haya as-sanïya fi l-haya as-sunnïya. Beirut; Wiesbaden: In Kommission bei Franz Steiner Verlag.

-- . 1978. Averroes’ Idea of Astronomy Being in Agreement with Reality. Hamdard Islamicus 1/3: 3-14.

Hilal, Aziz. 2001. Farabi et le problème de l’homonymie accidentelle. Studia Islamica 92: 155-165.

Hintikka, Jaakko, and Unto Remes. 1974. The Method of Analysis: Its Geometrical Origin and its General Significance. Dordrecht; Boston: D. Reidel Pub. Co.

Holmberg, Bengt. “Nastüriyyün.” Encyclopaedia of Islam, Second Edition. Leiden: Brill, 1960-.

Honigmann, Ernest. 1950. The Arabic Translation of Aratus’ Phenomena. Isis 41/1: 30-31.

Horowitz, W 1998. Mesopotamian Cosmic Geography. Winona Lake, Ind.: Eisenbrauns.

Huart, Clément. “Kursï.” Encyclopaedia of Islam, Second Edition. Leiden: Brill, 1960-.

Hübner, Wolfgang. 2000. The Ptolemaic View of the Universe. Greek, Roman and Byzantine Studies 41/1: 59-93.

Hübner, Wolfgang, and Hermann Hunger. 2002-. “Astrology.” In Brill’s New Pauly. Antiquity. Edited by H. Cancik and H. Schneider; English edition, managing editor,

C.    F. Salazar, assistant editor, D. E. Orton Brill. Leiden; Boston: Brill.

Hugonnard-Roche, Henri. 2007. Le corpus philosophique syriaque aux VIe-VIIe siè­cles. In The Libraries of the Neoplatonists, edited by C. D’Ancona. Leiden; Boston: Brill, 279-293.

-- . 2003. “De caelo. Traditions syriaque et arabe.” In Dictionnaire des philosophes antiques. Paris: Éditions du Centre national de la recherche scientifique, Supplément, 283-294.

-- . 1985. Lépitomé du De caelo d’Aristote par Averroès. Questions de méthode et de doctrine. Archives d’histoire doctrinale et littéraire du moyen-âge 52: 7-39.

Hyman, Arthur. 1977. Aristotle’s “First Matter” and Avicenna’s and Averroes’ “Corporeal Form.” In Essays in Medieval Jewish and Islamic Philosophy. New York: Ktav Publishing House, 335-356.

Iskenderoglu, Muammer. 2002. Fakhr al-Din al-Razi and Thomas Aquinas on the Question of the Eternity of the World. Leiden; Boston; Koln: Brill.

Ivry, Alfred L. 1991. Neoplatonic Currents in Maimonides’ Thought. In Perspectives on Maimonides: Philosophical and Historical Studies, edited by J. L. Kraemer. Oxford; New York: Published for the Littman Library by Oxford University Press, 115-141.

-- . 1990. An Evaluation of the Neoplatonic Elements in al-Farabi’s and Ibn Sina’s Metaphysics. In Acts of the International Symposium on Ibn Turk, Khwârezmî, Fârâbî, Beyrûnî, and Ibn Sînâ. Ankara: Atatürk Supreme Council for Culture, Language and History, 135-147.

Jaeger, Werner. 1948. Second edition. Aristotle, Fundamentals of the History of his Development. Translated with the author’s corrections and additions by R. Robinson. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

Janos, Damien. 2011 (forthcoming). Moving the Orbs: Astronomy, Physics, and Metaphysics and the Problem of Celestial Motion according to Ibn Sïnâ. Arabic Sciences and Philosophy 21/1.

-- . 2010a. The Greek and Arabic Proclus and al-Fârâbï’s Theory of Celestial Intellection and its Relation to Creation. Documenti e studi sulla tradizione filosofica medievale 21: 19-45.

- . 2010b. Al-Fârâbï on the Method of Astronomy. Early Science and Medicine 15/3: 237-265.

- . 2009a. Al-Fârâbï, Creation ex nihilo, and the Cosmological Doctrine of K. al-Jam and Jawabat. Journal of the American Oriental Society 129/1: 1-18.

- . 2009b. “Intellect, Substance, and Motion in al-Fârâbï’s Cosmology.” Ph.D. diss., McGill University.

Janssens, Jules. 2004. Experience (tajriba) in Classical Arabic Philosophy. Quaestio 4: 45-62.

- . 2003. Avicenne et sa « paraphrase-commentaire » du livre Lambda (« Kitâb al-insâf »). Recherches de théologie et philosophie médiévale 70/2: 401-417.

- . 1997. Creation and Emanation in Ibn Sïnâ. Documenti e studi sulla tradizione filosofica medievale 8: 455-477.

Jolivet, Jean. 2006. Étapes dans l’histoire de l’intellect agent. In Perspectives médiévales et arabes. Paris: Vrin, 163-175.

- . 1995. La matière den haut. In Philosophie médiévale arabe et latine. Paris: Vrin, 90-111.

- . 1993. Al-Kindï, vues sur le temps. Arabic Sciences and Philosophy 3/1: 55-77.

- . 1977. L’intellect selon Fârâbï: quelques remarques. In Mélanges offerts à Henri Laoust. Institut Français de Damas. Bulletin d’études orientales, XXIX, I, 252-259.

Kennedy-Day, Kiki. 2003. Books of Definition in Islamic Philosophy. London; New York: Routledge.

Khalil, Atif. Some Tensions in Farabi’s Metaphysics of the One and the Emanative Descent. Transcendent Philosophy 1 [no date]: 83-108.

Khalil, Georr. 1941-1946. Farabi est-il l’auteur des Fusüs al-hikam? Revue des études islamiques 15: 31-39.

King, David A. 1997. “Astronomy in the Islamic World.” In Encyclopaedia of the History of Science, Technology, and Medicine in Non-Western Cultures, edited by H. Selin. Dordrecht; Boston: Kluwer Academic, 125-134.

Kosman, A. 1994. Aristotle’s Prime Mover. In Self-Motion from Aristotle to Newton, edited by M. L. Gill and J. G. Lennox. Princeton: University Press, 135-153.

Kuhn, 'Thomas S. 1962. The Copernican Revolution: Planetary Astronomy in the Development of Western Thought. New York: Vintage Books.

Kraemer, Joel. 1992. Humanism in the Renaissance of Islam: The Cultural Revival dur­ing the Buyid Age. 2nd rev. ed. Leiden; New York: Brill.

- . 1991. Maimonides on the Philosophic Sciences in his Treatise on the Art of Logic. In Perspectives on Maimonides: Philosophical and Historical Studies, edited by J. L. Kraemer. Oxford; New York: Published for the Littman Library by Oxford University Press, 77-105.

- . 1986. Philosophy in the Renaissance of Islam: Abu Sulayman al-Sijistani and his Circle. Leiden: Brill.

- . 1967. “Abu Sulaymân as-Sijistânï: A Muslim Philosopher of the 10th Century.” Thesis (Ph.D.), Yale University.

- . 1965. A Lost Passage from Philoponus’ Contra aristotelem in Arabic Translation. JAOS 85/3: 318-327.

Krafft, Fritz. 2002-. “Astronomy.” In Brill’s New Pauly. Antiquity. In Brill’s New Pauly. Antiquity. Edited by H. Cancik and H. Schneider; English edition, managing editor, Christine F. Salazar, assistant editor, D. E. Orton Brill. Leiden; Boston: Brill.

Kraus, Paul. 1986. Jabir ibn Hiyyan: contribution a l’histoire des idées scientifiques dans l’islam. Jabir et la science grecque. Paris: Les Belles Lettres.

Kubesov, Audenbek. 1981. Astronomiia v trudakh al‘-Farabi. Alma-Ata: Izd-vo “Nauka” Kazakhskoi SSR.

- . 1974. Matematikeschoe nasledie al’-Farabi. Alma-Ata: Nauka.

Kubesov, Audanbek, et al. 1975. Kommentarii k ‘Al’-Magestu Ptolemeja. Alma-Ata: Izd-Nauka.

Kunitzsch, Paul, and J. Knappert. “al-Nudjüm.” Encyclopaedia of Islam, Second Edition. Leiden: Brill, 1960-.

Lameer, Joep. 1997. From Alexandria to Baghdad: Reflections on the Genesis of a Problematical Tradition. In The Ancient Tradition in Christian and Islamic Hellenism: Studies on the Transmission of Greek Philosophy and Sciences, edited by G. Endress and R. Kruk. Leiden: School of Asian, African, and Amerindian Studies, 181-193.

-- . 1994. Al-Farabi and Aristotelian Syllogistics: Greek Theory and Islamic Practice. Leiden; New York; Koln: Brill.

Langermann, Tzvi. 1991. The ‘True Perplexity:’ The Guide of the Perplexed, Part II, Chapter 24. In Perspectives on Maimonides: Philosophical and Historical Studies, edited by J. L. Kraemer. Oxford; New York: Published for the Littman Library by Oxford University Press, 159-175.

Langhade, Jacques. 1994. Du Coran à la philosophie: la langue arabe et la formation du vocabulaire philosophique de Farabi. Damas: Institut Français de Damas.

Lerner, Michel-Pierre. 1996. Le monde des sphères. 2 vols. Paris: Les Belles Lettres.

Lettinck, Paul. 1994. Aristotle’s Physics and its Reception in the Arabic World: With an Edition of the Unpublished Parts of Ibn Bajja’s Commentary on the Physics. Leiden: Brill.

Levin, Leonard and David R. Walker. 2008. “Isaac Israeli.” In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2008 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = <http://plato .stanford.edu/archives/fall2008/entries/israeli/>.

Lewin, Bernhard. 1954. La notion de muhdath dans le kalam et dans la philosophie. Orientalia suecana, vol. 2, fasc. 2/4: 84-94.

Lewis, Geoffroy. 1959. Theology of Aristotle. Translated into English by Geoffrey Lewis. In Plotini opera, edited by P. Henry and H.-R. Schwyzer. Paris and Brussels, II, 39-45, 63-81, 135-149, 177-189, 199-211, 219-231, 243-251, 263-275, 285-297, 375-395, 401-409, 431-473, 486-488.

Lindberg, David C. 2007. Second Edition. The Beginnings of Western Science: The European Scientific Tradition in Philosophical, Religious, and Institutional Context, Prehistory to A.D. 1450. Chicago; London: The University of Chicago Press.

Listfeldt, H. G. 1974. Some Concepts of Matter of Avicenna, Averroes, St. Thomas and Heisenberg. Aquinas 18: 310-321.

Lizzini, Olga. 2011. Fluxus (fayd). Indagine sui fondamenti della metafisica e della fisica di Avicenna (Ibn Sina, m. 427/1037). Bari: Edizioni di Pagina.

-- . 2009. Il nulla, l’inesistente, la cosa: note intorno alla terminologia e alla dottrina del nulla e della creazione dal nulla nel pensiero islamico. In Discussioni sul nulla tra medioevo ed età moderna, a cura di M. Lenzi e A. Maierù. Firenze: Leo S. Olschki editore, 63-104.

-- . 2008. Le cosmologie di Alfarabi e di Avicenna. In Cosmogonie e cosmologie nel Medioevo, Atti del XV Colloquio della SISPM. Società Italiana per lo Studio del Pensiero Medievale (Catania, 22-24 settembre 2006), a cura di C. Martello, C. Militello, and Andrea Vella (Textes et Etudes du Moyen Age, 46), FIDEM, Louvain-la-Neuve, 195-214.

-- . 2004. The Relation between Form and Matter: Some Brief Observations on the ‘Homology Argument’ (Ilahiyat, II.4) and the Deduction of fluxus. In Interpreting Ibn Sina: Science and Philosophy in Medieval Islam. Proceedings of the Second Conference of the Ibn Sina Study Group, edited by J. McGinnis. Leiden; Boston: Brill, 175-189.

Lloyd, G. E. R. 1978. Saving the Appearances. The Classical Quarterly 28: 202-223.

Luna, Concetta. 1989-. “La Métaphysique. Tradition grecque. Les commentaires grecs à la Métaphysique” In Dictionnaire des philosophes antiques. Paris: Éditions du Centre national de la recherche scientifique. Supplément, 249-258.

Madkour, Ibrahim. 1934. La place dal-Farabi dans l’école philosophique musulmane. Paris: Adrien-Maisonneuve.

Mahdi, Muhsin. 2001. Alfarabi and the Foundation of Islamic Political Philosophy. Chicago; London: University of Chicago Press.

- . 1990a. Al-Fârâbï’s Imperfect State. Journal of the American Oriental Society 110/4: 691-726.

- . 1990b. Philosophical Literature. In Religion, Learning, and Science in the Abbasid Period, edited by M. J. L. Young, J. D. Latham, and R. B. Serjeant. Cambridge; New York: Cambridge University Press, 76-103.

- . 1967. Alfarabi against Philoponus. Journal of Near Eastern Studies 26/4: 233-260.

Mallet, Dominique. 1996. Kalam et dialectique dans le commentaire des Topiques d’Alfarabi. Bulletin d’études orientales 48: 165-182.

- . 1990. Le Kitab al-tahlil d’Alfarabi. Arabic Sciences and Philosophy 4: 317-336.

--- . “Zaman.” Encyclopaedia of Islam, Second Edition. Leiden: Brill, 1960-.

Marmura, M. E. 1990. The Fortuna of the Posterior Analytics in the Arabic Middle Ages. In Knowledge and the Sciences in Medieval Philosophy, edited by M. Asztalos, J. E. Murdoch, and I. Niiniluoto. Helsinki: Yliopistopaino, vol. 1, 85-104.

- . 1962. Some Aspects of Avicenna’s Theory of God’s Knowledge of Particulars. Journal of the American Oriental Society 82/3: 299-312.

Maróth, Miklós. 1995. The Ten Intellects Cosmology and its Origin. The Arabist 13-14: 103-113.

- . 1994. Die Araber und die antike Wissenschaftstheorie. Leiden; New York; Koln: Brill.

Marquet, Yves. 1990. Descente et remontée chez Fârâbï: une filière dédoublée. In Acts of the International Symposium on Ibn Turk, Khwârezmî, Fârâbî, Beyrûnî, and Ibn Sînâ. Ankara: Atatürk Supreme Council for Culture, Language and History, 175-185.

- . 1987. La procession des âmes chez Fârâbï, ou le dédoublement de l’itinéraire. Journal asiatique 275: 65-78.

Martin, A. 1989-. “La métaphysique. Tradition syriaque et arabe.” In Dictionnaire des philosophes antiques. Paris: Éditions du Centre national de la recherche scientifique, vol. 1, 528-534.

Martini Bonadeo, Cecilia. 1989. “La métaphysique. Tradition syriaque et arabe. Mise à jour bibliographique.” In Dictionnaire des philosophes antiques. Paris: Éditions du Centre national de la recherche scientifique, Supplément, 259-264.

McGinnis, Jon. 2008. Avicenna’s Naturalized Epistemology and Scientific Method. In The Unity of Science in the Arabic Tradition: Science, Logic, Epistemology and Their Interactions, edited by S. Rahman, T. Street, and H. Tahiri. Dordrecht: Springer, 129-153.

- . 2006. Positioning Heaven: The Infidelity of a Faithful Aristotelian. Phronesis 51/2: 140-161.

- . 2003. Scientific Methodologies in Medieval Islam: Induction and Experimen­tation in the Philosophy of Ibn Sïnâ. Journal of the History of Philosophy 41/3: 307-327.

McGinnis, Jon, and David C. Reisman. 2007. Classical Arabic Philosophy: An Anthology of Sources. Translated with introduction, notes and glossary by J. McGinnis and

D.    C. Reisman. Indianapolis, Cambridge: Hackett Publishing Company.

McKirahan Jr., Richard D. 1978. Aristotle’s Subordinate Sciences. The British Journal for the History of Science 11/3: 197-220.

Mehren, A. F. 1885. Vues dAvicenne sur lastrologie et sur le rapport de la responsabilité humaine avec le destin. Louvain: C. Peeters.

Menn, Stephen. 2008. Al-Fârâbï’s Kitab al-hurüf and His Analysis of the Senses of Being. Arabic Sciences and Philosophy 18: 59-97.

Merlan, P. 1946. Aristotle’s Unmoved Movers. Traditio 4: 1-30.

Michot, Yahya (=Jean R.). 2006. Avicenne: Réfutation de l’astrologie. Beirut: Albouraq.

-- . 1986. La destinée de l’homme selon Avicenne: le retour à Dieu (ma ad) et l’imagination. Lovanii: Aedibus Peeters.

-- . 1982. Tables de correspondance des ‘Taliqât’ dal-Fârâbi, des ‘Taliqat’ d’Avicenne et du ‘Liber aphorismorum’ d’Andrea Alpago. MIDEO 15: 231-250.

Moraux, Paul. 1963. “Quinta essentia.” In Pauly-Wissowa-Kroll, Bd 24/1: 1171-1263.

Morelon, Régis. 2004. Une proposition de lecture de l’histoire de l’astronomie arabe. In De Zénon d’Elée á Poincaré: recueil d’études en hommage á Roshdi Rashed, edited by R. Morelon and A. Hasnawi. Louvain: Peeters, 237-251.

-- . 1999. Astronomie « physique » et astronomie « mathématique » dans l’astronomie précopernicienne. In Les doctrines de la science de l’antiquité à l’âge classique, edited by R. Rashed and J. Biard. Leuven: Peeters, 105-131.

-- . 1996a. General Survey of Arabic Astronomy. In Encyclopedia of the History of Arabic Science, 3 vols., edited by R. Rashed, vol. 1, 1-20. London: Routledge.

-- . 1996b. Eastern Arabic Astronomy between the Eighth and the Eleventh Centuries. In Encyclopedia of the History of Arabic Science, 3 vols., edited by R. Rashed. London: Routledge, vol. 1, 20-58.

-- . 1994. Thabit b. Qurra and Arab Astronomy in the 9th Century. Arabic Sciences and Philosophy 4/1: 111-141.

-- . 1993. Le traîté I du Livre des Hypothèses de Ptolémée. MIDEO 21: 7-87.

Morrison, Robert. 2007. Islam and Science: The Intellectual Career of Nizam al-Din al-Nisaburi. London; New York: Routledge.

-- . 2005. Qutb al-Din al-Shirazi’s Hypotheses for Celestial Motion. Journal for the History of Arabic Science 13/1-2: 21-141.

Mueller, Ian. 2006. Physics and Astronomy: Aristotle’s Physics II.2.193b22-194a12. Arabic Sciences and Philosophy 16/2: 175-207.

Murschel, Andrea. 1995. The Structure and Function of Ptolemy’s Physical Hypotheses of Planetary Motion. Journal of the History of Astronomy, 26/1: 33-61.

Najjar, Fauzi M. 2004. Al-Farabi’s Harmonization of Plato’s and Aristotle’s Philosophies. The Muslim World 94: 29-44.

Nallino, C. A. 1944. “Astronomi.” In Raccolta di scritti editi e inediti. Vol. 5. Astrologia, astronomia, geografía. Roma: Istituto per l’oriente.

Netton, I. R. “ Unsur.” Encyclopaedia of Islam, Second Edition. Leiden: Brill, 1960-.

-- . 1992. Al-Farabi and His School. London; New York: Routledge.

-- . 1989. Allah Transcendent: Studies in the Structure and Semiotics of Islamic Philosophy, Theology, and Cosmology. London; New York: Routledge.

Neuwirth, Angelika. 2001-. “Cosmology.” In The Encyclopedia of the Qur’an. J. D. McAuliffe, general editor. Leiden: Brill.

-- . 1976. ‘Abd al-Latif al-Bagdadis Bearbeitung von Buch Lambda der aristotelischen Metaphysik. Wiesbaden: Steiner.

Obrist, Barbara. 2004. La cosmologie médiévale: textes et images. Firenze: SISMEL/ Edizioni del Galluzzo.

O’Meara, Dominic. 2003. Platonopolis: Platonic Political Philosophy in Late Antiquity. Oxford: Clarendon; New York: Oxford University Press.

Opsomer, Jan. 2001. Who in the Heavens is the Demiurge? Proclus’ Exegesis of Plato Tim. 28C3-5. The Ancient World 32/1: 52-70.

-- . 2000. Proclus on Demiurgy and Procession in the Timaeus. In Reason and Necessity: Essays on Plato’s Timaeus, edited by M. R. Wright. London: Duckworth; Swansea: Classical Press of Wales, 113-145.

Owens, Joseph. 1950. The Reality of the Aristotelian Separate Movers. The Review of Metaphysics 3/9: 319-337.

Parens, Joshua. 2006. An Islamic Philosophy of Virtuous Religions: Introducing Alfarabi. New York: SUNY.

Pearson, Carl William. 1999. “Scripture as Cosmology: Natural Philosophical Debate in John Philoponus’ Alexandria.” Ph.D. diss., Harvard University.

Pedersen, Olaf. 1974. A Survey of the Almagest. Odense: University Press.

Périer, Augustin. 1920a. Yahya ben ‘Adi: un philosophe arabe chrétien du Xe siècle. Paris: J. Gabalda.

-- . 1920b. Petits traités apologétiques de Yahyâ ben Adî. Paris: Gabalda.

Peters, F. E. 1968. Aristoteles arabus. Leiden: Brill.

Pines, Shlomo. 1997 [1936]. Studies in Islamic Atomism. Jerusalem: The Magnes Press, The Hebrew University.

-- . 1987. Some Distinctive Metaphysical Conceptions in Themistius’ Commentary on Book Lambda and their Place in the History of Philosophy. In Aristoteles Werk und Wirkung Paul Moraux Gewidmet, Zweiter Band, herausgegeben von J. Wiesner. Berlin; New York: De Gruyter, 177-204. Reprinted in The Collected Works of Shlomo Pines, edited by S. Stroumsa. Jerusalem: The Magnes Press, The Hebrew University, 1996, vol. 3, 267-295.

-- . 1979. The Limitations of Human Knowledge According to al-Farabi, Ibn Bajja, and Maimonides. In Studies in Medieval Jewish History and Literature, edited by I. Twersky. Cambridge, Mass.; London: Harvard University Press, 84-109.

-- . 1972. An Arabic Summary of a Lost Work of John Philoponus. Israel Oriental Studies 2: 320-359. Reprinted in The Collected Works of Shlomo Pines. Jerusalem: The Magnes Press, The Hebrew University, 1986, vol. 2, 294-329.

-- . 1964. The Semantic Distinction between the Terms Astronomy and Astrology according to al-Bïrünï. Isis 55: 343-349. Reprinted in The Collected Works of Shlomo Pines. Jerusalem: The Magnes Press, The Hebrew University, 1986, vol. 2, 387-394.

Pingree, D. E. 1990. Astrology. In Religion, Learning, and Science in the Abbasid Period, edited by M. J. L. Young, J. D. Latham, and R. B. Serjeant. Cambridge; New York: Cambridge University Press, 290-301.

-- . 1973. The Greek Influence on Early Islamic Mathematical Astronomy. Journal of the American Oriental Society 93/1: 32-43.

Pingree, D. E., and S. N. Haq. “Tabïa.” Encyclopaedia of Islam, Second Edition. Leiden: Brill, 1960-.

Platti, E. 1983. Yahya ibn ‘Adi: théologien chrétien et philosophe arabe: sa théologie de l’incarnation. Leuven: Departement Oriëntalistiek.

-- . 1981-1982. La grande polémique antinestorienne de Yahya b. Adi. Lovanii:

E.    Peeters.

Ragep, F. J. 2010. Islamic Reactions to Ptolemy’s Imprecisions. In Ptolemy in Perspective, edited by A. Jones. New York: Springer-Verlag, 121-134.

-- . 2001. Freeing Astronomy from Philosophy: An Aspect of Islamic Influence on Science. Osiris 16: 49-71.

-- . 1993. Nasir al-Din al-Tusi’s Memoir on Astronomy (al-Tadhkira fi ‘ilm al-Haya).

2 vols. New York: Springer-Verlag.

--- . 1990. Duhem, the Arabs, and the History of Cosmology. Synthèse 83: 201-214.

Ragep, F. J., and S. P. Ragep. 2004. The Astronomical and Cosmological Works of Ibn Sïnâ: Some Preliminary Remarks. In Sciences, techniques et instruments dans le monde iranien (Xe-XIXe siècle), edited by N. Pourjavady and Z. Vesel. Téhéran: Presses Universitaires d’Iran, 3-17.

Ragep, Sally. 2007. “Ibn Sïnâ.” In The Biographical Encyclopedia of Astronomers, edited by T Hockey et al. New York: Springer.

Rahman, Fazlur. 1958. Prophecy in Islam: Philosophy and Orthodoxy. London: George Allen & Unwin Ltd.

Rashed, Marwan. 2009. On the Authorship of the Treatise On the Harmonization of the Opinions of the Two Sages Attributed to al-Fârâbï. Arabic Sciences and Philosophy 19: 43-82.

-- . 2008. Al-Fârâbï’s Lost Treatise On Changing Beings and the Possibility of a Demonstration of the Eternity of the World. Arabic Sciences and Philosophy 18: 19-58.

- . 2005. “Natural Philosophy.” In The Cambridge Companion to Arabic Philosophy, edited by P. Adamson and R. C. Taylor. Cambridge: University Press, 287-308.

- . 2004. The Problem of the Composition of the Heavens (529-1610): A New Fragment of Philoponus and its Readers. In Philosophy, Science and Exegesis in Greek, Arabic, and Latin Commentaries, 2 vols., edited by P. Adamson, H. Baltussen, and M. W. F. Stone. London: Institute of Classical Studies, School of Advanced Study, University of London, vol. 2, 35-58.

Rashed, Roshdi. 2007. The Celestial Kinematics of Ibn al-Haytham. Arabic Sciences and Philosophy 17/1: 7-55.

- . 2001. Al-Qühï: From Meteorology to Astronomy, Arabic Sciences and Philosophy 11/2: 157-204.

- . 1991. L’analyse et la synthèse selon Ibn al-Haytham. In Mathématique et philoso­phie de lAntiquité à l’Âge Classique, edited by R. Rashed. Paris: Éditions du C.N.R.S, 131-149.

Rashed, Roshdi, and Régis Morelon. “Thabit b. Kurra, Abu l-Hasan b. Zahrün al-Harranï.” Encyclopaedia of Islam, Second Edition. Leiden: Brill, 1960-.

Reisman, David C. 2005. Al-I'arabï and the Philosophical Curriculum. In The Cambridge Companion to Arabic Philosophy, edited by P. Adamson and R. C. Taylor. Cambridge: University Press, 52-72.

Rescher, Nicholas. 1964. Al-Kindi: An Annotated Bibliography. [Pittsburgh, Pa.]: University of Pittsburgh Press.

- . 1963. Al-Farabï on Logical Tradition. Journal of the history of ideas 24/1: 127-132.

- . 1962. Al-Farabi: An Annotated Bibliography. [Pittsburgh]: Pittsburgh University Press.

Rosemann, Philipp W 1996. Omne Agens Agit Sibi Simile: A “Repetition” of Scholastic Metaphysics. Leuven: University Press.

Rosenfeld, Boris A., and Ekmeleddin Ihsanoglu. 2003. Mathematicians, Astronomers, and Other Scholars of Islamic Civilization and their Works (7th-19th c.). Istanbul: Research Centre for Islamic History, Art, and Culture.

Rosenthal, Franz. 1975. The Classical Heritage in Islam. Translated from the German by E. and J. Marmorstein. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

- . 1956. Al-Kindï and Ptolemy. In Studi orientalistici in onore di Giorgio Levi della Vida, 2 vols. Rome: Istituto per l’Oriente, vol. 2, 436-456.

Rowson, Everett K. 1990. The Philosopher as Littérateur: Al-Tawhïdï and his Predecessors. ZGAW 6: 50-93.

- . 1988. A Muslim Philosopher on the Soul and its Fate: Al-Amiri’s Kitab al-amad ala l-abad. New Haven, Connecticut: American Oriental Society.

Rudavsky, Tamar. 2000. Time Matters: Time, Creation, and Cosmology in Medieval Jewish Philosophy. Albany, N.Y.: State University of New York Press.

Rudolph, Ulrich. 2008. Reflections on al-Farabï’s Mabadi ara' ahl al-madina al-fadila. In In the Age of al-Farabi: Arabic Philosophy in the Fourth/Tenth Century, edited by P. Adamson. London: The Warburg Institute/ Turin: Nino Aragno Editore, 1-15.

- . 2007. Al-Farabï und die Mutazila. In A Common Rationality: Mutazilism in Islam and Judaism. Edited by C. Adang, S. Schmidtke, and D. Sklare. Würzburg: Ergon in Kommission, 59-80.

- . 1989. Die Doxographie des Pseudo-Ammonios: Ein Beitrag zur Neuplatonischen Überlieferung im Islam. Stuttgart: Deutsche Morgenlandische Gesellschaft; Stuttgart:

F.   Steiner Wiesbaden.

Sabra, A. I. 2000. Reply to Saliba. Perspectives on Science 8: 342-345.

- . 1998. Configuring the Universe: Aporetic, Problem Solving, and Kinematic Modeling as Themes of Arabic Astronomy. Perspectives on Science 6: 288-330.

--- . 1996. Situating Arabic Science: Locality versus Essence. Isis 87: 654-670.

-- . 1994. Philosophy and Science in Medieval Islamic Theology: The Evidence of the Fourteenth Century. Zeitschrift für Geschichte der arabischen-islamischen Wissenschaften 9: 1-42.

-- . 1987. The Appropriation and Subsequent Naturalization of Greek Science in Medieval Islam: A Preliminary Statement. History of Science 25: 223-243.

-- . 1984. The Andalusian Revolt against Ptolemaic Astronomy: Averroes and al-Bitrüjï. In Transformation and Tradition in the Sciences, edited by E. Mendelsohn. Cambridge [Cambridgeshire]; New York: Cambridge University Press, 133-155.

--- . 1971. The Astronomical Origin of Ibn al-Haytham’s Concept of Experiment.

Actes du XIIe Congrès International d’Histoire des Sciences, T.III A, Paris 1968. Paris: Albert Blanchard. (Reprinted in A. I. Sabra, Optics, Astronomy, and Logic in Arabic Science and Philosophy, Aldershot, Hants: Variorum, 1994).

Saliba, George. 2007. Islamic Science and the Making of the European Renaissance. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.

-- . 2004. Aristotelian Cosmology and Arabic Astronomy. In De Zénon d’Elée á Poincaré: recueil d’études en hommage á Roshdi Rashed, edited by R. Morelon and Ahmad Hasnawi. Louvain: Peeters, 251-269.

-- . 2000. Arabic versus Greek Astronomy: A Debate over the Foundations of Science. Perspectives on Science 8: 328-341.

-- . 1999. Astronomy and Astrology in Medieval Arabic Thought. In Les doctrines de la science de l’antiquité à l’âge classique, edited by R. Rashed and J. Biard. Leuven: Peeters, 131-165.

-- . 1994a. Astrology/Astronomy, Islamic. In A History of Arabic Astronomy: Planetary Theories during the Golden Age of Islam. New York; London: New York University Press, 66-85.

-- . 1994b. Early Arabic Critique of Ptolemaic Cosmology: A Ninth-Century Text on the Motion of the Celestial Spheres. Journal of the History of Astronomy 25: 115-141.

-- . 1991. The Astronomical Tradition of Maragha: A Historical Survey and Prospects for Future Research. Arabic Sciences and Philosophy 1/1: 67-101.

Sambursky, Samuel. 1962. The Physical World of Late Antiquity. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

Sayili, Aydin. 1981 [1960]. The Observatory in Islam and its Place in the General History of the Observatory. New York: Arno Press.

Shroeder, F. M. 1989. Two Greek Aristotelian Commentators on the Intellect: The De intellectu attributed to Alexander of Aphrodisias and Themistius’ Paraphrase of Aristotle De anima 3.4-8. Introduction, translation, commentary, and notes by F. M. Schroeder and R. B. Todd. Toronto: Pontifical Institute of Mediaeval Studies.

Serra, Giuseppe. 1993. Due studi arabo-latini. Medioevo: rivista di storia della filosofía 19: 27-66.

Sezgin, Fuat. 1967-. Geschichte des arabischen Schrifttums. 12 vols. Leiden: Brill.

Sharples, Robert W 2003. Pseudo-Alexander on Aristotle, Metaphysics A. In Alessandro di Afrodisia e la “Metafisica” di Aristotele, edited by G. Movia. Milano: Vita e pensiero, 187-219.

Siorvanes, Lucas. 1996. Proclus: Neo-Platonic Philosophy and Science. New Haven: Yale University Press.

-- . 1987. “Proclus on the Elements and the Celestial Bodies.” Ph.D. diss., University of London.

Sorabji, Richard (ed.). 2005. The Philosophy of the Commentators, 200-600 AD: A Sourcebook, 3 vols. Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press.

-- . 1988. Matter, Space, and Motion: Theories in Antiquity and their Sequel. London: Duckworth.

Steel, Carlos. 2010. Proclus. In The Cambridge History of Philosophy in Late Antiquity, 2 vols., edited by L. P. Gerson. Cambridge: University Press, vol. 2, 630-654.

Steinschneider, Moritz. 1966 [1869]. Al-Farabi (Alpharabius): des arabischen Philosophe» Leben und Schriften. Amsterdam: Philo Pres.

Stone, Abraham D. 2001. Simplicius and Ibn Sinñ on the Essential Corporeity of Material Substance. In Aspects of Ibn Sina, edited by R. Wisnovsky. Princeton, NJ: Markus Wiener, 73-130.

Street, Tony. 2004. “Arabic Logic.” In Handbook of the History of Logic, 8 vols., edited by D. M. Gabbay and J. Woods. Amsterdam: Elsevier, vol. 1, 523-597.

Strohmaier, Gotthard. 1996. The Nature of the Supralunar World: From Anaxagoras to ibn al-Haytham. Republished in Von Demokrit bis Dante. Hildesheim; Zürich; New York: Georg Olms Verlag, 30-34.

Stroumsa, Sarah. 1993. Al-Fârâbï and Maimonides on Medicine as a Science. Arabic Sciences and Philosophy 3: 235-249.

-- . 1991. Al-Fârâbï and Maimonides on the Christian Philosophical Tradition: A Re-Evaluation. Der Islam 68: 263-288.

Taub, Liba. 1993. Ptolemy’s Universe. Chicago: Open Court.

Taylor, Richard C. 1992. A Critical Analysis of the Structure of the Kalam fi mahd al- khair (Liber de causis). In Neoplatonism and Islamic Thought, edited by P. Morewedge. Albany: SUNY, 11-40.

-- . 1986. The Kalam fi mahd al-khair in the Islamic Philosophical Milieu. In Pseudo­Aristotle in the Middle Ages, edited by J. Kraye, W F. Ryan and C. B. Schmitt. London: Warburg Institute, University of London, 37-52.

-- . 1981. The liber de causis (Kalam fi mahd al-khair): A Study of Medieval Neoplatonism. Toronto: School of Graduate Studies, University of Toronto.

Thillet, Pierre. 2003. Remarques sur le livre Lambda de la « Métaphysique ». Recherches de théologie et philosophie médiévale 70/2: 361-401.

Thillet, Pierre, and Saleh Oudaimah. 2001-2002. Proclus arabe, un nouveau Liber de causis? Bulletin d’études orientales 53-54: 293-369.

Todd, Robert B. 1989-. “Geminos.” In Dictionnaire des philosophes antiques. Paris: Éditions du Centre national de la recherche scientifique, vol. 3, 472-477.

Trouillard, Jean. 1967-68. La genèse de l’hylémorphisme selon Proclos. Dialogue: Revue canadienne de philosophie 6: 1-17.

Türker, Mubahat. 1968. L’importance et l’origine de la métaphysique chez al-Fârâbï. Ankara Universitesi Dil ve Tarih-Copgrafya Fakültesi Dergisi 20/1-2: 55-64. Ankara.

Vajda, Georges. 1965. A propos d’une citation non identifiée d’al-Fârâbï dans le « Guide des Egarés ». Journal asiatique 253: 43-50.

Vallat, Philippe. Forthcoming. L’intellect selon Fârâbï: la transformation du savoir en être.

-- . Forthcoming. L’intellect et les intellects selon Farabi. Belles Lettres en annexe à la traduction de la Risala fi l-‘aql de Farabi.

-- . 2011 (forthcoming). Al-Farabi’s arguments for the Eternity of the World. In Interpreting the Bible and Aristotle - The Alexandrian Commentary Tradition between Rome and Baghdad, ed. by J. Watt and J. Lossl. Ashgate.

-- . 2008. Du possible au nécessaire: La connaissance de l’universel chez Farabi. Documenti e Studi sulla tradizione filosofica medievale 19: 89-121.

-- . 2004. Farabi et l’école d’Alexandrie: des prémisses de la connaissance à la philoso­phie politique. Paris: Vrin.

Varisco, D. M. 2000. “Islamic Folk Astronomy.” In Astronomy across Cultures: The History of Non-Western Astronomy, edited by H. Selin. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

--- . 1992. The Origin of the anwa in Arab Tradition. Studia Islamica 74: 5-28.

--- . “Anwâ.” Encyclopaedia of Islam, Third Edition. Leiden: Brill, 2007-.

Vaulx d’Arcy, Guillaume de. 2010. La naqla: étude du concept de transfert dans l’œuvre d’al-Fârâbï. Arabic Sciences and Philosophy 20: 125-176.

Verrycken, Koenraad. 1990a. The Metaphysics of Ammonius Son of Hermeias. In Aristotle Transformed, edited by R. Sorabji. Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 199-233.

-- . 1990b. The Development of Philoponus’ Thought and its Chronology. In Aristotle transformed, edited by R. Sorabji. Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 233-74.

Wakelnig, Elvira. 2006. Feder, Tafel, Mensch: Al-Amiri’s Kitab al-Fusul fi l-Maalim al-ilahiya und die arabische Proklos-Rezeption im 10. Jh. Leiden; Boston: Brill.

Walzer, Richard. 1974. Aristotle’s Active Intellect NOUS POIETIKOS in Greek and Early Islamic Philosophy. In Plotino e il neoplatonismo in oriente e in occidente: [atti del convegno] Roma, 5-9 ottobre 1970. Academia Nazionale dei Lincei, 423-436.

--- . 1957. New Studies on al-Kindi. Oriens 10: 203-232.

--- . 1950. The Rise of Islamic Philosophy. Oriens 3: 1-19.

Watt, John W 2008. Al-Farabi and the History of the Syriac Organon. In Malphono w-Rabo d-Malphone: Studies in Honor of Sebastian P. Brock, edited by A. Kiraz. Gorgias Press, 751-778. Reprinted in Analecta Gorgiana 129, Gorgias Press, 2009.

-- . 2007. Christianity in the Renaissance of Islam. Abu Bishr Matta, al-Farabi, and Yahya ibn Adi. In Christians and Muslims in Dialogue in the Islamic Orient of the Middle Ages. Christlich-muslimische Gesprache im Mittelalter, edited by M. Tamcke. Beiruter Texte und Studien 117. Beirut: Orient-Institut/Würzburg: Ergon Verlag, 99-112.

Wiesner, Hillary Suzanne. 1993. “The Cosmology of al-Kindi.” Ph.D. diss., Harvard University.

Wilberding, James. 2006. Plotinus’ Cosmology: A Study of Ennead II.1 (40). Text, Translation, and Commentary. Oxford: University Press.

Wildberg, Christian. 1988. John Philoponus’ Criticism of Aristotle’s Theory of Aether. Berlin; New York: Walter de Gruyter.

Wisnovsky, Robert. “Yahya al-Nahwi.” Encyclopaedia of Islam, Second Edition. Leiden: Brill, 1960-.

-- . 2005. Avicenna and the Avicennian Tradition. In The Cambridge Companion to Arabic Philosophy, edited by P. Adamson and R. C. Taylor. Cambridge University Press, 92-137.

-- . 2003a. Towards a History of Avicenna’s Distinction between Immanent and Transcendent Causes. In Before and After Avicenna, edited by D. Reisman and A. H. Al-Rahim. Leiden: Brill, 49-68.

-- . 2003b. Avicenna’s Metaphysics in Context. Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press.

-- . 2002. Final and Efficient Causality in Avicenna’s Cosmology and Theology. Quaestio 2: 97-123.

Wolfson, H. A. 1976. The Philosophy of the Kalam. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

-- . 1970. The Identification of ex nihilo with Emanation in Gregory of Nyssa. Harvard Theological Review 63: 53-60.

-- . 1966. Plato’s Pre-existent Matter in Patristic Philosophy. In The Classical Tradition: Literary and Historical Studies in Honor of Harry Caplan, edited by Luitpold Wallach, 409-420. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

-- . 1962. The Problem of the Souls of the Spheres from the Byzantine Commentaries on Aristotle through the Arabs and St. Thomas to Kepler. Dumbarton Oaks Papers 16: 65-93.

-- . 1959. The Meaning of ex nihilo in Isaac Israeli. The Jewish Quarterly Review 50/1: 1-12.

-- . 1958. The Plurality of Immovable Movers in Aristotle and Averroes. Harvard Studies in Classical Philology 63: 233-253.

-- . 1947-48. Arabic and Hebrew Terms for Matter and Element with Especial Reference to Saadia. The Jewish Quaterly Review 38: 47-61.

-- . 1929. Crescas’ Critique of Aristotle: Problems of Aristotle’s Physics in Jewish and Arabic Philosophy. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

Wright, L. 1973. The Astronomy of Eudoxus: Geometry or Physics? Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 4: 165-172.

Wright, M. R. 1995. Cosmology in Antiquity. London; New York: Routledge.

Yousef, Mohamed Haj. 2008. Ibn ‘Arabi: Time and Cosmology. London; New York: Routledge.

Zimmermann, Fritz. 1994. Proclus Arabus Rides Again. Arabic Sciences and Philosophy 4: 9-51.

-- . 1986. The Origins of the So-Called Theology of Aristotle. In Pseudo-Aristotle in the Middle Ages: The Theology and Other Texts, edited by Jill Kraye, W F. Ryan, and C. B Schmitt, 110-241. London: The Warburg Institute, University of London.

Zonta, Mauro. 1995. The Reception of al-Farabi’s and Ibn Sina’s Classifications of the Mathematical and Natural Sciences in the Hebrew Medieval Philosophical Literature. Medieval Encounters 1/3: 358-382.

-- . 1994. Hebraica veritas: Temistio, parafrasi del De coelo. Athenaeum: Studi peri­odici di letteratura e storia dell’ antichita, NS LXXXII: 403-428.


Abu l-Hudhayl 47

Abu l-Qasim al-Balkhï 14, 29

Abu Mashar 47, 50,140, 161 accident (‘arad) 79 n. 171, 256, 257 n.

140, 277, 317-319, 339, 390

actual, in actuality (bi-l-fi‘l) 129 n. 41, 139-141, 173-174, 268, 346, 386-387, 389, 393, 397-401

Adrastus of Aphrodisias 155 aether 20, 38, 53-54, 66, 68, 70, 71 n.

151, 74, 119, 134, 203, 205-208, 213, 216-222, 224-225, 229, 231, 234-237, 247-255, 268-269, 275 n. 178, 283-284, 286-287, 300, 308, 327-328, 341-343, 348, 352, 354 n. 57, 370, 374, 375 n. 101, 385

aim, skopós 248, 257, 261, 263, 335, 371, 373 n. 96, 374

Alcinous 155

Aleppo 47, 323 n. 296

Alexander of Aphrodisias 4-5, 11 n. 2, 13, 15, 20-21, 122 n. 18, 123, 128-130, 134-137, 140-160, 162, 167, 177 n. 186, 201, 214-215, 222-228, 231, 237, 253 n. 134, 272 n. 171, 305-307, 311 n. 269, 314, 334, 336, 340, 342-343, 348, 351 n. 53, 353, 355 n. 58, 379

Alexandria, Alexandrian 19, 56-57, 158, 216 n. 34, 222, 256-257, 261, 263, 302, 326, 331

Ammonius, son of Hermeias 20, 120, 158-161, 180, 185-186, 218-219, 232, 237, 240, 245, 249, 334, 380

analogy 84, 94-112, 184 n. 204, 208 n.

12, 209, 310 n. 265, 318, 360, 365, 367, 380

analysis (tahlïl) 104-105, 108

Aristotle 1,' 3-5, 11, 14-22, 30-31, 36-38, 41, 50-59, 61 n. 125, 62, 65-74, 77-80, 85-87, 90, 92, 96 n. 214, 97, 99, 102-107, 109, 112, 116 n. 4, 118 n. 12, 119-120, 122-129, 133-134, 136-137, 139, 145-166, 173-174, 178-182, 185­191, 195 n. 226, 201, 203, 205-208, 214-238, 241, 243-266, 269 n. 163, 271-273, 275, 277-278, 280, 283-286, 289 n. 210, 291-292, 300-302, 307, 313-314, 316 n. 277, 322, 325 n. 302,

327, 329-330, 333-334, 336-337, 340-342, 345-364, 366 n. 85, 367, 372, 375, 385, 388, 392, 394-395, 399, 401 al-Ashari 29, 47, 319 astrology 11 n. 1, 30, 42, 44-51, 56-57, 61-62, 117, 161

astronomy 2-4, 7-8, 11 n. 1, 12, 23-26, 30-31, 34-45, 51-73, 76-86, 88, 93, 97, 111-112, 116 n. 3, 120, 123, 126-127, 159, 167 n. 155, 334-339, 344 n. 30, 360 n. 68, 369, 371-376, 380-381

atomism 29, 184 n. 205, 213, 229-232

al-Baghdadi, Abd al-Latif 45 n. 74 al-Baghdadi, Abu l-Barakat 213, 229

n. 72

al-Baghdadi, Abu Ishaq Ibrahim ibn Abd Allah 46 n. 77

Baghdad 2-4, 13-15, 18-19, 21, 26, 30-33, 46-47, 63, 98, 112, 177 n. 186, 182, 215, 222, 227-228, 239 n. 91, 261-262, 266, 269, 271-272, 275-278, 282, 286, 293, 303, 321-324, 326-327, 329, 332, 334, 379, 381 n. 1

al-Battani 35, 63

al-Bitruji 123, 132

causation, causality 1, 4, 6, 8, 15, 17, 22, 29, 34, 37, 50, 51 n. 92, 69, 82, 108 n. 246, 136, 142 n. 86, 143, 160-164, 167, 182-183, 186, 188-189, 192-193, 196-203, 211-212, 222, 228, 235, 237-238, 246-247, 249, 258, 266 n. 153, 269, 273, 276 n. 180, 278 n. 186, 284, 286-311, 314, 323, 325, 326-333, 339, 345 n. 35, 362, 368, 375-376, 380-381, 383-384, 389-390, 393, 399 efficient 51, 126, 137, 143, 160-164, 166, 172, 186, 188, 193, 198-202, 232, 237-238, 243 n. 101, 245 n. 107, 249 n. 121, 253 n. 133,

264- 265, 269, 272, 284-291, 294, 295 n. 226, 297 n. 232, 300-301, 303-304, 307, 314, 325, 330-331, 386, 388, 399

final 137, 160, 162, 166, 189, 198-202, 237, 239, 249 n. 121, 264, 272,


284-286, 288-289, 297 n. 232, 303-304, 314, 325, 327, 330-331,

351- 352, 355, 359, 368, 375,

398- 399

formal 200 n. 236, 285, 310 n. 266, 374, 375 n. 101

‘illah 49, 184 n. 203, 245 n. 107, 267, 351 n. 53, 353

and intellection 138-139, 162-174, 298-301, 303, 348-355

and mediation (tawassut) 138, 143, 146, 178 n. 194, 182, 198 n. 234, 247, 293-297, 304, 388

lazima ‘an 288, 290, 293-295 material 234, 305, 310 n. 266, 374 sabab 49, 68-69, 77, 80-82, 90, 180, 184 n. 203, 206-207, 278 n. 186, 284, 285 n. 202, 287-288, 294, 316, 322, 346 n. 44, 350, 369, 387 n. 20, 388 n. 21, 392 n. 37

celestial body (jism samawi) 20, 22, 27, 29, 34, 39, 48-56, 61, 67-76, 82-83, 90, 94, 97, 103, 106-108, 115-142, 208, 214, 218, 226, 232, 288, 304, 306, 309, 339, 344, 348, 350-353, 356-357, 367-368, 370, 376, 395, 399

celestial harmony (Pythagorean) 11 chance (ittifaq) 49, 253, 273

composite, composed (murakkab) 54 n. 100, 119, 131, 134-135, 141, 169, 183,

194-      195, 207, 209, 211, 214, 216-217, 219, 224, 229, 244, 254, 275 n. 178, 305 n. 249, 306-307, 311, 384-386

creation 3, 6, 8, 15, 22, 29-30, 32-34, 88, 90, 160-164, 180, 182, 192 n. 219, 203, 211, 214, 229-230, 235-284, 286-287, 290, 291 n. 215, 293 n. 224, 296-307, 314-333, 337 n. 11, 340, 379-380,

387-      389

all at once (dafatan) 180, 242, 244-245, 254, 270, 277, 281 n. 194, 305

al-bari' 241, 243, 267, 270, 272, 274 demiurge and demiurges 34, 230, 243,

265,    272, 298-299, 302-303, 380

eternal creation 238, 242, 273, 277-281

ex nihilo 86, 180, 238, 245, 247, 254,

266,    269-270, 274 n. 177, 278 n. 186, 291 n. 215, 304, 324, 327

hadatha ‘an 258, 260, 262, 291 n. 215 ibda 241-242, 245 n. 107, 246, 270,

290, 295, 296 n. 227

khalaqa 258, 262, 290

al-mubda‘ 242 n. 98, 390

al-mubdi 241, 267, 299 n. 236 al-muhdith 267 al-sani 241

time and creation 242-245, 247, 267, 270 n. 168, 278 n. 186, 291

Damascus 25, 47, 63

deficiency (naqs) 174-175, 181, 190,

195-      196, 198, 209, 307, 334, 386-387,

399-  400

demonstration (burhan) 58-59, 62, 71 n. 151, 76-78, 80, 84-94, 107 n. 242, 109, 111 n. 252, 250, 256, 258, 375

dialectic 29 n. 46, 30, 85-89, 92 n. 203, 302 n. 246, 315 n. 274, 318 n. 287

eclipse 49, 50 n. 91, 52

Egypt 3, 18 n. 18, 324, 326

emanation

fayd 6, 11, 40-41, 182, 218 n. 41, 242, 246, 270 n. 165, 284, 289 n. 210, 290, 291 n. 215, 294 n. 224, 295, 301, 304, 314, 343, 380

inbijas 291 n. 215

emission (inbi‘ath) 291 n. 215, 360

Empedocles, Pseudo-Empedocles 178 n.

194, 204, 218 n. 41, 220 n. 45, 232-233 estimation (wahm) 366, 368

eternity 28, 34, 39, 86-93, 97,

106 n. 240, 146 n. 95, 203, 207, 211, 214 n. 30, 229, 231, 235-236, 238, 243, 246-253, 255, 270 n. 167, 273-277, 280, 283, 284 n. 200, 286 n. 205, 291, 307, 320 n. 290, 321, 324 n. 300, 337 n. 11

qidam 324 n. 300

eternal

azali 87, 180, 269, 278

qadim 242, 278 n. 184

Euclid 65, 101 n. 228, 107

existence (wujud) 4, 41, 55-56, 62, 73-74, 77-83, 85, 89-90, 93-94, 102, 131, 134, 136-137, 142-144, 150, 160, 163-164, 168, 171-172, 180-185, 188,

196-     201, 206-207, 210, 232-234, 237-238, 242-247, 257-294, 297-298, 300, 303-308, 313-315, 327, 331-332, 346 n. 41, 349-350, 384, 390, 395, 399

experience (tajribah) 7, 26, 42, 48-50, 58-63, 66-69, 73, 76, 106-109, 111-112, 166, 380

Fârâb 12-13

al-Farghanï 35, 63, 337 n. 13

finitude 169-170, 235, 242, 245, 247,

265-      266, 268, 270, 273-277, 281, 291 n. 216, 304, 319

form (surah) 98, 100-101, 176-180, 200 n. 236, 207-209, 211, 214, 220, 244, 383-384, 401

Galen 86-87, 366 n. 85, 367

Geminus 5, 23, 54, 70-73, 84, 372, 379 al-Ghazâlî 1, 41, 51, 211-212, 276 n. 180 God 8, 17, 22, 27, 29, 32-34, 51 n.

92, 79, 81, 94, 101-102, 137-140, 143, 146, 149 n. 107, 150-151, 153, 159-161, 168, 170-172, 174, 178 n. 194, 179-190, 194, 197, 210, 218 n. 41, 229-230, 235-238, 241-247, 253, 258-260, 262-274, 276-281, 284-286, 290, 291 n. 216, 293-296, 299, 302-305, 313-314, 316, 319 n. 289, 320-322, 327, 331, 333, 340, 346, 349, 351, 354-355, 377, 380-381, 384, 386-387, 390, 395, 398

Allah 184 n. 203, 257-258, 262-263, 266, 316, 322

divine knowledge 184-188, 243, 316 n. 277, 321

divine will 32, 236, 243, 245, 247, 276 n. 180

First Unmoved Mover 97, 145, 148-150, 155, 159, 161, 181, 189, 237, 257, 291, 307, 340, 353, 355, 394

the First (al-awwal) 180-190, 197, 246, 256-260, 264 n. 150, 265, 270, 285, 287, 297, 316, 322

the One (al-wahid) 180, 183, 194, 197, 260, 262

happiness, eudaimonia (saadah) 323, 398, 402

Harran 16

heart (physiology and cosmological analogy) 363, 365-367

homonymy 99-100, 102 n. 230, 178

Ibn Adï, Ibrâhîm 31 n. 51, 239 n. 91, 317, 323 n. 296

Ibn Adî, Yahyâ 19, 21, 31 n. 51, 227, 239 n. 91, 271' n. 169, 277, 279, 282

Ibn Bâjjah 18 n. 17, 38, 122

Ibn Haylân, Yühannâ 13-14, 16, 18-19, 325

Ibn al-Nadîm 12 n. 4, 17 n. 14, 18 n. 18, 23 n. 27, 30 n. 48, 50 n. 91, 186 n. 207, 225 n. 61, 227

Ibn al-Qiftî 17, 23, 29 n. 45, 34 n. 55, 39, 94 n. 208, 231 n. 77, 283 n. 197, 335 n. 5, 337 n. 11

Ibn Qurra, Thâbit 35, 63

Ibn al-Râwandî 14, 29

Ibn Rushd 1, 18 n. 17, 38, 97, 107 n. 242, 116 n. 5, 122-123, 129 n. 41, 132, 147-150, 153 n. 122, 214-216, 220, 222, 224 n. 56, 232, 249 n. 122, 315, 336 n. 9, 353-354, 361-363

Ibn al-Sarrâj 14

Ibn al-Sîd al-Batalyüsî 321 n. 291

Ibn Sînâ 1, 2 n. ' 3, 8-9, 17 n. 15, 20 n. 22, 24-26, 31, 37, 41, 44-46, 48, 50, 57, 58 n. 111, 59 n. 118, 61 n. 125, 73 n. 154, 79, 84, 92-93, 101 n. 227, 113, 116 n. 3, 120 n. 16, 122 n. 18, 123, 125 n. 26, 126 n. 33, 127, 129 n. 41, 130 n. 43, 131-132, 141 n. 84, 142, 144, 147 n. 99, 151, 155-157, 159, 164-167, 171-172, 187, 192 n. 220, 198 n. 234, 200 n. 236, 202, 204 n. 4, 211-212, 214, 220, 232-233, 239 n. 91, 272 n. 171, 274 n. 176, 276 n. 180, 278 n. 186, 290, 294 n. 221, 296 n. 228, 301, 305, 309, 325 n. 302, 330, 333 n. 1, 334, 342-348, 354 n. 57, 355 n. 58, 356-373, 375-377, 381, 383 n. 1, 384-385, 388-397

Ibn Suwâr, Abu l-Khayr al-Hasan 277-279, 281-282

al-Ijî, Adud al-Dîn 126 n. 33

Ikhwân al-Safa46, 230 n. 75, 233, 336 n. 9

imagination (takhayyul) 65, 110, 130-132, 141, 173, 309 n. 259,

352-      353, 366, 368, 371, 385-396

imitation (cosmological, iqtida, tashabbuh) 157 n. 135, 351 n. 53, 395

imitation (human faculty, muhakat) 91, 110-111, 322

inclination (mayl) 134-135, 157 n. 135, 333, 339-341, 346 n. 42, 352, 370, 393 n. 43, 394-395

inference (istidlal, istinbat) 66-67, 90 n. 197, 103-104

infinity 169-170, 273-276, 286 n. 205 intellect

Agent Intellect 8, 137 n. 74, 143-144, 163, 167, 174-176, 178-179, 210 n. 21, 226 n. 64, 232, 283, 285-286, 304, 309, 310 n. 268, 357, 362,

388- 389, 400

human 8, 85, 97, 140, 174-179, 210 n. 21, 285, 309, 311, 397-402 self-reflexivity 141, 181, 187-188, 193, 197, 199, 297, 370

separate intellects (al-thawam) 8, 20 n. 22, 28 n. 42, 29, 39, 76, 78-79, 81-82, 89-90, 93, 96, 123, 128-130, 136, 138-140, 142-182, 188, 190, 191 n. 217, 193-194, 196-200, 202, 210-212, 234, 238, 258, 284, 286-289, 292-303, 305 n. 249,

307- 308, 322 n. 294, 323, 326-327, 330-331, 336, 346 n. 41, 349-352, 354-355, 357, 359, 361-366, 375-376, 380-381, 384-387,

389- 391, 395, 397, 399-400

Israeli, Isaac 266, 269-270, 275, 279, 281, 325

kalam 2 n. 3, 11 n. 2, 14, 27-30, 36, 38, 47, 51, 79 n. 172, 87, 96, 103, 105, 126 n. 33, 184-185, 187, 213, 229, 230 n. 75, 231, 235-236, 277, 282, 290, 292, 318, 350

Khurasan 13-14, 29, 32-33 al-Khwarizmi, Muhammad ibn

Ahmad 45-46

al-Kindi 4, 26-27, 30-35, 47, 48 n. 82, 50-51, 62-63, 65, 93, 104 n. 238, 112, 123, 126, 128, 131-132, 140, 146 n. 95, 161-162, 177 n. 186, 181 n. 197, 204, 219-220, 223 n. 50, 228, 231, 233, 244, 253-255, 264 n. 150, 265-281, 286 n. 205, 290, 303, 319, 325-327, 329, 330 n. 307, 377, 380, 388

al-Kirmani, Hamid al-Din 1, 20 n. 22, 41, 296, 362, 381

logic (mantiq) 14-16, 18-21, 25, 36, 64, 95, 98-111, 261 n. 144, 283-284, 318, 320-321, 326

al-Mamun 26 n. 37, 33, 35, 46-47, 63 Maimonides 1, 18 n. 17, 20, 38, 61 n. 125, 85-89, 96 n. 214, 97, 212-216, 220-222, 229 n. 72, 315, 374n. 99

Maragha School 63, 84

mathematics, geometry 22-26, 44, 51, 54-55, 64-66, 68-74, 77, 82, 101 n. 228, 104 n. 238, 108, 112, 165, 256, 357, 373 n. 95

Matta ibn Yünus, Abu Bishr 13-16, 18, 21, 147-148, 227-228, 267, 271-276, 279, 286 n. 205, 321-326, 328,

353-      354

matter

‘unsur 204, 217-220

celestial matter 3, 8, 17, 20-21, 29, 32, 119, 137, 203-236, 238, 241, 253-255, 275 n. 178, 283, 287, 305, 306 n. 250, 312, 327-328, 342-343, 348, 352, 374 n. 99, 384-385

fire 54, 121-122, 134, 195, 206, 217-220, 224, 230 n. 76, 342

hayula 98, 204, 208 n. 12, 210-211, 217, 218 n. 41, 228, 230-232, 243 n. 100

elements 18 n. 16, 54, 67, 116, 118, 121-122, 190, 195, 204 n. 1, 206-208, 213, 217, 218 n. 41, 219, 220 n. 45, 224, 229, 230 n. 76, 232-234, 236-237, 247-248, 251, 254, 283, 286, 307, 341-342, 349, 385, 394 n. 46

intelligible 204, 218 n. 41 maddah 66, 95, 98, 168 n. 156,

178 n. 191, 191 n. 217, 204, 205 n. 5, 206-210, 214-217, 220-221, 232-233, 244, 287, 305, 309, 339, 383-385

prime matter 96, 136, 144, 190, 218 n. 41, 230-234, 236-237, 243, 287, 304-305, 307, 327

sublunary 118, 174, 205, 207, 209, 225, 228 n. 69, 305, 306 n. 250

tmah 204 n. 1, 243 n. 101

medicine 57-58, 61 n. 125, 87 n. 189 Merw 13-15

motion (harakah) 1-2, 4, 8, 17, 23, 28, 32, 33, 36-39, 45, 52, 54, 60, 63, 65, 67-71, 74, 76, 81-83, 88, 91, 97, 116-118, 120, 122-127, 131-132, 134-135, 138, 146, 148-159, 162-167, 189, 193, 198-199, 205 n. 7, 206, 208, 212-213, 216, 218, 222, 225, 227, 232, 234-235, 237, 242, 245, 251-252,

266-      277, 283-284, 286-289, 291, 306, 333-379, 396

precession 120, 337, 364

Mutazilism 29, 47, 184 n. 205 multiplicity (kathrah) 137, 144, 156, 161, 168-170, 175, 181, 185, 188,

190-     202, 259-260, 265, 297, 306, 339, 384-386, 390, 400

nature (tabiah) 66-68, 74-76, 98, 108 n. 246, 133-138, 150, 172, 181 n. 198,

191-     192, 205, 232, 234, 244, 272 n.

171, 273-274, 285, 297, 299, 306, 308, 340-346, 385, 394

by nature 67, 109, 135, 142 n. 86, 150, 244, 254, 274 n. 177, 341-344, 394 al-Nazzam 47

necessity 95, 142 n. 86, 168 n. 156, 188 n. 213, 243 n. 101, 272 n. 171, 290 n. 214, 294, 295 n. 226, 394

Neoplatonica arabica 5-6, 21 n. 24, 22 n. 25, 31-32, 96 n. 214, 144, 170, 173-174, 178, 181-182, 191-192, 194 n. 222, 202, 228, 231, 238, 240, 244, 245-246, 253 n. 134, 258-264, 266, 273, 279-281, 290 n. 214, 291 n. 215, 293, 295, 299, 313, 328-329, 379, 386-387

Neoplatonism 3-6, 8, 11, 21-22, 31-32, 40-41, 55, 65, 73, 75 n. 161, 92 n. 203, 94, 96, 102 n. 230, 112, 129, 131, 141-142, 144, 146 n. 96, 147-148, 152, 160 n. 143, 161, 164, 168, 170, 173, 178, 181, 187-195, 198 n. 234, 201-202, 205 n. 7, 218 n. 41, 219 n. 43, 225 n. 59, 233-234, 237-238, 239 n. 93, 245, 246 n. 110, 257, 262, 270 n. 168, 271, 280, 284 n. 201, 285-286, 291-293, 295 n. 226, 296-297, 299, 300-303, 308, 313-314, 325, 327-331, 336, 368-369, 380, 397 n. 1, 399

Nestorian 14, 334

observation 7, 26, 35, 48, 50-51, 55-63, 66-69, 73, 76, 78, 80-81, 83 n. 182, 97, 109, 111-112, 166, 167 n. 155, 221, 370, 374, 380

occasionalism 229-230

Olympiodorus 15

orbs and spheres 7-8, 17, 23, 27, 32, 36, 39, 52-53, 66, 69, 74, 78-79, 82 n. 179, 83, 93, 97, 115-134, 138, 144-145, 147-167, 177 n. 186, 189-192, 209, 211-212, 216, 218, 220, 225 n. 60, 234, 242, 288-289, 295, 300, 305-308, 331, 335-340, 342-344, 347-348, 350-352,

354-      355, 357, 359-367, 370, 373 n. 96, 374 n. 99, 375-376, 383, 385-386, 389-395, 399 eccentrics and epicycles 23, 65, 68­69, 81-83, 115-128, 154, 158-159, 162, 165 n. 153, 234, 338-339,

355- 376

orb of the fixed stars 115-118, 120, 154 n. 129, 155-156, 159, 165, 336-338, 355, 357, 362-365 outermost orb 120, 133, 153 n. 124, 154 n. 129, 155, 157, 165, 189-190, 206, 308, 336-338, 343, 347, 355-357, 360, 363-364, 384

Pappus of Alexandria 103 n. 235 perfection 65, 74-75, 102, 110, 118, 132, 137, 174, 183, 190, 198-199, 243 n. 101, 259, 308 n. 257, 310, 331, 334, 336, 350, 352, 367, 370, 375, 386, 392, 395, 397-402

perpetual, continuous (daim) 67, 74,

138-     140, 150, 153, 268-269, 273-274, 276 n. 180, 277-278, 283, 286, 291, 346, 386, 401

perpetuity 268, 274, 276 n. 180, 281, 370 Philoponus 4, 20-21, 38, 85 n. 186, 91, 207, 213, 219-220, 222, 225 n. 60, 228-231, 234-235, 244-245, 247-255, 266, 269, 271, 274-275, 277-279, 325-326, 333-334, 340

Plato 11, 34, 53 n. 99, 54-55, 65, 68, 73, 75, 90, 128, 155, 178, 185, 187-188, 219, 224, 230-231, 237, 243 n. 101, 313, 333, 340, 345, 348-349, 391

Plotinus 31 n. 51, 144, 168 n. 159, 173, 186 n. 208, 192 n. 220, 193, 218 n. 41, 220, 291 n. 215, 329

Plotinus arabus 11, 21 n. 24, 31 n. 51, 171, 327

Porphyry 239 n. 93

Poseidonios 70

posteriority 102, 142, 288, 291 potentiality, potential (bi-l-quwwah) 129,

139-     140, 173-175, 194-195, 210, 226 n. 63, 233 n. 83, 268, 273-274, 276 n. 180, 278, 281, 286 n. 205,

308-  309, 310 n. 266, 311 n. 269, 341, 346, 386 n. 13, 391, 398

power (quwwah) 100, 110, 131, 135-136, 138-139, 165-166, 171, 173, 210, 226 n. 64, 268, 274, 278 n. 184, 336 n. 9, 338, 340, 345-348, 355 n. 58, 356-358, 360-361, 363-367

principles (mabadi‘)

and astronomy 57-73, 76, 80, 82-84, 369-376

and metaphysics 22, 34, 39, 41-42, 73-84, 90, 94, 104 n. 238, 108 n. 246, 148-151, 164-165, 168, 184 n. 203, 186, 190, 198 n. 234, 209, 216, 229, 232 n. 80, 238, 247, 256, 264,

272, 284-285, 287-288, 292 n. 218, 300, 303, 308 n. 257, 333, 370, 373 and physics 66-73, 82 n. 179, 82-84, 120, 124, 271, 369-376

first 57-59, 62, 68-70, 76, 77 n. 165, 83, 104 n. 238, 256, 257 n. 140

of knowledge 42, 57-66, 68-69, 90, 112, 124, 256, 339

of motion 68, 71, 134-135, 148-151, 156, 340-341, 352-356, 359, 364­365, 366 n. 85, 368-371, 373, 394 priority 142, 180, 183, 193, 287 n. 206, 291, 299

Proclus 4-5, 8, 11, 21 n. 24, 25-26, 31 n. 51, 65, 73, 75 n. 161, 102 n. 230, 123, 126 n. 34, 138, 143-144, 161, 164, 166, 168-170, 173 n. 175, 192 n. 220, 193, 199 n. 235, 200 n. 236, 217, 219, 224, 233 n. 85, 235, 245, 278, 293, 297-303, 308 n. 257, 314, 328-329, 331, 334, 348, 379, 399

Proclus arabus 4-5, 11, 21 n. 24, 22, 31 n. 51, 138, 141-142, 168-171, 173, 178 n. 194, 183 n. 200, 192 n. 220, 201-202, 243 n. 100, 278, 290 n. 214, 291, 294, 295 n. 226, 299, 301 n. 245, 328 n. 303, 322, 327, 330, 354, 379 prophetology 39-40, 110, 388 providence (‘inayah) 140, 161, 199, 244, 311 n. 269

Ptolemy 2, 3, 5, 11, 22-26, 27 n. 40, 28, 31-32, 35-39, 54-57, 62-63, 65, 69-71, 73, 83 n. 182, 84, 86, 119-121, 123-127, 145, 152, 154-159, 165 n. 153, 167, 201-202, 222, 234-235, 333-334, 336-339, 343, 345-348, 356, 359-365, 368-369, 372-373, 380

Pythagoras 118 n. 12, 159 n. 140

al-Qabïsi, Abu l-Saqr 47

Quran 27-29, 204 n. 1, 267, 279, 280 n. 188

al-Razï, Abu Bakr 4, 27, 30, 34-35, 45, 61 n. 125, 222, 228-233, 236, 325

al-Razï, Abu Hatim 218 n. 41, 232 n. 80 al-Razï, Fakhr al-Dïn 45 n. 74, 126 n. 33 religion 13, 16, 28, 92 n. 203, 239 n. 93, 261, 263, 270 n. 168, 279, 282, 302 n. 246, 320-322

rhetoric 17, 19, 29 n. 46, 40, 85-87, 92 n. 203, 109, 111 n. 252

Saadia Gaon 266, 269-270, 275, 276 n. 180, 279, 280 n. 188, 303, 319, 325

Sayf al-Dawlah 47

sense perception (hiss) 55, 57-63, 73, 90, 93, 96-97, 102-103, 107-109, 117, 131, 141-142, 187, 219, 353 n. 55, 366, 368

seven heavens 27-28

al-Sijistanï, Abu Sulayman 132, 177 n. 186, 351 n. 53, 395

al-Sijistanï, Abu Ya'qub 233

similarity (shabah, tashabuh) 100-103, 107-108, 179, 197-198, 201, 209, 228

al-Sïrafï, Abu Saïd 15

al-Suyutï, Jalal al-Dïn 27

simple (basif) 53-54, 66-68, 71 n. 151, 119, 131, 134, 137, 168-170, 180-181, 183, 185, 190, 194, 195 n. 226, 197, 201, 206-207, 211, 214-215, 217, 218 n. 41, 228-229, 233, 248, 305-308, 386-387

Simplicius 4-5, 20, 23, 26, 54, 72 n. 152, 84, 118 n. 12, 120 n. 16, 126 n. 34, 128 n. 38, 130 n. 43, 134, 136, 149 n. 107, 153, 157-162, 167, 201, 219, 225 n. 60, 235, 237, 239 n. 93, 244, 248 n. 115, 307, 314, 334, 340, 341 n. 21, 348, 353, 355 n. 58, 373, 379-380

soul (nafs)

celestial 39, 119, 128-142, 144-145, 147, 151, 167-168, 173-177, 179, 184, 188, 190-195, 197-199, 202, 215, 218, 221, 234, 295, 297, 305,

309- 311, 340-343, 348-352, 354-357, 359, 361, 363, 365-366, 368-369, 371, 375-376, 385-392,

400- 402

human 39, 96 n. 214, 129-130, 132, 140, 177, 218, 226 n. 64, 310-311, 345 n. 36, 368, 388, 397-398, 400-402

inner senses (hawass batinah) 366-368

substance (jawhar) 53-54, 66, 74, 76, 79 n. 171, 95, 99, 106, 119, 129, 133, 135-137, 140, 142 n. 86, 148, 150-151, 159-160, 168 n. 156, 173, 180, 182, 191, 195, 204 n. 4, 205, 209, 215, 221, 231-238, 244, 264, 289, 296, 306-308, 317, 319 n. 289, 350, 383-385, 397-402

substantialization (tajawhur) 352, 397-402

substrate (mawdu) 103, 108, 118-119, 128-130, 133, 135, 141-142, 176-179, 190, 195, 208-218, 221-235, 287, 304-312, 328, 352, 385, 401 syllogism (qiyas) 59 n. 118, 77, 87-89, 92, 94, 104, 106 n. 240, 109, 252, 317-318

synthesis (tarkïb) 65, 91 n. 200, 104-105, 166

Syrianus 5, 73, 164, 186, 237, 298-303, 314, 328, 331, 379

al-Tabari, Abu Amr 271 n. 169 tafsïr 27, 45 n. 74, 147-149, 354 Themistius 4-5, 15, 21, 79, 123, 129 n.

42, 151-157, 162-163, 185 n. 206, 186-187, 214-216, 222-228, 231, 310 n. 265, 314, 334, 348, 353, 379

Theon of Alexandria 25

throne (arsh) 27

time (zaman) 18 n. 16, 34, 38, 91, 142, 180, 182, 186, 193, 229-230, 241 n. 95, 242, 244-247, 249, 251 n. 127, 252-254, 267-270, 273-274, 276 n. 180, 277-283, 286, 291, 294, 318, 324 n. 300, 327, 337, 393, 398

transfer (naqlah) 58, 67, 98-112, 311, 317-318

Transoxania 13-14, 33

true, truth (haqq) 184 n. 203, 257, 260, 262

al-Tusi, Nasir al-Din 25, 36, 48 n. 82, 53 n. 98, ’54, 81 n. 176, 82-84, 113, 116 n. 3, 126 n. 33, 127, 344 n. 30, 360 n. 68, 361-363, 365-367, 372-373, 377

unity, oneness (wahdah) 116 n. 5, 136 n. 69, 164, 168, 188, 190-202, 235, 257-258, 260, 262, 264 n. 150, 283 n. 197, 292, 398

unmoved movers 3, 7, 79, 97, 134, 144 n. 90, 145-157, 159-161, 164-165, 167, 189, 191-192, 202 n. 7, 288, 292-293, 300-301, 330, 340, 350, 353-354, 357-362, 368, 394-395

al-Urdi, Muayyad al-Din 82, 84

void (al-khala) 62, 121-122, 230, 394 volition, will (iradah) 49-50, 132 n. 54, 134-135, 177 n. 186, 270, 349, 392

world (‘alam) 39, 53, 66, 75, 135,

190, 206-207, 242 n. 98, 246 n. 113, 274, 277 n. 181, 318 n. 284, 320 n. 290, 324

Xenarchus 220



142    Although this section precedes the one above it in Jam', I have decided to place it after al-Fârâbï’s exposition of Aristotelian metaphysics in section 57 for the sake of a clear comparison with Ihsa.



[1] See notably Vallat (2004), Colmo (2005), and Parens (2006).

[2] De Smet (2008).

[3] A precedent for this approach may be found in Morrison’s study (2007); see also Janos (2011) for Ibn Sïnâ. Morrison focuses on the dialectic between Arabic astronomy and theology in the works of the fourteenth-century author al-Nïsâbürï and examines how these two disciplines mutually shaped one another. His book opens many interest­ing avenues for future research.

[4] Druart (1984a), Maróth (1994), D’Ancona (1995 and 2000), and Vallat (2004).

[5] M. Rashed (2008 and 2009).

[6] Several monographs focusing on cosmology and creation in the works of indi­vidual Arabic authors have been published recently; see for instance Iskenderoglu (2002), Acar (2005), Yousef (2008), and Griffel (2009). Al-Fârâbï’s place at the begin­ning of the Arabic philosophical tradition makes it all the more important to better understand his views on these topics.

[7] Notable examples are Galston (1990), Butterworth (in al-Fârâbï 2001a), Colmo (2005), and Parens (2006). But the last decade has also witnessed the publication of several studies that either question the existence of a Fârâbïan ‘political philosophy’ (Gutas 2002, 2003, and 2004b) or analyze it by avoiding Mahdi’s interpretive paradigm and by connecting it with other aspects of al-Fârâbï’s thought; see Crone (2003 and 2004), Gannagé (2004), and especially Vallat (2004), whose book provides a new and compelling discussion of this topic in light of late antique philosophy. An original attempt to connect al-Fârâbï’s political theories with Ismaïlï ideas had also been made by Daiber (1991).

[8] Gutas (2002, 24); see also Gutas’ (2003) review of Mahdi’s book entitled Alfarabi and the Foundation of Islamic Political Philosophy.

[9] Mahdi (2001, 82, 121-122, 124).

[10] For an analysis of this topic, see Davidson (1972 and 1992), Lucchetta (in al-Fârâbï 1974), Geoffroy (2002), and Vallat (“L’intellect selon Fârâbï: la transformation du savoir en être,” forthcoming).

[11]      It should be stressed from the outset that al-Fârâbï and medieval Arabic thinkers in general do not use a specific term to express our modern notion of ‘cosmology.’ Rather, as this study will show, their cosmology consisted of various disciplines, espe­cially astronomy, physics, metaphysics, and sometimes astrology, whose relations vary from one system to another. It is insofar as these thinkers attempted to provide a sys­tematic and rational interpretation of the cosmos using the various sciences available to them that one may legitimately speak of ‘medieval cosmology.’

[12]      Al-Fârâbï’s Ara' and Siyasah seem to possess a unique structure when compared to other works of the Greek and Arabic philosophical traditions, but as Maróth (1995, 105-106) and Genequand (in Alexander 2001, 21-22) have shown, they do share structural parallels with Alexander’s Mabadi'. Rudolph (2008) has argued that their format can be fruitfully compared to contemporary kalam works. At any rate, these treatises are usually referred to as ‘emanationist,’ due to the so-called doctrine of ema- nationism they articulate. In spite of the ambiguity of this concept in al-Fârâbï’s meta­physics and the fact that I will question its specificity in a later section of this book (ch. 3, 2.6.), I decided to follow this common appellation for the sake of convenience, although I will also refer to them as the ‘metaphysical’ works. I have used Najjâr’s edi­tion for Siyasah (al-Fârâbï 1964), as well as the English translation of the first section of this work by McGinnis and Reisman (2007, 81-104). As for Âra\ I have relied on both Walzer’s (al-Fârâbï 1985a) and Nâdir’s (al-Fârâbï 1985b) editions. The former contains some lacunae and has been criticized (see Mahdi 1990a), but it occasionally provides a better reading than the latter. Unless otherwise stated, all English translations are taken from McGinnis and Reisman and Walzer.

[13]      Gutas (1982a); Vallat (2004, 11-25). Legends and folklore, just as much as valid historical information, are the stuff of al-Fârâbï’s life, but Gutas has deftly sorted out these various threads and provided a solid critical account of the Second Teacher’s career. I, for my part, prefer to adhere to this ‘minimalist’ account, except with respect to the issue of al-Fârâbï’s birthplace and to his intellectual formation with the Christian thinkers, two crucial points concerning which Vallat’s arguments seem convincing and open several avenues for further research.

[14]      As stated above, I follow Vallat and others on this point. The alternative place of birth, Fâryâb (or Fâriyâb), mentioned by Ibn al-Nadïm and apparently favored by Gutas (1982a, 210-211) in his critical evaluation of the biographical sources strikes me as less plausible. First, one may rightly assume that if al-Fârâbï had been born in or hailed from Fâryâb, he would have been known as ‘al-Fâryâbï’ and not as ‘al-Fârâbï,’ the two names being written and pronounced differently in Arabic. But the Arabic tradi­tion seems unanimous on this point. Second, one of the names attributed to al-Fârâbï, ‘ibn Tarkhân,’ (sometimes in nisbah form ‘al-Tarkhânï’), even by some of the early bio­graphical sources, such as Ibn al-Nadïm, is clearly an Arabicized form of a Turkic name. Regardless of whether it refers to al-Fârâbï’s grandfather, as has been suggested, or to another member of his family, it agrees with the previous point in suggesting al-Farabfs Transoxanian origin, a not altogether surprising hypothesis given the number of thinkers active in Baghdad during the ninth and tenth centuries who origi­nated from this region.

[15]      Barthold [and Spuler] EI2, Le Strange (1905, 484-485), and Barthold (1977, 176-9), who also provide the references to the Arabic geographic works.

[16]      See al-Farabi’s autobiographic account, sometimes called Ft zuhur al-falsafah, pre­served by Ibn Abi Usaybiah (1965, 604); see also Zimmermann (1981, cv-cvi); and Landron (1994, 93). The interpretation of the historical data given by al-Farabi con­cerning the transmission of ancient philosophy to the Middle East via the Syriac Christians has been debated by scholars; see notably Stroumsa (1991), Lameer (1997), Gutas (1999), and more recently Watt (2008).

[17]      Van Ess (1980).

[18] Holmberg EI2.

[19]      Ibn Abi Usaybiah (1965, 604) and Zimmermann (1981, cv ff.). The latter provides the most substantial discussion of al-Farabi’s relation to the Christian thinkers of his time.

[20] See Endress EI2 and Ferrari (2005). For the study of logic in the Syriac tradition and its relation to al-Farabï, see Watt (2008).

[21] See Vallat (2004, 19 ff.). While tantalizing, this hypothesis requires additional evi­dence, especially given the semi-mythical status of Harrân in the Arabic historio­graphic sources.

[22] Habby (1997) has assembled virtually all the known information on Ibn Haylân.

[23] For the translation and reception of these texts in Syriac and Arabic, see Peters (1968), Endress (1966, 1995, and 1997b), Martin (1989), Luna (1989), Bertolacci (2001 and 2005b), Hugonnard-Roche (2003), and Thillet (2003).

[24] Ibn al-Qifti (1903, 279-280), Ibn Abi Usaybiah (1965, 608-609); see also Ibn al-Nadim (1970, vol. 2, 599-602, 629). For the surviving excerpt of al-Farabi’s com­mentary on Aristotle’s Physics, see Birkenmajer (1935). This work appears to have been very influential and was frequently cited by later Arabic authors when they redacted their own Physics commentary; see Lettinck (1994, 260, 308-311, 315, 491, 602, 606, 614, 639, 644, 650).

[25] Still extant, however, is Aghrad, which is not a commentary, but rather a brief summary of the aim of the various books of Metaphysics. See al-Farabi (1999c) for the Arabic text, Druart (1982b) for a French translation, and McGinnis and Reisman (2007, 78-81) for an English translation. Ibn Sina reports in his autobiography that he could only grasp the true aim of Metaphysics after having chanced upon al-Farabi’s Aghrad; see al-Bayhaqi (1935, 16), who reports the anecdote; and Gutas (1988, 240­242) and Bertolacci (2001 and 2005a) for the relevant excerpt and the impact this work had on Ibn Sina’s metaphysics.

[26] For a detailed discussion of al-Fârâbï’s logical studies with the Christian Peripatetics, see Zimmermann (“Introduction,” in al-Fârâbï 1981a). The importance devoted to cosmology in al-Fârâbï’s works is clearly visible in his emanationist trea­tises, but it can also be perceived in his summary of Aristotle’s philosophy entitled Falsafat Aristii ta lis. This work quickly surveys crucial concepts of Aristotelian physics, such as time, but discusses in excessive detail the place and nature of the elements in the cosmos.

[27] It is well known that al-Fârâbï’s commentaries had a profound impact on subse­quent thinkers, especially on those hailing from the Western part of the dar al-Islam. Ibn Bâjjah, Ibn Rushd, and Maimonides made extensive use of the Fârâbïan commen­taries in their cosmological, psychological, and logical writings, developing and criti­cizing some of his ideas in the process.

[28] Apart from the connection with these Christian scholars, themselves translators of and/or commentators on the Aristotelian corpus, this seems supported by the report in Ibn al-Nadïm’s Fihrist (1970, vol. 2, 599-602, 629), which surprisingly mentions only al-Fârâbï’s commentaries and not his mature metaphysical works. It is noteworthy that

Ibn al-Nadim was active shortly after al-Farabi’s death and may even have been a younger contemporary of the philosopher for a few years in Baghdad. Since al-Farabi presumably wrote most of his commentaries during his early Baghdad phase, these are the works that Ibn al-Nadim would have primarily known and to which he would have had easy access. On the other hand, and as will be argued later on, the emanationist treatises were presumably written during the end of al-Farabi’s stay in Baghdad, as well as during his sojourn in Syria and Egypt, which might explain why they are not men­tioned in Fihrist.

[29] For Yahya ibn Adi’s activity as a commentator, see Endress (1977) and Kraemer (1992, 108 ff.).

[30] For K. al-qiyas, see al-Farabi (1963 and 1985c), Gyekye (1972), and Lameer (1994); for ‘Ibarah, see Zimmermann’s analysis (in al-Farabi 1981a), and Black (2006); for Khatabah, see al-Farabi (1971a), Black (1990), and Aouad (1992).

[31] Maimonides (1963, vol. 2, 309); see chapter 3 for a fuller discussion of this passage and celestial matter.

[32] Ibn Sïnâ and Hamïd al-Dïn al-Kirmânï, to name but two thinkers, adopted some of the key features of al-Fârâbï’s cosmology. Although they considerably modified al-Fârâbï’s scheme, their model of a heaven divided into nine sections each associated with one or several separate intellects is directly indebted to the philosophy of the Second Teacher. For al-Kirmânï, see De Smet (1995, 282-284, 380; 2007, 488, and note 33; and 2008). I will say more about Ibn Sïnâ’s cosmology later on.

[33] Chapter 3 will argue that al-Fârâbï’s doctrine of celestial matter in his emanation- ist works owes an unquestionable debt to the cosmology of Alexander of Aphrodisias and Themistius; yet their names are not mentioned directly. This need hardly surprise us, since al-Fârâbï rarely refers to other thinkers by name, except in those works which are meant to summarize the doctrine of a particular philosopher, such as Falsafat Aflatii n and Falsafat Aristii ta lis.

[34] The Neoplatonic texts translated and adapted into Arabic are collectively known as Neoplatonica arabica and consist chiefly of the Plotinus arabus (itself composed of Theology of Aristotle, the Sayings of the Greek Sage, and Epistle on Divine Science spuri­ously attributed to al-Fârâbï) and the Proclus arabus, mostly known through adapta­tions of Proclus’ Elements of Theology. For the Plotinus arabus, see Badawï (1977b), Aouad (1989), and Adamson (2002a). The present study will focus especially on the Arabic versions of Proclus’ Elements, which survived in Arabic in different forms: the excerpts assembled and studied by Endress (1973) (to these must be added an addi­tional excerpt identified by Zimmermann 1994); the Liber de causis, known in Arabic as Kalam fi mahd al-khayr, which was edited by Badawï (1977a), and analyzed and translated into English by Taylor (1981); and finally Liber de causis II, edited by Thillet and Oudaimah (2001-2002), which is another version of Mahd al-khayr and which presents several divergences from its better known homonym. Mahd al-khayr and Liber II, which consist of 31 and 29 propositions respectively as opposed to Proclus’ original 211, deal mostly with the structure of the intelligible world and the relation between the One and the other intelligible entities. The most comprehensive studies of these Proclean texts are to be found in Taylor (1981 and 1986), D’Ancona (1995), and D’Ancona and Taylor (2003).

[35] Al-Fârâbï’s relation to Neoplatonism has been widely discussed and debated in the scholarly literature. See notably the studies by Galston (1977), Ivry (1990), Druart (1987a and 1992), and more recently Vallat (2004). In spite of this, few detailed com­parative analyses of the terminology and concepts in al-Fârâbï’s writings and in the Neoplatonica arabica have been conducted. For recent attempts, see Vallat (2004 and id., “Al-Farabi’s arguments for the Eternity of the World,” forthcoming), and Janos (2010a).

[36] See al-Qiftï (1903, 279,17-18) and Ibn Abï Usaybi'ah (1965, 608).

[37] For the Arabic translations of Almagest, see Ibn al-Nadïm (1970, vol. 2, 639) and Toomer (1984, 2). No edition of the entire Arabic version of Planetary Hypotheses exists to this day. Throughout this book, I relied on the reproduction of the Arabic manuscript by Goldstein (1967), the complete Spanish translation executed by García Blanco and Cano Ledesma (Ptolemy 1987), and Morelon’s (1993) French translation of Book One. Saliba (2007, ch. 1-3) provides a detailed discussion of the cultural and social circumstances surrounding the translation of the Greek astronomical works into Arabic and especially the reception of Ptolemy’s works in the Islamic astronomical circles. In the case of Hypotheses, there is no direct evidence that al-Fârâbï knew or read this work, although it would be surprising if he ignored its existence, since it was known to earlier and contemporary astronomers. Chapter 4 will show that Hypotheses underlies some crucial points of his theory of celestial kinematics.

[38] For the Arabic fragments of Aratus, see Honigmann (1950). Geminus’ Introduction to the Phenomena and Simplicius’ commentary on On the Heavens are not mentioned by the bio-bibliographers in their surveys of the Arabic translations, although it is pos­sible that some excerpts of these works were known to Arabic thinkers.

[39] Brockelmann (1996, vol. 1, 234) only mentions the British Library manuscript; Sezgin (1967-, vol. 5, 195) and Rosenfeld and îhsanoglu (2003, 76). Following a con­vention in Greco-Arabic studies, I use the term ‘Arabic’ to describe those scholars who wrote most or all of their philosophical and/or scientific works in Arabic, regardless of their ethnic and religious background. The term therefore refers to the Arabic lan­guage, which was the prevalent means of communication shared by Muslims, Jews, and Christians alike.

[40] Kubesov et al. (1975). Soviet scholars working during the 1970s and 1980s, espe­cially A. Kubesov and B. A. Rosenfeld, published extensively on al-Fârâbï’s mathemati­cal treatises and on Arabic mathematics in general. Because of the language barrier, these studies have rarely been integrated into Western scholarship. With regard to al-Fârâbï’s views on astronomy, however, Kubesov’s studies (1974, 1981) are problem­atic, in that they rely extensively on the British Library manuscript. Moreover, the authenticity of many of the treatises he discusses has to be more firmly established before his conclusions can be fully accepted. In spite of this, Kubesov must be given credit for being one of the only scholars to focus on the astronomical theories of the falasifah.

[41] Goldstein (1980, 342).

[42] Judging from their comments, it appears that Kubesov et al. were not cognizant of the existence of the Majlis Libary manuscript, which was first mentioned by Sezgin. More unsettling is the fact that their Russian rendition of the opening section of the commentary does not exactly match the text of the British Library manuscript. For example, the name al-Fârâbï is nowhere to be found in their Russian translation, although it appears on numerous occasions in the British Library copy. This indicates either that Kubesov et al. adumbrated the text at their disposal or that they did not after all consult exactly the same document as the one owned by the British Library.

[43] A certain Abû l-Fath Ahmad ibn Muhammad ibn al-Sari (d. 1153 CE) wrote a treatise entitled Qawl fi bayan ma wahama fihi Abu Nasr al-Farabi ‘inda sharhihi l-fasl al-sabi' ‘ashar min al-maqalah al-khamisah min al-majisti wa-sharh hadha l-fasl, as reported by Sezgin in GAS (1967-, vol. 5, 195).

[44] Rosenthal (1956), Rescher (1964, 45), and Adamson (2007a, 8).

[45] See for example Àra (al-Farabi 1985a, 129 and 1985b, 73).

[46] See further section 2.2.1 below.

[47] Although there is no solid evidence for the existence of permanent and full- fledged observatories in ninth- and tenth-century Baghdad, we know that astronomi­cal observations were carried out in this city, some of which were sponsored by the Abbasid caliphs, especially al-Mamun; see Sayili (1981, 51-80) and King (1997, 130-131).

[48] See, for instance, verses 2:29, 17:44, 23:86, and 65:12: “It is God Who created seven heavens, and of earths their like.”

[49] For a clear and concise overview of this traditional model, see Neuwirth (2001).

[50] Al-Suyûti’s main work on traditional cosmology, Al-hay‘ah al-saniyyah fi l-hayah al-sunniyyah, was extensively studied by Heinen (1982). Al-Suyûti relied on many earlier such works to write his book. This indicates an uninterrupted Islamic cosmo­logical tradition running possibly from the formation of the Quran and hadith literature—or shortly thereafter—to the fifteenth century. However, this traditional model also underwent substantial transformation as a result of its contact with the Ptolemaic worldview. In some kalam works, for instance, the throne and footstool are identified with the eighth and ninth celestial orbs of the Ptolemaic universe, although it is unclear when exactly this exegetical trend began; see Heinen (1982, 76 ff.) and Huart EI2.

[51] For insight into this Biblical cosmological tradition and its Mesopotamian roots, see Collins (1996) and Horowitz (1998).

[52] One striking exception is the equation al-Fârâbï makes between the separate intellects and the angels of the Islamic tradition (al-Fârâbï 1964, 32). But this almost incidental identification is not developed at any length in the rest of the work and does not reflect a systematic attempt to adapt philosophical cosmology to an ‘Islamic’ template.

[53] Pines (1936), Wolfson (1976), and Dhanani (1994).

[54] Rudolph (2007 and 2008).

[55] Van Ess (1980). Ibn al-Qiftï (1903, 279) mentions a Kitab al-radd ‘ala l-Rawandi as one of al-Fârâbï’s compositions.

[56] In spite of the foregoing, it is difficult to identify the theologians whom al-Fârâbï addresses in his writings, since he does not name individual thinkers and since his remarks usually remain quite general. Al-Fârâbï in many cases adopts an ambiguous position vis-à-vis the theological camp, endorsing some aspects of their method but condemning others. For instance, his reliance on analogical tools and his obvious interest in the political and didactic potential of rhetoric and dialectic, which he shares with the theologians, point to complicated interactions between him and the various theological groups of his day. These interactions would have been at any rate unavoid­able in the vibrant intellectual centers that were Baghdad and the major cities of Khurâsân at this epoch.

[57] For an illustration of this dialectic in al-Kindï’s works, see Adamson (2003), and in al-Fârâbï’s works, Rudolph (2007 and 2008).

[58] Al-Kindï (1950-53 and 1997); al-Kindï’s treatises on these subjects are listed by Ibn al-Nadïm (1970, vol. 2, 615-622). See also Adamson (2008, passim).

[59] As Adamson (2007a, 29, 37, 46, and 112) notes, al-Kindi perceived Aristotelianism and Neoplatonism as compatible systems, and he strove to harmonize their various doctrines into a new synthesis. This project was facilitated by the translations and com­pilations of Neoplatonic material in Arabic executed in the al-Kindi circle; see Adamson (2002a), D’Ancona (2003, 84, 88-90); and D’Ancona and Taylor (2003, 627-628). It is however unclear to what extent these translations were informed by the idea of philo­sophical harmonization or, conversely, to what extent the latter idea emerged as a result of these translations.

[60] There has been long scholarly disagreement on this question. It was the view of some of the first historians of Arabic philosophy that al-Farabi was ignorant of the true provenance of these Arabic Neoplatonic works (see for instance B. Carra de Vaux, E. J. Brill’s First Encyclopaedia of Islam, vol. 3, 53-55). In the last decades, various schol­ars, especially M. Mahdi, M. Galston, and C. Butterworth, have contested this view as part of an attempt to define al-Farabi chiefly as an Aristotelian philosopher, who relied on the Arabic Neoplatonic texts with full cognizance of their spuriousness and for apologetic or ideological reasons. As I try to show in this book, this thesis is in many respects unconvincing, and I believe that al-Farabi’s understanding of Aristotelian metaphysics was shaped both by original works from the Stagirite and by the Neoplatonica arabica. For a detailed treatment of these issues, see chapter 3.

[61] In this regard, Adamson’s remarks (2007, 15) that the Arabic Neoplatonic works were “of little import” for the Baghdad School, including al-Farabi, and that “the Baghdad school ... were not much influenced by Plotinus and Proclus”

are surprising. Recent publications building on the work of Maróth and Druart, nota­bly by Vallat (2004 and “Al-Farabi’s arguments for the Eternity of the World,” forthcom­ing) and Janos (2010a), have shown convincingly that al-Fârâbi knew about and drew heavily from the Arabic Neoplatonic texts and especially the Proclus arabus. The present study will largely confirm this hypothesis. Moreover, the research that has until now focused on the Baghdad School seems too limited to allow for a definitive conclu­sion on the place of the Neoplatonica arabica in this circle and their use of it. For instance, if the contention put forth by M. Rashed that Jam' was composed by one of the Ibn Adi brothers is indeed true, then this author was definitely using the Arabic Plotinus and Proclus texts, as is substantiated by the many terminological and doctri­nal parallels between these works.

52     Adamson (2007a, 14).

53     Adamson (2007a, 86-88).

[64] For this thinker and the Kindïan tradition in general, see Rowson (1988 and 1990) and Adamson (2007a, 12-17 and 2007b).

[65] In this regard, Ibn al-Qiftï (1903, 280) lists a Kitab al-radd ‘ala l-Razi in his bib­liography of al-Fârâbï. This treatise is no longer extant, but it indicates that al-Fârâbï may have attempted to refute some of the cosmological theories of al-Râzï.

[66] For pre-Islamic Arab astronomy and the anwa tradition, see Varisco (1992 and 2000) and EI3.

[67]     For a survey of the sources of early Arabic astronomy and of the early practition­ers of this science, see Nallino (1944, vol. 5), Pingree (1973), Morelon (1996a and 1996b), and Saliba (1994a and 2007).

[68]     The history of the interactions between ‘ilm al-hayah and falsafah remains to be studied, particularly in the eastern Islamic lands; for efforts in this direction, see Saliba (2004), Ragep and Ragep (2004), and Janos (2010b and 2011).

[69] This may be true even though al-Fârâbï does not cite this text. The same problem applies to Ibn Sïnâ, who most likely read this Ptolemaic work, but does not mention it by name; see Janos (2011). The fate of Planetary Hypotheses in the early Arabic milieu is at any rate obscure and poorly understood by scholars, in spite of the seemingly wide impact of its theories on the works of many Arabic authors.

[70] See M. Rashed (2008) for an analysis of On Changing Beings. Lettinck (1994, 2) seems to imply that al-Farabi’s Physics commentary and On Changing Beings were one and the same work. But although the latter focuses on topics discussed in Book 8 of Physics especially, it is unclear whether it was originally part of al-Farabi’s commentary or composed as a separate treatise.

[71] See Mahdi (1972) for an Arabic edition of Against Philoponus and Mahdi (1967) for an analysis and English translation of the same work. This work will be analyzed in chapter 3.

[72] Ibn al-Qiftï (1903, 279-280).

[73] Brockelmann (1996, vol. 1, 235).

[74] Mahdi (2001, 7).

[75] Mahdi (2001, 82, 121-122, 124).

[76] Mahdi (in al-Fârâbï 2001c, the “Introduction” to the 1962 edition).

[77] Vallat (2004).

[78] See for example Tahsïl (al-Fârâbï 2001c, 39-42).

[79] Rudolph (2008). I decided to refer to this treatise simply as Ára' rather than by its full title for the sake of stylistic simplicity and to demarcate it clearly from Siyasah, also known as Mabadi l-mawjudat.

[80] In fact, Mahdi himself at one point admits “that it is perhaps not quite fair to speak of ‘political cosmology’ or ‘myth,’ that is, of a cosmos or a human body presented with no attention to the scientific accounts of the cosmos or of the human body. For it is precisely the relationship between science and the city that is at issue. ... Differently stated, the integrity of scientific knowledge should be maintained even when it is used to help form the opinions of the citizens” (2001, 11). From Mahdi’s own admission, then, there is no reason not to take the cosmology developed in these works as a serious and genuine attempt on the part of al-Fârâbï to provide a valid “scientific” worldview.

[81] Mehren (1885). More recently, Y. Michot (2006) devoted an entire study to this treatise, which also contains a wealth of information on the medieval Muslim percep­tion of astrology in general. Al-Bïrünï is another important figure in this respect, but his relation to astrology is more ambiguous, since he himself composed treatises on this art; see Pines (1964).

[82] Ibn Sina (1999, 120-121). It is interesting to note that many Latin thinkers also classified astrology as a physical science, as is shown by Lindberg (2007, 270-277).

[83] Ragep (1993, vol. 1, 34-35); Bosworth (1963, especially 101 and 110) briefly com­pares al-Farabi’s Ihsa‘ to al-Khwarizmi’s Mafatth al-‘ulum.

[84] For instance, Abd al-Latif al-Baghdadi inserted a section on astronomy in his commentary on Book Lambda, which he entitled Mukhtasar ma tabayyana min al-harakat ft [‘ilm] al-hayah (Neuwirth 1976, 67). Fakhr al-Din al-Razi in his various works, including his tafstr, refers to the astronomers exclusively as ashab ‘ilm al-hayah and to the discipline itself as ‘ilm al-hay'ah; see for instance al-Razi (2002, 94 fl.).

[85] Al-Farabi (1949, 84). The expression ‘ilm al-nujum also appears in one of al-Farabi’s introductory works on logic, Nass al-tawti’ah (al-Farabi 1985c, vol. 1, 59,1), where it is classified as a sub-section of the mathematical part of philosophy.

[86] Al-Khwarizmi (1968, 210-232); Ikhwan al-Safa’ (1957, vol. 1, 22, 114-115).

[87] Al-Farabi (1976 and 1987). Some features of these works have already been dis­cussed by Druart (1978 and 1979), Michot (2006, 55-60), and Saliba (1991, 68-69). The history of the edition of these two treatises is somewhat confusing, due to the vari­ous titles under which they were published. The first treatise was initially published by Dieterici (1890, 104-114) under the title Nukat fïma yasihhu wa-la yasihhu min ahkam al-nujum, and it was soon followed by a German translation (Dieterici 1892, 170-186). An anonymous edition entitled Risalah fï fadïlat al-‘ulum wa-l-sinaat was then pub­lished in Hayderabad on two occasions (1921 and 1948). Finally, the treatise was edited and published a third time by Jafar Àl Yasin (al-Farabi 1992, 281-301) under the title Maqalat Abï Nasr al-Farabïfï ma yasihhu wa-ma la yasihhu min ahkam al-nujum. This astrological work is not by al-Farabi’s hand. Its contents are related by Abû Ishaq Ibrahim ibn Abd Allah al-Baghdadi, who claims to have asked the Second Teacher to help him distinguish the true from the false in the realm of astrological study. As for the second treatise, which is much shorter and also seems to have been transmitted to us indirectly—the text starts with the statement qala Abu Nasr—it has to my knowl­edge been edited only once by M. Mahdi (1976, 69-74); cf. the French translation by Druart (1979, 47-51).

[88] Pingree (1990) and Gutas (1998, 45-53, 77-78, 108-110).

[89] Pingree (1990), Burnett (2002), and Adamson (2002b).

[90] Sayili (1981, 32-33) and Adamson (2002b, 262).

[91] Pingree (1990, 299). See the recent study and translation of al-Qabisi’s Introduction to Astrology by Burnett et al. (2004).

[92] In the short treatise Qawl al-Farabï fï l-tanasub wa-l-talïf; see al-Fârâbï (1987, vol. 1, 504-506, 505). To my knowledge, this expression appears only once in al-Fârâbï’s corpus, but it is for all purposes synonymous to ‘ilm al-nujüm al-talïmï. Consequently, Druart’s statement (1979, 47; cf. id. 1978, 43) that “l’arabe classique n’use pas de termes différents pour parler de l’astronomie, de la climatologie et de l’astrologie,” while true in some cases, is nonetheless misleading. In the Arabic astronomical tradition, the terms ‘ilm al-hayah, as used by such thinkers as Ibn Sïnâ, al-Tüsï, and many later astronomers, refer exclusively to mathematical astronomy and exclude astrological pursuits, such as the prognostication of future events. Indeed, most hay ah authors were careful to distinguish between astronomy and astrology at the terminologi­cal level, a distinction which furthermore entailed conceptual and methodological differences. Even the case of al-Fârâbï does not vindicate Druart’s statement. True, the expression ‘ilm al-nujüm used in Ihsa is ambiguous, since, as al-Fârâbï himself explains, it includes and may refer to both astrology and astronomy. But as we have seen, al-Fârâbï also possesses a more specific terminology, namely, ‘ilm al-nujüm al-talïmï and ‘ilm al-hayah, two expressions that refer exclusively to mathematical astronomy and distinguish it from astrology, called ah kam al-nujüm. As a corollary, Steinschneider’s and Druart’s decisions to translate the terms ah kam al-nujüm that appear in the titles of al-Fârâbï’s two astrological treatises as “astronomy” are mislead­ing, since these treatises discuss astrological themes, which bear no relation to mathe­matical astronomy. In fact, for al-Fârâbï and most early Arabic thinkers, ahkam al-nujüm refers exclusively to astrology; see Nallino (1944, vol. 5, 1 ff.), and Adamson (2007a, 192), who translates ahkam al-nujüm as “astrology” in al-Kindï’s works.

[93] Al-Fârâbï (1976, 69 and 1992, 291-292). This feature of al-Fârâbï’s cosmology will be further addressed in chapter 2.

[94] Al-Fârâbï (1976, 70-71, 73 and 1992, 286) and Druart (1979).

[95] Ibn Sïnâ (1999, 120-121).

[96] Al-Fârâbï (1976, 74).

[97] Al-Fârâbï (1976, 72 and 1992, 286-290).

[98] Al-Fârâbï (1992, sec. 23-24, 296-297).

[99] In a sense, then, it appears that al-Fârâbï is arguing for a distinction between what one might call ‘natural’ or ‘physical’ astrology on the one hand and ‘judicial’ astrology on the other.

[100]     For the conclusion that human free will escapes the determinism of the stars, see al-Fârâbï (1976, 74). But some Arabic astrologers managed to reconcile astral deter­minism with human free will; for a discussion of this issue in the circle of al-Kindï and Abû Mashar, see Adamson (2002b, 260 ff.). It should also be noted that many Latin thinkers made a similar distinction between a valid and an invalid branch of astrology and also discussed its impact on the issue of free will; see Lindberg (2007, 270-277).

[101]     Walzer (1957, 227), Wiesner (1993, 11, 32, especially 107 ff.), and Adamson (2007a, 7, 13-14, 191 ff.). Al-Kindï’s various treatises on astrology are listed by Ibn al-Nadïm (1970, vol. 2, 621-622). Some titles, such as Indications of the Two Maleficent Planets in the Sign of Cancer and Obtaining Indications about Happenings from Eclipses, indicate clearly that al-Kindï was much less critical than al-Fârâbï when dealing with astrology and fully embraced this discipline.

[102]     In spite of the apparent agreement of al-Fârâbï and some of the contemporary theologians on the general invalidity of astrological predictions, further research is necessary to clarify the relation between their views. It should not be assumed, for instance, that they accepted al-Fârâbï’s endorsement of the physical aspects of astrol­ogy, i.e., of those aspects dealing with the influence of the planets on generation and corruption, especially given the frequent criticism of a secondary level of causality between God and the physical world in kalam (for an extensive analysis of this ques­tion in al-Ghazâlï and in later kalam and falsafah, see Griffel 2009).

[103]     Nallino (1944, 25).

[104]     For example, al-Fârâbï (1985a, 135 ff. and 1985b, 76 ff.). One question that emerges from the foregoing is whether the valid aspects of astrology—i.e., those dealing prima­rily with the study of how the heat and light emanating from the celestial bodies influ­ence the generation and corruption of sublunary bodies—can truly be said to differ from physics, and especially those aspects of physics discussed in Aristotle’s On Generation and Corruption and Meteorology. In other words, according to al-Fârâbï, is not valid astrology, once purified of its undesirable elements, merely reducible to a part of physics, in which case its classification as part of the mathematical science of ‘ilm al-nujum would be inadequate and even confusing?

[105]     Al-Fârâbï (1949, 43); see also his Introductory Risalah on Logic (al-Fârâbï 1957, 232).

[106]     This sentence was translated incorrectly in one of my previous articles (Janos 2010b, 244). Al-Fârâbï’s point is that astronomy examines both phenomena that do not involve the earth and others that do: the eclipse of the sun is an example of the former, the eclipse of the moon an example of the latter.

[107]     Al-Fârâbï (1949, 84-86, my translation).

[108]     Al-Tüsï’s Tadhkirah, for instance, is divided into these two main sections of hay ah; see Ragep (1993, vol. 1, 36).

[109]     See his discussion of this topic and of Aristotle’s and Plato’s views on mathemati­cal objects in Burhan (al-Fârâbï 1985c, vol. 4, 68-69).

[110] Al-Fârâbï (1949, 96). In this passage, al-Fârâbï divides physics into eight parts, the second of which inquires into the bodies that are simple, as opposed to the fifth part that inquires into composite bodies.

[111] Al-Fârâbï (1949, 96).

[112] See Aristotle, Physics 2.2, as well as Simplicius’ (1997, 290,1-293,15) commen­tary on this passage and his report of Geminus’ commentary on a work by Poseidonius.

[113] As Ragep (1993, vol. 1, 39) writes in the case of Tusï, “it was for ‘ilm al-hay'ah to examine the outward manifestations of simple bodies, whereas it was for al-sama wa-l- ‘alam to investigate their essential nature.”

[114] Mueller (2006).

[115] Republic 7.530b.

[116] Republic 7.529d.

[117] See Taub (1993).

[118] For the place of mathematics in Almagest, see Pedersen (1974, 47-94).

[119]     It would appear that the Greeks did not have a specific term at their disposal to describe the purely mathematical aspects of astronomy until the end of antiquity; see Krafft (2002-) and Hübner and Hunger (2002-).

[120] Al-Fârâbï (1960a, 96).

[121]     Al-Fârâbï (1960a, 92-96 in particular). Tajribah corresponds to Aristotle’s èpneipia, which is described in several of his works, for instance in Prior Analytics 46a18-21 and Posterior Analytics 100a3-9. Al-Fârâbï and Ibn Sïnâ developed their own concept of experience, which plays a special role in their philosophy; see McGinnis (2003 and 2008) and Janssens (2004).

[122]     Al-Fârâbï (1960a, 95-96, my translation, as well as all forthcoming passages of this work).

[123] Al-Fârâbï (1960a, 96).

[124] Al-Fârâbï (1960a, 100).

[125] Al-Fârâbï (1960a, 101).

[126] Al-Fârâbï (1985c, vol. 4, 71).

[127]     Janssens (2004, 50): “It is clear that experience is not opposed to observation, but is closely linked with it: they both pay special attention to things, or events. But experi­ence transcends observation, in that, contrary to the latter, it does not simply notice particulars, but in addition tries to establish a kind of universality out of a number of particulars.”

[128]     Al-Fârâbï (1960a, 94-96). This passage of Müsïqa may have been inspired by Posterior Analytics 1.31, where Aristotle explains that sense perception per se cannot lead to certain knowledge and demonstration. See also Aristotle’s discussion of induc­tion in Prior Analytics 2.23, which he contrasts to demonstrative syllogisms. It is inter­esting that Ibn Sïnâ in Burhan also provides an elaborate discussion of the distinction between induction and experience in connection with the acquisition of first princi­ples; see the insightful articles by McGinnis (2003 and 2008), which focus on Ibn Sïnâ’s elaborations on these two Aristotelian concepts and their place in his philosophy. In many respects, such as their mutual endorsement of experience as a valid method of investigation, al-Fârâbï’s and Ibn Sïnâ’s accounts share many parallels.

[129] Al-Fârâbï (1985c, vol. 4, 25,2-3), translated by Janssens (2004, 52).

[130] Al-Fârâbï (1960a, 95).

[131] Al-Fârâbï (1998, 124) translated by Janssens (2004, 50).

[132] Janssens (2004, 48).

[133]     Al-Fârâbï (1960a, 100-101). Burhan (al-Fârâbï 1985c, vol. 4, 75) also contains an interesting section on the relation between the practical and theoretical dimensions of the sciences and mentions astronomy as an example.

[134] Al-Fârâbï (1976, sec. 3-4) translated by Druart (1979, 48-50).

[135]     Al-Fârâbï (2001a, 105): “Clearly, he [the physician] could not have acquired this determination [how to cure a particular person] from the books of medicine he stud­ied and was trained on, nor from his ability to be cognizant of the universals and gen­eral things set down in medical books, but through another faculty developing from his pursuit of medical practices with respect to the body of one individual after another, from his lengthy observation of the states of sick persons, from the experience acquired by being occupied with curing over a long perio d of time, and from ministering to each individual.” This passage may be based on Aristotle, who also uses the medical art as an example in Metaphysics 1.1.981a1 ff. Al-Fârâbï’s views on the method of medicine probably shared many parallels with his conception of the other particular disciplines, although they are difficult to reconstruct due to the lack of extant evidence. One of his writings on the various branches of the medical art—whether originally a part of Ihsa ’ or an independent treatise is unclear—influenced later generations of Jewish scholars, including Maimonides. For this work and for a discussion of al-Fârâbï’s views on medi­cine, see Plessner (1972), Stroumsa (1993), and Zonta (1995). It should be noted that unlike Abu Bakr al-Râzï and later Ibn Sïnâ, who were famous physicians, al-Fârâbï does not seem to have devoted much time to the study and practice of medicine.

[136] This text has been edited and translated into English (al-Fârâbï 1951).

[137] Al-Fârâbï (1960a, 92).

[138] Translated by A. J. Jenkinson (in Aristotle 2001).

[139]    Ptolemy (1984, 1.1 H8) alludes to the work of previous scientists and the impor­tance of empiricism; 1.2 H9 refers more directly to the role of observation: “We shall try to provide proofs in all of these topics by using as starting points and foundations, as it were, for our search the obvious phenomena, and those observations made by the ancients and in our own times which are available” (translated by G. J. Toomer); see also 4.1 H266, and Goldstein (1997, 1-2).

[140] Wiesner (1993, 35-38).

[141]     For the role of observation in Arabic astronomy, see Goldstein (1972), Sabra (1971 and 1998, 290 ff.), Morelon (1994), Saliba (2007, ch. 3), and Ragep (2010).

[142]     The latter text, which is conveyed in Ibn Abi Usaybiah’s Uyün al-anba (1965, 604), has been translated by F. Rosenthal (1975, 50-51); see also Rescher’s comments (in al-Farabi 1963). As for the historical section of Hurüf, see al-Farabi (1970, part 2, 131-161).

[143] Al-Fârâbï (1985c, vol. 1, 58-59).

[144] Al-Fârâbï (2001c, 18-20).

[145] Al-Fârâbï (2001c, 19 ff.).

[146] Al-Fârâbï (1985c, vol. 4, 65).

[147]     McGinnis and Reisman (2007, 79); for Burhan, see al-Fârâbï (1985c, vol. 4, 68-69).

[148]     See the interesting article by Gutas (2004a, especially 204-205, 208) on the role of mathematics in al-Kindï’s philosophy.

[149] Freudenthal (1988 and 1990).

[150]     The world comprises all the corporeal, perceptible beings, and excludes the immaterial beings. Al-Fârâbï does not use a specific Arabic term that encompasses both the material and immaterial existents.

[151] Al-Fârâbï (1949, 34).

[152]     Al-Fârâbï (2001c, 13) explains that whereas some primary principles are acquired naturally and from birth, others must be reached through “investigation and inference” (fahs wa-instinbat). Although he does not mention experience (tajribah) in this passage, it clearly plays a role in the process of acquiring the other principles, as was discussed with respect to Musiqa. The two texts can be read side by side and fruit­fully compared.

[153] Al-Fârâbï (2001c, 21).

[154] Al-Fârâbï (1960a, 102).

[155] The most extensive and detailed analysis of the relation between physics and astronomy in antiquity is still to be found in Duhem (1913-59, vol. 1, 468 ff. and vol. 2, 59 ff.); see also Bowen (2007).

[156] Mueller (2006).

[157] Both texts have been translated into English and analyzed by Evans and Berggren (2006); see also Bowen (2007, especially 331 ff.).

[158] Evans and Berggren (2006, 53-58, 252-255); see also Bowen (2007).

[159] Evans and Berggren (2006, 254-255). This quotation resembles al-Fârâbï’s state­ment in Musiqa.

[160] Evans and Berggren (2006, 252). Some parts of Geminus’ Introduction to the Phenomena seem to have been available in Arabic, as Todd (1989, 473) mentions that some of the Hebrew translations were based on Arabic versions. This means that this work or other writings by Geminus could very well have been the direct model for al-Fârâbï’s conception of the astronomical method.

[161] The differences between Ptolemy’s and al-Fârâbï’s methods are in part rooted in their classification of the sciences. One should remember that according to Ptolemy, mathematics is the highest science because it alone can provide certain knowledge. Physics in contrast is hindered by the preponderance of obscure matter in its subject, while metaphysics cannot reach true knowledge and is marred by its speculative nature. Of all the theoretical sciences, then, mathematics is best equipped to lead to demon­stration and to a conception of the divine nature. The key passage appears at the begin­ning of the Almagest: 1.1 H5-H8. In spite of his claims concerning the superiority of mathematics, Ptolemy does not hesitate to borrow certain ideas from physics in order to strengthen his arguments. An example of this occurs in 1.3 H14, when he uses Aristotle’s theory of aether and simple body in order to prove the sphericity of the heavens.

[162] Al-Fârâbï (1985c, vol. 4, 68, my translation). In using this particular example, al-Fârâbï is probably following Geminus as reported by Simplicius in his commen­tary on Physics 2.2, as well as Simplicius himself (1997, 290,25 ff.). But al-Fârâbï’s account differs in one important respect from the one found in Simplicius. According to Geminus, the mathematician is not interested in causes: “the former [the physicist], with an eye to productive power, often touches on causes. But the latter [the astrono­mer], when he is constructing proofs from what impinges on a heavenly body from outside itself, does not pay any great attention to causes, as for example when he is presenting the earth or the spherical bodies as spherical” (Simplicius 1997, 292,9 ff.). Al-Fârâbï and Geminus thus seem to disagree on this point, for as we have seen, al-Fârâbï believes that the physicist and astronomer both give an aetiologi- cal account of the sphericity of the heavenly bodies and the world, although they examine different causes. Whereas Geminus refers only to physics and says nothing about metaphysics, al-Fârâbï, as will be shown shortly, describes the latter as the ulti­mate cosmological discipline on which the particular sciences, including astronomy, must rely.

[163] Al-Fârâbï (2001c, 18,10 ff.).

[164] These conclusions agree with the recent research on the scientific methodology of Muslim thinkers conducted by McGinnis (1993) and Ragep (2010), who emphasize the importance of induction, experience, and observation in the works of Ibn Sïnâ and Arabic astronomers respectively. Their studies also stress the discernment with which the Muslims criticized and tested the body of knowledge they inherited from the ancient Greeks, an attitude which was partly due, as Ragep explains, to theological and social reasons.

[165] See Syrianus (2008, 24,4 ff.) and Lloyd (1978, 207) for a translation of the relevant passages and a discussion of Proclus’ Hypotyposis.

[166] More precisely, the part of metaphysics that deals with immaterial substances; see Ihsa‘ (al-Fârâbï 1949, 99) and Druart (1987a, 39).

[167]     ’ Al-Fârâbï (2001c, 129).

[168] Al-Fârâbï (2001a, 61-62).

[169] Al-Fârâbï (2001c, 21-22).

[170] Al-Fârâbï (2001a, 45).

[171] This passage of Fusül is also reminiscent of Neoplatonic cosmology, especially that of Proclus. As Siorvanes (1996, 267) explains, for Proclus “the heavenly objects may be divine, but they stand between the intelligible and the sensible.” They are “inter­mediaries” (278).

[172] Al-Fârâbï (1964, 31).

[173] Al-Fârâbï (1985c, vol. 4, 65) translated by Endress (2003, 139, slightly revised); see also al-Fârâbï (1985c, vol. 4, 70).

[174] Al-Fârâbï (1985c, vol. 4, 70,13-14).

[175] McGinnis and Reisman (2007, 80). It is likely that al-Fârâbï’s classification of the sciences and his belief that some sciences are subordinated to others was inspired by Aristotle’s Posterior Analytics, especially 1.5.74a38-1.7.75b20, 1.13.78b35- 79a15, and 1.27.87a32-38. Aristotle in general maintains the autonomy of the sciences, but in some passages he also hints at their interconnectedness and seems to subordi­nate some disciplines to others (e.g., optics to geometry). While he may have been inspired by this work, al-Fârâbï nevertheless provides a different classification of the philosophical disciplines. On the one hand, he develops the concept of the “coopera­tion of the sciences” (mushtarakat al-‘ulum), which is crucial to understanding his methodology and how the first principles are aquired. On the other hand, al-Fârâbï devises a pyramidal and highly hierarchical classification of the sciences. He estab­lishes metaphysics as the first universal science, to which all the other particular sci­ences are subordinated, and in so doing he set a profoundly influential model for sub­sequent Arabic thinkers.

[176] See Marmura (1990), who provides an overview of the influence of Aristotle’s Posterior Analytics on Arabic thought.

[177] Al-Fârâbï (1985c, vol. 4, 26 ff.); cf. his comments in Tahsil (al-Fârâbï 2001c, 15). For a discussion of these proofs in Aristotle and the later Arabic commentators, includ­ing al-Fârâbï, see Lettinck (1994, 105-113).

[178] Al-Fârâbï (2001c, 16-17).

[179] Al-Fârâbï (1985c, vol. 4, 66, my translation).

[180]     Aristotle in Metaphysics 12.8.1073b1 ff. and particularly the conclusion at 1074a14-17.

[181] Ibn Sina (2005, 14-15). It is also reflected in a passage of Themistius’ paraphrase of Metaphysics, Book Lambda, preserved in Hebrew; see Themistius (1999, sec. 8.5, 101): “Si j’ai dit que la science des astres est très unie à la philosophie [i.e., metaphysics], cest seulement parce qu’elle seule cherche la substance sensible éternelle. Quant au reste des mathématiques, leur recherche porte sur les accidents qui affectent les

» corps.

[182] It is worth comparing this approach to the Arabic theologians’ justification of the practice of astronomy. According to al-Nisâbüri, for instance, astronomy can help one to perceive the divine order that pervades the cosmos and that testifies to God’s glory; see Morrison (2007, 29).

[183] Al-Farabi (1985c, vol. 4, 66, my translation). The Arabic reads: fa-li-dhalika tusta'malu ashyau tabarhanat fi ‘ilm al-nujum muqaddamat uwal fi l-falsafah al-ula wa-fi l-‘ilm al-tabi‘i.

[184] Al-Farabi (1985c, vol. 4, 66,14-17, my translation).

[185] Marmura (1990, 94).

[186]     Ragep (1993, vol. 2, 387) and his discussion of the innï/limmïproofs in al-Tüsï’s astronomy (386-388).

[187] Al-Fârâbï (1960a, 102, my translation).

[188] Al-Farabi (1964, 31).

[189] Indeed, one wonders whether the statement of the philosophers to the effect that astronomy merely “borrows” physical principles is sufficiently adequate to express this state of affairs. This raises the question of why al-Farabi and many of his contemporar­ies continued to classify astronomy as a mathematical science, in spite of the heavy reliance of astronomy on physics and the fundamental assumption of the physicality of the orbs.

[190]     For the former, see Ragep (1993, 38-46); for the latter, see Sabra (1998, 307-308, 313).

[191] Ragep (1993, vol. 1, 90).

[192] In this respect, Arabic astronomers considered that Ptolemy had not success­fully synthesized the mathematical theories put forth in Almagest and the physical descriptions of the cosmos found in Planetary Hypotheses, and they therefore strove to combine both trends in a more thorough synthesis. As Ragep (1990, 210) writes: “In accepting that astronomy was based on both mathematical and physical principles, Arab astronomers reached a rather simple conclusion—the mathematical models had to be consistent with the physical principles.” As for Sabra (1998, 300), he defines the hay'ah project as follows: “the program consisted in seeking, or urging to seek, a recon­ciliation between the Ptolemaic “mathematical” hypotheses assumed to be already sup­ported by observational tests ... and adopted theories of cosmology and physics or natural philosophy”; cf. Saliba (2007, especially ch. 3).

[193] Ragep (1993, vol. 1, 2.5 [10]).

[194] Al-Fârâbï (1985a, 119-135 and 1985b, 69-76).

[195] The impact of al-Farabi’s and especially Ibn Sina’s cosmological views on the post-classical hay'ah tradition remains to be studied in detail. In noting these parallels, I do not wish to argue that al-Tû si read al-Farabi’s works, but merely to point out some of the main similarities in their cosmologies and highlight the continuity between the early falasifah and the hay'ah authors with regard to their views on the method of astronomy. There are also substantial differences in these thinkers’ approach to this subject. To begin with, there is no evidence that al-Farabi intended to modify or criti­cize Ptolemy’s astronomy in the systematic way that later hayah practitioners did. Since al-Farabi’s commentary on Almagest has not survived, we cannot know whether he was conscious of any shortcomings in Ptolemy’s planetary models and whether he believed that it was the task of Arabic thinkers to complete the astronomical project begun by the Alexandrian. Moreover, whereas hay'ah practitioners wanted to achieve a synthesis of astronomical and physical theories within a distinct and well-delineated literary genre and discipline, which finds an outstanding example in al-Tû si’s Tadkhirah, for instance, al-Farabi, in contrast, addresses astronomical and physical issues in differ­ent treatises and by resorting to different disciplines. His synthetic approach therefore appears quite superficial in comparison with the hay'ah works. In addition, it should be noted that some post-classical hay'ah authors attempted to “free” astronomy completely from its reliance on physical and metaphysical principles. In that sense, they went beyond not only al-Farabi, but al-Tûsi himself, who, as we have seen, emphasized the need for physical principles in astronomy. A brilliant example of this later development is embodied in the fifteenth-century astronomer al-Qûshji, studied by Ragep (2001).

[196] Maimonides (1963, 2.15.33a-b). This passage is reminiscent of some aspects of Philoponus’ criticism of Aristotelian cosmology.

[197] Maimonides (1963, 2.24.54b). Naturally, this passage should not be regarded as Maimonides’ last word on the topic, since Guide, as is well known, is a multi-layered and somewhat esoteric text. In any case, past scholarship has often portrayed Maimonides as a somewhat radical skeptic; see for instance Pines (1979), who empha­sizes the aporetic aspect of Maimonides’ thought. This picture, however, has been chal­lenged in favour of a more balanced assessment of Maimonides’ attitude vis-à-vis cos­mological and metaphysical knowledge; see Kraemer (1991), Ivry (1991), and especially Langermann (1991) and Rudavsky (2000, 24-30) (the last two references also provide a re-assessment of Maimonides’ attitude toward astronomy).

[198] Maimonides (1963, 2.15.33b, my emphasis); see also Vajda (1965).

[199] Al-Fârâbï (1985c, vol. 3, 81,15-82,4) translated into English by M. Rashed (2008, 27); cf. Mallet (in al-Fârâbï 1999e, 32). In the passage immediately following this one (82,4 ff.), al-Fârâbï criticizes Galen “the physician” (al-tabib) for having failed to grasp the distinction between dialectic and demonstration and for having limited himself to the former in treating the question of the eternity of the world; see M. Rashed (2008, 27-28).

[200] Al-Fârâbï begins by stating that the goal of the theoretical sciences is “to make the beings and what they contain intelligible with certainty” (al-Fârâbï 2001c, 13). It is clear that al-Fârâbï is referring to demonstration here, which alone can lead to certain knowledge. But a few lines afterwards, he cautions that “the attainment of certain truth is aimed at in every problem. Yet frequently we do not attain certainty. Instead we may attain certainty about part of what we seek, and belief and persuasion about the rest” (my emphasis).

[201] As Mallet (1996 passim) notes, it is likely that al-Fârâbï has the mutakallimun in mind when he discusses these aspects of dialectic in his K. al-jadal.

[202] This is true at least for al-Fârâbï’s extant works. For the arguments in his lost treatise Fï l-mawjudat al-mutaghayyirah, see M. Rashed (2008), whose interesting arti­cle nevertheless rests on a hypothetical reconstruction of its contents. For proofs for eternity in al-Fârâbï, see also Davidson (1987) and Vallat (“Al-Farabi’s arguments for the Eternity of the World,” forthcoming). In any case, al-Fârâbï’s attitude toward this issue was nuanced and complex, and may also have evolved over time, as this study will argue.

[203] Al-Fârâbï (1985c, vol. 4, 21 ff., 26 and 59 in particular).

[204] Al-Fârâbï (2001c, 13, 39 ff.).

[205] Al-Fârâbï (2001a, 158). Naturally, one faces the problem in this case of explaining why al-Fârâbï describes Aristotle as a creationist; on this question, see chapter 3.

[206] Al-Fârâbï (1985a, 88-89 and 1985b, 55).

[207] According to al-Fârâbï in Al-fusül al-khamsah (1985c, vol. 1, 64,12-15), these common first intelligibles are one among four kinds of things that are not known through reflection and inference. The others include “things that are received, things that are well known, and sensibles [maqbülat wa mashhürat wa mahsüsat]”

[208] Al-Fârâbï (1985a, 205 and 1985b, 103).

[209] Al-Fârâbï (1985a, 277-279, translation slightly revised, and 1985b, 146-147).

[210] See M. Rashed (2008). Rashed concludes that al-Fârâbï relied on both analytical and synthetic arguments to achieve this aim. Vallat (“Al-Farabi’s arguments for the Eternity of the World,” forthcoming) shows that al-Fârâbï used Proclean material to articulate some of his proofs of eternity.

[211] Al-Fârâbï (1985c, vol. 1, 56,8).

[212] Endress (2003, 138).

[213] In view of the substantial evidence pointing to this conclusion, it is difficult to understand the thesis defended by some scholars, who argue that al-Fârâbï rejected the demonstrative method and adopted dialectic or even rhetoric as his principal means of philosophical argumentation. This view was intimated by Mallet (1996 and his intro­duction in al-Fârâbï 1999e) and developed more systematically by Galston (1990), who defines al-Fârâbï’s metaphysics as a veiled form of dialectic. But more radical interpre­tations have also been advanced, in which al-Fârâbï’s alleged lack of interest in the demonstrative method is combined with the claim that he substituted political science for metaphysics. This position, which is grounded in the works of L. Strauss and M. Mahdi, has been articulated notably by Colmo (2005) and Parens (2006). Parens argues that al-Fârâbï was fully aware of the limits of metaphysics and thus promoted politics as the key science. He writes: “These limitations of the theoretical sciences no doubt contributed to Alfarabi’s conviction that political science or political philosophy may offer a superior frame for philosophy as a whole than metaphysics” (Parens 2006, 116). As for Colmo, he argues that al-Fârâbï’s philosophical language is not essentially different from the rhetorical and metaphorical language he attributes to religion. Accordingly, al-Fârâbï’s philosophy should itself be construed as a kind of religious imagery. Central to this approach is the correlation made between al-Fârâbï’s alleged belief in the limits of metaphysical knowledge and the impossibility of a demonstrative method and the subsequent establishment of the political science as the most impor­tant discipline in his philosophy. In his recent book on al-Fârâbï, Vallat (2004, espe­cially 85-129) has compellingly criticized some of these views and argued that al-Fârâbï’s political theories reflect a complex ontological and epistemological system that finds its roots in the Neoplatonic tradition. He concludes that it is metaphysics, not politics, which forms the foundation of al-Fârâbï’s philosophy, even though al-Fârâbï did develop an elaborate political theory on this metaphysical foundation.

[214] One exception is to be found in Ithbat (al-Fârâbï 1999d, 4 ff.), which provides several proofs for the existence of the separate intellects, although it says nothing about their number. The authenticity of this work, however, remains to be established.

[215] Vallat (2004, 12).

[216] As Ragep (1993, 36) writes: “Since a haya basilah work was an account meant to give a general overview of astronomy, it was generally held that it should be devoid of mathematical proof.”

[217] This conclusion, it should be noted, is not incompatible with Rudolph’s (2008) convincing argument that the structure of Àra was partly modeled on contemporary theological treatises.

[218] The latter work is mentioned by Ibn al-Qiftï (1903, 280). Some of al-Fârâbï’s extant metaphysical works are not devoid of a certain interest for demonstration. For example, in Àra (al-Fârâbï 1982a, 37-46) he demonstrates in some depth that the First must necessarily be a unique being with no associates, that It cannot have a contrary, that It is not divisible, etc. His argumentation in these passages is not devoid of a cer­tain deductive quality.

[219] Al-Fârâbï (1999e, sec. 67, 145 and 2001a, 161, translation revised).

[220] Al-Fârâbï (1999e, sec. 70, 149 and 2001a, 162-163).

[221] Al-Fârâbï (1985a, 78-79 and 1985b, 50).

[222] Al-Fârâbï (1985a, 84-85 and 1985b, 53). For equivalent statements in Siyasah, see al-Fârâbï (1964, 46-47, 49-50).

[223] Al-Fârâbï (1960a, 105).

[224] This skeptical streak in al-Fârâbï’s philosophy has been recognized for some time. Already in 1979, Pines published an article on al-Fârâbï’s psychology and metaphysics in which he argued that Maimonides’ skepticism toward the possibility of metaphysical knowledge stemmed partly from his reading of some of al-Fârâbï’s writings, especially his commentary on Nicomachean Ethics. According to Pines, in this work, which inci­dentally has not survived, the Second Teacher denied the immortality of the human soul and its capacity to apprehend metaphysical beings. Pines’ method and conclusions have been criticized by Vallat (2004, 102 ff.). See also Booth (1983), who devotes a chapter of his book to al-Fârâbï, as well as the more recent comments by Reisman (2005, 58). This feature of al-Fârâbï’s thought may find its origin in the far-reaching influence of the Neoplatonica arabica in the early centuries of Islam, which promoted the Neoplatonic doctrine of the transcendence and ineffability of the One. There are striking resemblances between al-Fârâbï’s statements and passages from Theology of Aristotle (see Adamson 2002, 112 ff., especially 115), which also bring to mind Proposition 5 of Mahd al-khayr (Badawï 1977a, 8) and Proposition 1 of Liber de causis II (Thillet and Oudaimah 2001-2002, 318). Al-Fârâbï seems to share with some earlier Neoplatonists the belief that some intelligible entities are inaccessible to the human mind (at least through discursive thought), and he also shares a penchant for analogi­cal language when it comes to describing these immaterial beings; see Vallat (2004, 275 ff.).

[225] The interpretations of Langermann (1991) and Rudavsky (2000, 24-30) should be taken into account when assessing Maimonides’ cosmological method.

[226] Al-Fârâbï (2001c, sec. 14, 20).

[227] See M. Rashed (2008, 23-25).

[228] Al-Fârâbï (2001c, 102-103).

[229] M. Rashed (2008).

[230] Zimmermann (in al-Fârâbï 1981a), Abed (1991), Langhade (1994), Lameer (1994), Alon (2002), Kennedy-Day (2003), Black (2006), and Menn (2008).

[231] Hartner EI2, and Kunitsch and Knappert EP.

[232] Al-Fârâbï (1970, sec. 68-69, 101-102).

[233] The latter treatise was translated and published by Zimmermann after al-Fârâbï’s commentary (in al-Fârâbï 1981a, 220 ff.). A recently published article by Vaulx d’Arcy (2010) provides a detailed analysis of the concept of transfer (and transferred terms) in al-Fârâbï’s philosophy. Although the author claims that “cet article entend présenter pour la première fois un concept central d’al-Fârâbï,” insight into this concept has already been given by Rescher (in al-Fârâbï 1963), Lameer (1994, 13-20), Gyekye (1972 and 1989), and especially by Janos (in his doctoral dissertation “Intellect, Substance, and Motion in al-Fârâbï’s Cosmology,” McGill University, 2009, 94-107), who discusses many ideas and passages also found in Vaulx d’Arcy’s article. It is surprising that the latter does not acknowledge any of these previous contributions.

[234] Al-Fârâbï (1981a, sec. 48, 227-228). Transferred terms are also briefly discussed in Introductory Sections on Logic (al-Fârâbï 1955, 274-275).

[235] Al-Fârâbï does distinguish, however, between the homonymy of transferred terms and other types of homonyms by introducing a chronological distinction. In this regard, he writes (1981a, sec. 49, 228-229): “The difference between transferred and homonymous terms is that the homonymy of the homonym has been with it from the moment it was first introduced, so that none of its two significations preceded the other in time, while with the transferred term one of the two significations preceded the other in time.” On homonymous terms in al-Fârâbï’s philosophy, see Menn (2008), who provides an in-depth study of al-Fârâbï’s discussion of particles and philosophical terms in Hurüf and its relation to Metaphysics Book Delta. Menn’s study is useful to understand the development of al-Fârâbï’s metaphysical vocabulary, although it does not explain how the conception of being as expressed in Hurüf relates to al-Fârâbï’s emanationist treatises.

[236] Al-Fârâbï (1949, 95, my translation).

[237]     Al-Fârâbï (1981a, 231). Furthermore, al-Fârâbï distinguishes in this passage transferred terms from metaphors, which, unlike the former, are “not used in any sci­ence.” Ibn Sïnâ in Metaphysics of Shifa (2005, 125) refers several times to terms that are “transferred” (nuqila) in a manner that recalls al-Fârâbï’s comments, but it is not pos­sible on the basis of this passage to conclude that he shared al-Fârâbï’s historical theory of transferred terms.

[238] It is difficult to distinguish the two concepts of analogy and similarity in al-Fârâbï’s philosophy, and it is unclear to me to what extent they overlap. The ambiguity sur­rounding analogy and similarity partly stems from al-Fârâbï’s own terminology and his failure to provide clear definitions. As Alon’s Lexicon shows, al-Fârâbï uses a whole array of terms to express these concepts, some of which have a common root. Qiyas, tamthïl, tanasub, munasabah, may all mean “analogy,” while “similarity” is expressed by shibh or tashabuh. Another hint at their connection appears in al-Fârâbï’s definition of analogy in one version of Hurüf: “Analogy, which is a similarity in ratios, consists of the excesses, deficiencies, and equalities that possess a similarity, be they of different genera” (wa-l-tanasub, huwa tashabuh al-nisab, an taküna l-ziyadat aw al-naqsanat aw al-musawat allatï laha mutashabihah wa-in kanat fï ajnas mukhtalifah). Although this definition refers primarily to Euclidean geometry, it is also relevant to the wider con­text of al-Fârâbï’s philosophy and it stresses the close connection between similarity and analogy. I owe this citation to Vallat (2004, 276-277), who took it from an unpub­lished edition of Hurüf. Vallat (2004, 275-278) reaches the same conclusion on the relation between similarity and analogy.

[239] Al-Fârâbï (1985a, 75-77 and 1985b, 48-49); cf Siyasah (al-Fârâbï 1964, 46-47, 49-50).

[240] See al-Fârâbï (1964, 50-51, 1985a, 73-77, and 1985b, 46-49), Vallat (2004, 275 ff.), and Menn (2008). Whereas Vallat’s account emphasizes the Neoplatonic back­ground of al-Fârâbï’s theories and connects him to thinkers such as Proclus, Menn proposes to construe al-Fârâbï’s theories on philosophical terminology and his doc­trine of being as an original interpretation of Aristotle’s Metaphysics, particularly Book Delta, thus highlighting the importance of this text in the development of al-Fârâbï’s philosophy in general. Many of the concepts I discuss in the context of al-Fârâbï’s cos­mology, such as transference, homonymy, and analogy, are alluded to or described by Aristotle in this part of Metaphysics. For instance, in Delta 16, Aristotle mentions terms such as “perfect” and “good,” which can be “transferred” (pera^épovreç and Kara pera^opàv) from one context to another. Al-Fârâbï conceives of transference differ­ently, but it is tempting to view Book Delta, in addition to Aristotle’s logical treatises, as a possible model for some aspects of his analogical method.

[241] Al-Fârâbï (1985a, 100-101 and 1985b, 60).

[242] Al-Fârâbï (1964, 51).

[243] Al-Fârâbï (1964, 41, 1985a, 120-121, and 1985b, 69-71). In these passages, al-Fârâbï deploys an analogical language or language of similarity, which is based espe­cially on the sh-b-h root, and which stresses the parallels between superlunary and sublunary bodies without establishing an identity between the two. It is worth reiterat­ing that terms from the sh-b-h root also appear in al-Fârâbï’s discussion of the tech­nique of transference in his logical works. This common terminology suggests a close connection between transference, similarity, and analogy; see Vallat (2004, 226 ff., 307 ff.).

[244] Rescher translates it as “inference by transfer” or simply “analogy,” and Gyekye as “analogical inference.” See al-Fârâbï (1963, especially 266,13-268,20), Lameer (1994, 13-20), Gyekye (1972, 33), and Rescher (in al-Fârâbï 1963, 93). The present discussion of transfer will be restricted to its relevance for al-Fârâbï’s cosmology. For a broader treatment of this concept, see Vaulx d’Arcy (2010).

[245] Al-Fârâbï (1963, 266,15 and 1985c, vol. 2, 45): wa-huwa alladhi yusammihi ahl zamanina l-isdidlal bi-l-shahid ‘ala l-ghaib. The theological background of al-Fârâbï’s account of istidlal has been studied by Lameer (1994, 204 ff.). For a more general discussion of this technique in kalam, see Alami (2001, 121 ff.). In contrast, Rescher (al-Fârâbï 1963) and Gyekye (1972 and 1989) emphasize the link between naqlah and ancient Greek logic. The former proposes to trace analysis and synthesis to Aristotle’s Prior Analytics, the latter to the works of Sextus Empiricus and Pappus of Alexandria. Lameer restricts his analysis of naqlah mostly to kalam, but he agrees with Gyekye in regarding the work of Pappus as a possible precedent (216).

[246] Al-Fârâbï (1963, 266,13-14).

[247] Al-Fârâbï (1963, 266,16-18).

[248] Al-Fârâbï (1963, 267,20 ff. and 1985c, vol. 2, 46 ff.), Lameer (1994, 215-216). According to Lameer, the practical difference between these two modes of inference in logic is somewhat “superficial,” since both rely on the data provided by induction and are analytical in essence. But analysis and synthesis also appear in al-Fârâbï’s mathe­matical treatises. As Freudenthal explains, al-Fârâbï stresses two different, yet com­plementary, ways of approaching the problem of the relation between abstract geo­metrical entities (points, lines, etc.) and physical bodies. One consists of analysis, i.e., proceeding from the consequences to the first principles, and the other of synthe­sis, the opposite method, which involves moving from the first principles to the conse­quences and putting the elements in “the order in which they exist” (Freudenthal 1988, 110, 124 ff.; and 1990, 55; al-Fârâbï 1960a, 185-188, 211). Al-Fârâbï’s comments on analysis and synthesis should be construed in light of his digressions on the scientific method in some of his philosophical treatises, especially Tahsil. In the latter work, al-Fârâbï broadly follows Aristotle’s Physics 1.1 in describing the physical method as being essentially analytical, and he contrasts it with the synthetic, deductive method of mathematics, which proceeds from basic abstract principles to composite objects and finally bodies; see al-Fârâbï (2001c, 18-22); cf. Adamson (2007a, 18), who briefly dis­cusses synthesis and analysis in al-Kindï’s works. As it turns out, the methods of analy­sis and synthesis in mathematics and physics bear an ambiguous relation to those discussed by al-Fârâbï in K. al-qiyas; see Freudenthal (1988, 129-133). Perhaps the most obvious difference is that analysis in geometry consists of a process of gradual abstraction and is thus not an analogical mode of reasoning in the way that analysis in transference is. Freudenthal, who is to my knowledge the only scholar to have addressed the relation between these concepts in al-Fârâbï’s corpus, rightly suggests in my view that analysis and synthesis in a geometrical and in a logical context stem from different traditions. The concepts discussed by Freudenthal are definitely the ones that appear in al-Fârâbï’s Musiqa (al-Fârâbï 1960a, 185-188, 211), and they are also similar to the ones analyzed in M. Rashed (2008, 37-39, 42-43, 54). In contrast to geometry, music, physics, and metaphysics, the concepts of analysis and synthesis in al-Fârâbï’s logical works, and in his discussion of naqlah in particular, seem to have their own character­istics. In any case, this issue is intricate and requires further research. I refer the reader to Beaney’s (2007) article and bibliography, which discusses the different functions of these concepts in the ancient, medieval, and modern periods; see also Hintikka and Remes (1974). With regard to Arabic philosophy, analysis and synthesis have been studied mostly in a mathematical context; see Rashed (1991) and Bellosta (1991), who focus on the works of Ibn al-Haytham and Ibn Sinân respectively.

[249] Al-Fârâbï (1985c, vol. 2, 45 and 1963, 266,18-20).

[250] The warning that appears at the beginning of K. al-qiyas can be compared to what al-Fârâbï says in Jam' about the cosmological examples given in Aristotle’s Topics: “It has escaped those who disagree [those who claim that Aristotle asserts the eternity of the world] that, first, what is set forth as an example does not stand as a belief and, also, that Aristotle’s purpose in Topics is not to explain about the world; instead, his purpose is to explain about syllogisms composed of widely-held premises” (al-Fârâbï 2001a, 154). In illustrating his logical explanations with cosmological examples, al-Fârâbï is perpetuating a long tradition that harkens back to Aristotle’s Topics and Posterior Analytics.

[251] See for instance al-Fârâbï (1985a, 120-125 and 1985b, 69-71).

[252] As mentioned previously, terms of similarity from the sh-b-h root appear both in al-Fârâbï’s descriptions of the First and the celestial bodies in Àra and Siyasah and in his exposition of naqlah in Al-qiyas al-saghir and On Interpretation and form a con­tinuous thread throughout these works. It should be noted that Ibn Rushd adopts a similar view and also justifies the use of analogical reasoning in cosmological inquiries. In his Jawami' 42.4-10 on On the Heavens, he writes that “the things from which are acquired the premisses by which man scrutinizes many of the things concerning the heavenly body and through which he aspires to know their causes are [themselves] derived from the things which most closely resemble them, viz. the animate bodies, and especially man.” And in his Talkhis on the same work (Ibn Rushd 1984a, 196, 13-18), he adds: “clearly this statement about directions in the heavens with reference to those extant in animals is ambiguous, as also the concept of ‘ensouled’ applied to the heavens. Still, generally accepted premisses may be employed in demonstration in a certain way, especially in matters for which no other deduction is possible” (both pas­sages are translated by Endress 1995, 31). Unlike al-Fârâbï, however, Ibn Rushd insists on the ambiguity of this approach. In Jawami', he notes that “this kind of statement is ambiguous” [yuqal bi-l-tashkik] and therefore “weak” (Endress 1995, 31). Yet Ibn Rushd also believes that the premises derived from the study of sublunary existents may be used to form a “demonstration” and a “deduction.” See also Hyman’s comments (in Ibn Rushd 1986, 28-29).

[253] Gyekye (1989, 138); Rescher (al-Fârâbï 1963, 93 note 2) mentions Topics 108b10- 14 and Prior Analytics 2.25 as possible starting points for al-Fârâbï’s transference. Again, it is worth pointing out the potential influence of Book Delta, particularly Delta 16. The fact remains, however, that al-Fârâbï devotes a whole section of his commen­tary to a theory that is not explicitly spelled out by Aristotle. As Rescher (al-Fârâbï 1963, 43) notes, al-Fârâbï’s discussion of transference goes “so far beyond its Aristotelian original ... as to qualify, in effect, as an entirely fresh approach to the subject.” This illustrates al-Fârâbï’s willingness to depart from his models.

[254] Freudenthal (1990, 60) describes al-Fârâbï’s approach as follows: “to the claim that there is no systematic, intellectual, way leading from the world of sensible to that of intelligible, the Commentary answers that geometry is a decisive counter-example: the intelligible objects of geometry are obtained from the sensible body through analy­sis. ... To the teachers of geometry, it shows how to guide the student from the sensible objects to the knowledge of the intelligible, ideal, geometrical objects.”

[255] Al-Fârâbï (1970, sec. 157, 160,1-4, my translation).

[256] An example of the latter appears when al-Fârâbï (1961a, 114,19-20) states that “all of what was said about nature should be transferred [yanbaght an yunqala] to the soul.” The justification for the use of transfer in this passage is that both nature and soul share similar principles, notably with regard to causality, and that soul is placed onto­logically above nature, so that its study follows that of nature.

[257]     See Ibn Abï Usaybiah (1965, 604) for the former; al-Fârâbï (1970, part 2, 131-161) and Langhade (1994, 215 ff.) for the latter.

[258] Translated by Hardie and Gaye (in Aristotle 2001).

[259] Al-Fârâbï (1961a, 85 and 1969, 93, my emphasis).

[260] Al-Fârâbï (1985a, 219 and 1985b, 111).

[261] For clear statements to this effect, see Nass al-tawti’ah (al-Fârâbï 1985c, vol. 1, 57,11); cf. Falsafah Aristufalts (id. 2001c, 92-93).

[262] This being said, analogy also plays an important role in al-Fârâbï’s rhetoric and poetics; see Black (1990) and Vallat (2004, 318 ff.). Al-Fârâbï wrote a short treatise on this subject entitled Treatise on Analogy and Poetical Composition (al-Fârâbï 1987, vol. 1, 504-506). The relation between these rhetorical and poetic forms of analogy and the ones discussed and implemented in al-Fârâbï’s other works remains ambiguous. It is perhaps too early to make a final judgment on this question, but I believe that al-Fârâbï probably distinguished between various forms of analogy, some of which he regarded as philosophically unacceptable and downright rhetorical, and others as inclining toward the realm of demonstration. In this respect, Black (1990) stresses the ambiguous status of analogy in the method of the falasifah.

[263] For insight into this topic in Aristotle, see McKirahan (1978). As Adamson (2007b, 357) notes, “the topic of the subordination of the sciences receives a detailed treatment by some figures in the Arabic tradition, especially al-Fârâbï, whose Attainment of Happiness is devoted precisely to explaining how knowledge of the vari­ous sciences may be achieved, and how the sciences interrelate.”

[264] Adamson (2007b, 362 and 358 respectively); in contrast to al-Fârâbï, the notion of the subordination of the sciences is absent in al-Kindl’s method (Adamson 2007a, 33).

[265]     Al-Fârâbï (1985a, 115 and 1985b, 67).

[266]     Al-Fârâbï (1985a, 119-121 and 1985b, 69).

[267]     Al-Fârâbï uses the terms falak and kurah interchangeably; cf. for instance al-Fârâbï (1964, 32 and 1985a, 128-129). Although later authors, especially those working in the hay'ah tradition from the tenth century onward, sometimes assigned a fixed meaning to these two terms, falak referring to the orbs, kurah to the spheres—see for example the definitions provided in al-Tüsï’s Tadhkirah (in Ragep 1993, vol. 1, 97,5 ff., 99,3 ff. and vol. 2, 378-379)—there was no consensus on this issue in early Islamic times, and even Ibn Sïnâ in the eleventh century still uses these two terms interchangeably (see Janos 2011). I have nevertheless decided to follow a common practice in the modern historiography on Arabic astronomy by translating falak as orb and kurah as sphere. The orbs can be concentric or eccentric vis-à-vis the earth, which they in any case sur­round. The spheres are spherical bodies attached to the orbs that do not surround the earth and in which the planets are embedded. It is important to stress that according to al-Fârâbï both terms refer to concrete bodily entities.

[268]     Al-Fârâbï (1964, 31); McGinnis and Reisman (2007, 82). Cf. with the classification of bodies in his K. al-maqulat (1985c, vol. 1, 91,7-8). The term jism is, together with jirm and badan, the main Arabic word used in natural philosophy to render Aristotle’s ornpa. Unlike Greek, however, which possesses generic terms such as oñpávioi to des­ignate the celestial bodies in opposition to sublunary bodies, the Arabic jirm and jism can refer to both the sublunary and the superlunary body.

[269]     Al-Fârâbï (1985a, 120-121 and 1985b, 69) writes in Àra that “all these bodies [i.e., the celestial bodies] have one and the same genus [jins] while differing in species [al-anwa]. But in each of these different species only one body can exist and no other can share that species with it.” A similar view appears in K. al-wahid wa-l-wahdah, where al-Fârâbï (1989, 56) explains that “moonness” (qamriyyah) belongs to the moon alone, which is the single existent of a single species. The justification for making each celestial body a unique species is that its substrate can only receive one form and can­not have other forms opposed to the one it already has. For a discussion of this issue in Ibn Rushd, see Di Giovanni (2006), and in Medieval Latin cosmology, see Grant (1994, 220-223).

[270]    Al-Fârâbï (1985a, 118-119 and 1985b, 69).

[271]    Al-Fârâbï (1949, 84 and 1985a, 123-125).

[272]    Al-Fârâbï (1985a, 123-125 and 1985b, 71).

[273]    Al-Fârâbï (1964, 53-54).

[274]     Al-Fârâbï (1992, 292).

[275]     Only a few remarks will be given here, as this topic is covered in depth in chapter 4.

[276]     In Müsïqa (al-Fârâbï 1960a, 89) he writes: “As for what the followers of Pythagoras [Ál Fithaghüras] believe concerning the orbs and stars, namely, that they produce a harmonious melody through their motions, this is plainly wrong. For it was briefly shown in [the book on] natural philosophy that their view is not possible and that the heavens, orbs, and stars [al-samawat wa-l-aflak wa-l-kawakib] cannot emit sounds through their motions.” Aristotle himself had refuted the Pythagorean doctrine of the harmony of the spheres in On the Heavens 2.9; see also Simplicius’ (2004a, ch. 2.9) commentary.

[277]     Al-Fârâbï (1964, 53) and McGinnis and Reisman (2007, 94).

[278]     This term appears in Ara' (al-Fârâbï 1985a, 118-119 and 1985b, 69).

[279]     Al-Fârâbï (1985a, 114-115 and 1985b, 66-67).

[280]     The outermost orb was accepted by most Arabic philosophers and astronomers, probably on the basis of certain passages of Ptolemy’s Planetary Hypotheses (see Goldstein 1967, 38-42). Arabic astronomers also call it “orb of orbs” (falak al-aflak) and the “encompassing orb” (al-falak al-muhit). Some late antique Greek commenta­tors, such as Ammonius and Simplicius, seem to have taken into consideration the possibility of its existence without endorsing it systematically (Simplicius 2004a, 462,20-25). By the time of Ibn Sïnâ, however, belief in the existence of this orb was firmly established, and its discovery was attributed to Ptolemy himself; see K. al-najah (Ibn Sïnâ 1985, 303), Danesh-nameh (id. 1986, 142), and Metaphysics of Shifa (id. 2005, 317). For a discussion of how this ninth orb is responsible for the daily rotation of the heavens, see Ragep (1993, vol. 2, 409).

[281]     This order appears in Ptolemy’s Hypotheses; see Goldstein (1967, 6a).

[282]     Lettinck (1994, 297-303, 307- 315). Ibn Bajjah followed al-Fârâbï’s physical the­ory implicitly, since he does not cite the Second Teacher by name. Ibn Rushd, however, explicitly ascribes this view to al-Fârâbï and notes that this was also the view followed by Ibn Bâjjah. Ibn Rushd himself adheres to this definition of place, but unlike al-Fârâbï and Ibn Bâjjah, he considers the heavenly place to be accidental, not essential. All of these thinkers depart from earlier commentators, such as Alexander, according to whom the heavens did not have a place, be it accidental or essential. Once again, we witness the degree of influence that al-Fârâbï’s physical ideas exercised on later Arabic thinkers, in this case with regard to a cosmological puzzle in Aristotle that had gener­ated many different interpretations among the commentators. For an analysis of this same issue in the works of Ibn Sïnâ, see McGinnis (2006).

[283]     Al-Fârâbï (1961a, 106,14-15 and 2001c, 110).

[284]     By secondary or subordinate orbs I mean the smaller eccentric or concentric orbs and the epicycle spheres contained in the main orb of a planetary system; for a discus­sion of such planetary models, see Murschel (1995).

[285]     Walzer (in al-Fârâbï 1985a, 364); Davidson (1992, 45): “the version of the [astro­nomical] scheme presupposed by Alfarabi gave its attention to the primary celestial spheres and ignored the subordinate spheres”; Griffel (2009, 136).

[286]     Al-Fârâbï (1985b, 69, my translation). The Arabic text reads: wa-l-thalith, wa-ma ba'duhü ila tamam al-tis‘ah, yashtamilu ku.ll wahid minha ‘ala ajsam kathirah mukhtali- fah fi harakat ma. Walzer’s edition and translation of this passage (in al-Fârâbï 1985a, 119-121), which differs from Nâdir’s, is probably incorrect, since it ascribes only “one body” (jism wahid) to each group, which consists of a planet and several orbs and spheres. Walzer provides the alternative reading minha ‘ala ajsam kathirah, which is given by Nâdir and which should be preferred.

[287]     Al-Fârâbï (1960a, 102).

[288]     Al-Fârâbï (1985a, 128-129 and 1985b, 73).

[289]     Al-Fârâbï (1985a, 128-129 and 1985b, 23): wa-li-kull wahid min al-ukar wa-l- dawa’ir al-mujassamah allati fiha harakah ‘ala hiyaliha”

[290]     Ibn Sïnâ also clearly ascribes corporeal existence to the eccentrics and epicycles, as can be seen in Isharat (Ibn Sïnâ 1951, 419/168-169).

[291]     Al-Fârâbï (1985a, 130-131 and 1985b, 74-75).

[292]     Al-Fârâbï (1964, 55).

[293]     These models may have been discussed at greater length in a physical-astronom­ical context in al-Fârâbï’s no longer extant treatise Ft anna harakat al-falak sarmadi- yyah. Reference to the epicycles also appears in Taltqat (al-Fârâbï 1992, sec. 68, 392), where the author explains that “the planets are in themselves also moving around their own centers in epicyclic spheres” (wa-l-kawakib aydan ft dhatiha mutaharrikah ‘ala marakiziha anfusiha ft aflak tadawtriha). But this treatise was probably composed much later in the Ibn Sïnâ circle, as is argued in appendix 1.

[294]     This basic fact has not always been recognized in past studies on the Second Teacher. In his classic but outdated work on al-Farabi, Madkour (1934, 90-94) describes his cosmology as reproducing that of Aristotle in Metaphysics, Book Lambda, and does not recognize its basic Ptolemaic character. No mention is made of the eccentrics and epicycles.

[295]     McGinnis and Reisman (2007, 12-13).

[296]     Al-Farabi (1985a, 118-119, 122-123 and 1985b, 69 and 71).

[297]     The existence of these subordinate orbs and spheres within the main orbs appears to have been accepted by many authors of the classical and post-classical periods, such as Ibn Sina, al-Tusi, al-Iji, Fakhr al-Din al-Razi and others. For instance, al-Tusi states in his Tadhkirah (Ragep 1993, 2.2.4, vol. 1, 110-111): “Each of these seven orbs [i.e., the main planetary orbs] must be further divided into other orbs so that its planet’s com­pound motion results from them, consistent with what is observed”; cf. al-Iji’s Kitab al-mawaqif fi ‘ilm al-kalam (al-Iji [n.d.], 200).

[298]     For a comprehensive discussion of this topic among the ancient astronomers, see Duhem (1908/1990 and 1913-59, vol. 2, 36-8, 67 ff.); see also L. Wright (1973) and Evans (2003). In the first work, Duhem adopted an exaggerated ‘instrumental­ist’ framework, but his view is expressed in a more nuanced way in his later mag­num opus. The issue of the materiality of the orbs was also discussed by Simplicius and Proclus in his Hypotyposis, about which see Lloyd (1978) and Sorabji (2004, vol. 2, 376-80). For further insight into the Arabic tradition and into Duhem’s interpretation of it, see Ragep (1990).

[299]     For Ptolemy, see Evans (2003); for Ibn Sïnâ and Tusi, Janos (2011).

[300]     For an assessment of Ibn Sïnâ’s astronomical works, see Ragep and Ragep (2004).

[301]     See On the Heavens 2.2 and 2.12; and Metaphysics 12.8.1074b1-15, where Aristotle endorses the age-old view that the celestial bodies are gods.

[302]     See Simplicius (2004a, 378,1-382,1.32), who also discusses the view of Alexander on this subject.

[303]     Badawi (1977b, 104), Lewis (1959, 77, 181), al-Kindi (1950-53, passim), Gobillot (2002), and Alexander (2001, 46-47, 52-53, and passim). For an overview of the ani­mation of the heavens in ancient thought, see Wolfson (1962) and Endress (1995). Wolfson traces the continuity of the idea of an ensouled heaven from the Greek to the Islamic period via the church fathers.

[304]     On the Soul 2.1.412a20-21, translated by Smith (in Aristotle 2001).

[305]     See Fotinis (in Alexander 1980, 163-183) for a discussion of the relation between soul and form from Aristotle to Alexander; for an overview of the various interpreta­tions of On the Soul in late antique philosophy, see Blumenthal (1996). Davidson (1992, ch. 2), “Greek and Arabic Antecedents,” also provides information on the Greek back­ground of al-Fârâbï’s, Ibn Sïnâ’s, and Ibn Rushd’s theories. A further level of exegetical difficulty was created by Aristotle’s definition of soul as an actuality in On the Soul 2.1.412a.28-29, and more precisely as the “first grade of actuality of a natural body pos­sessing life potentially in it” (translated by Smith in Aristotle 2001). Subsequent think­ers exerted much effort to clarifying the relation between soul, form, and the various grades of actuality, a task rendered more difficult in the Neoplatonic context by the postulation of various super-cosmic and encosmic souls and by new definitions of potency and actuality.

[306]     Surprisingly, no commentary on On the Soul is ascribed to al-Fârâbï by the early bio-bibliographers, although he did write a commentary on Alexander’s Treatise on the Soul (Maqalah fi l-nafs). Moreover, he may have known Alexander’s De intellectu and Themistius’ paraphrase of On the Soul, which were translated into Arabic; see Davidson (1992, 7-9) and more recently Vallat (“L’intellect selon Fârâbï: la trans­formation du savoir en être,” forthcoming). For a study of the reception of Aristotle’s psychology in Arabic philosophy, see Gâtje (1971).

[307]     Alexander (2001, 52-53, 82-83, 100-101) and Sharples (2003, 199). Alexander was famous in antiquity for making soul the true nature of the celestial bodies, thus emphasizing their psychological qualities and downplaying their material qualities. See Simplicius’ On the Heavens commentary (2004a, 380, 30-382, 10). The equation of soul and form is later adopted by Ibn Sïnâ as well (1985, 314 and 2005, 311, 31-32). Some ambiguity remains in the case of al-Fârâbï as to how form can be applied to the super­lunary beings, since he is in general quite clear that form cannot exist without inhering in a material substrate. This tension will be addressed later on with respect to the intellects.

[308]     Al-Fârâbï (1985a, 121-123, translation slightly revised, and 1985b, 70).

[309]     Al-Fârâbï (1964, 53), McGinnis and Reisman (2007, translation revised). This Arabic passage lacks felicity of expression, but the general meaning, i.e., that the sphere­souls are intellects, is clear.

[310]     Al-Fârâbï (1964, 34).

[311]     See for example al-Fârâbï (1964, 34, and passim). Unlike al-Fârâbï, Ibn Sïnâ in Shifa (1983, 383, 14 ff., 387, 5) maintains a sharp distinction between soul and intellect in his cosmology and does not define the celestial souls as intellects. The reason for this may be that Ibn Sïnâ ascribes imagination, knowledge of particulars, and a certain degree of corporeality to these souls, which implies that they cannot be pure intellects. As Ibn Sïnâ (2005, 312,4 ff.) explains: “As for the motive soul, it is—as this became evident to you—corporeal, transformable, and changeable, and it is not denuded of matter; rather, its relation to the heavenly sphere is the same as the relation of the ani­mal soul that belongs to us.”

[312]    Al-Farabi (1999d, 46). But the ascription of this treatise to al-Farabi remains to be confirmed by future research.

[313]    For al-Kindi’s view on this issue, see Wiesner (1993, 79 ff.); for a survey of this question in the Greek and early Arabic background, see Wolfson (1962) and Walzer (in al-Farabi 1985a, 366). This argument has its roots in ancient Greek thought, and some thinkers such as Plutarch of Chaeronea also ascribed hearing and sight to the heavenly bodies on these grounds; see Wolfson (1962, 77-79).

[314]    Badawi (1977b, 101 ff.) and Lewis (1959, 75-79).

[315]     Al-Fârâbï (1964, 33).

[316]     Walzer (1957, 230), Ibn Sïnâ (1983-86, 383, 11-13, 391, 10), al-Sijistânï (1974a, 370 and 1974b, 374-375).

[317]     For al-Bitrüjï, see Samso (1992, 8 ff.); and for Ibn Rushd, Carmody (1952, 580-581).

[318]     For example, in Falsafat Aristii ta lis (al-Fârâbï 2001c, 129) he writes about “the acts generated from will, volition, and choice” that “it is these that make up the human will [al-iradah al-insaniyyah]”

[319]     Al-Fârâbï (1985a, 118-123 and 1985b, 69-71).

[320]     Al-Fârâbï (2001c, 129).

[321]     Notably on On the Heavens 1.2-4, Physics 2.1, and Metaphysics 5.4. Aristotle also mentions the “nature of the stars” at Metaphysics 12.8.1073a34. The loss of al-Fârâbï’s commentaries on the first two of these works is particularly problematic when treating such questions as the heavenly nature.

[322]     As in Physics 2.1.192b23-24 and Metaphysics 5.4.1014b19-21.

[323]     In On the Heavens 1.2-4 Aristotle explains celestial motion through aether’s natu­ral tendency to move in circles, but in section 2.2 of the same work he seems to make soul responsible for causing this same motion.

[324]     See the various excerpts collected in Sorabji (2005, vol. 2, 49-53).

[325]     Al-Fârâbï (1964, 36) translated in Alon (2002, 655).

[326]     Al-Fârâbï (1961a, 89,11-16 and 114,15-22).

[327]     Al-Fârâbï (1999a, sec. 13, 60) and Alon (2002, 655); but as will be shown in appen­dix 1, ‘Uyun is probably not authentic.

[328]     Al-Fârâbï (1949, 83, 8).

[329]     Al-Fârâbï (1949, 91); the corresponding passage seems to be Physics 2.1.192b12-20.

[330]     Al-Fârâbï (2001c, 20).

[331]     Al-Fârâbï (1964, 55-56, 1985a, 104-105, 132-133, and 1985b, 62, 75).

[332]     Al-Fârâbï (1964, 55).

[333]     This view is articulated in Mantissa and Quaestiones; see the fragments collected in Sorabji (2005, vol. 2, 41). It should be noted, however, that the ascription of these works to Alexander has been contested. As for Mabadi, the more likely vector of trans­mission for these ideas, see Alexander (2001, 113), where he explains that the processes of generation and corruption are due to the power (quwwah) of the celestial bodies. He writes: “This [celestial] nature and power are the cause of the unity and order of the world.”

[334]     Al-Fârâbï (1964, 55).

[335]     As Sorabji (2005, vol. 2, 40) explains, for Alexander, nature is “a divine power, because derived from the heavenly bodies which are divine”; al-Fârâbï (1964, 32).

[336]     The relevant passage (1219,1-7) is reproduced in Sorabji (2005, vol. 2, 49).

[337]     Alexander (2001, 94-95).

[338]     There seems to be a significant difference in their use of the term nature, however. Whereas Alexander limits nature to soul, al-Fârâbï (1964, 55) goes further and even speaks of the nature of the Agent Intellect. “The Agent Intellect,” he writes, “is disposed in its nature [bi-tabiatihi] and substance to examine everything that the celestial body prepares and gives.” This mention of a nature in connection with an intellectual princi­ple is quite surprising and seems incongruous, since the Agent Intellect is removed from all materiality and the perceptible world.

[339]     Al-Fârâbï (1985a, 122-123, 1985b, 70, and 1964, 34).

[340]     Al-Fârâbï (1985a, 70-73 and 1985b, 46-47), which echoes certain passages of Metaphysics 12.9; more on this later on.

[341]     Proclus (1963, 196, 18-19).

[342]     Badawï (1977a, 5, my translation).

[343]     Badawï (1977a, 6, my translation).

[344]     Al-Fârâbï (1964, 34).

[345]     Al-Fârâbï (1964, 34) and McGinnis and Reisman (2007, 83, translations slightly revised).

[346]     For the influence of the Alexander arabus in this respect, see Alexander (2003), Wiesner (1993, 41-107) and Fazzo and Wiesner (1993). For al-Kindl and Abû Mashar, see Adamson (2002b) and Burnett (2002).

[347]     Al-Fârâbï (1964, 34).

[348]     On this issue, as on many other specific cosmological points, Ibn Sïnâ departed from his predecessor and ascribed knowledge of past, present, and future particulars to the celestial souls. This seems a direct corollary of Ibn Sïnâ’s ascription of the faculty of imagination to these souls. On this point and its implications for human knowledge, see Gutas (2006a, 360-363).

[349]     Al-Fârâbï (1985a, 122-123 and 1985b, 70): “but the entirety of what it [the celes­tial soul] thinks of its essence is not intellect, because it [also] thinks its substrate [mawdu '].”

[350]     As these purely immaterial beings are beyond or outside of time, they do not have a temporal relation to other entities. Consequently, the relation between them can only be defined according to the concepts of ‘prior’ and ‘posterior.’ In his logical treatises Al-fusül al-khamsah and K. al-maqülât (al-Fârâbï 1985c, vol. 1, 66,9 ff. and 129 ff.), al-Fârâbï identifies five senses in which the ‘prior’ and ‘posterior’ may be predicated of a thing: according to time, to nature, to rank, to nobleness, and to being a cause of something else. It is interesting, if somewhat challenging, to attempt to apply this clas­sification to al-Fârâbï’s metaphysics. As we saw above, the notion of time should defi­nitely be excluded, since the immaterial beings do not have a temporal subsistence. As for the other notions, a separate intellect may be said to be prior to another intellect

according to the following senses: a) by being a cause of its existence. This is perhaps the most obvious sense of prior with regard to the separate intellects, as they are the causes of existence of lower beings. This causality should not be understood tempo­rally, but rather in terms of logical entailment and necessary simultaneity, such as the synchronous movement of a hand and a doorknob when a door opens or the rising of the sun and the emission of its light; b) by being nobler in substance than the lower beings. This goes hand in hand with the intellects being causes of other beings, a cause always being nobler than its effect; and c) by being higher in ontological rank, which is a corollary of the two previous propositions concerning the priority of a cause over its effect. Finally, with regard to the ambiguous expression ‘prior by nature,’ al-Fârâbï pro­vides two examples to illustrate what he means: the natural priority of ‘one’ over the number ‘two,’ and the natural priority of the concept and definition of animal over that of human. Following this line of reasoning, it would seem that the separate intellects can also be said to be prior by nature, for their existence precedes that of the lower existents according to the structure of reality and the ordo essendi. In other words, if one were to eliminate the separate intellects, then the effects below them would not exist, just as if the concept ‘one’ were to be eliminated, then the numbers following it would not exist either.

87     Al-Fârâbï (1964, 31).

[352]     See Badawï (1977a, 7,8), where there is mention of al-‘uqül al-thawant. In Mahd al-khayr, this formula also refers to separate intellects, but these do not fulfill the same role as in al-Fârâbï’s cosmology.

[353]     Al-Fârâbï (1964, 58).

[354]     Ibn Sïnâ is aware of the need to justify the existence of the unmoved movers, and he devotes several sections of his metaphysical treatises to this effect, as in Najah (Ibn Sïnâ 1985, 314-316), Ilahiyyat of Shifa (id. 1983-86, 393,5), and Isharat (id. 1951, 402/160 ff.).

[355]     Maróth (1995).

[356]     Indeed, Aristotle’s description of these various beings in this work is obscure and has given rise to many different interpretations. It is beyond the scope of this book to analyze this question in detail and to provide a survey of the Aristotelian scholarship on it. For more information, I refer the reader to some classic studies: Merlan (1946), Owens (1950, who provides an overview of the debate before 1950), Wolfson (1958 and 1962), Broadie (1993), Kosman (1994), Gill (1994), and Beere (2003). What is of inter­est here is not what Aristotle’s original cosmological ideas were like, but how al-Fârâbï may have interpreted the Aristoteles arabus and used it as a model for his own cosmology.

[357]     The problem in a sense is to address how al-Fârâbï interpreted Aristotle at Metaphysics 3.1.995b.31-34, when he writes that “we must inquire and discuss espe­cially whether there is, besides the matter, any thing that is a cause in itself or not, and whether this can exist apart or not, and whether it is one or more in number.” Indeed, one of the key issues of Arabic cosmology seems to have revolved around the question of how Arabic philosophers interpreted the immovable substances posited by the Stagirite.

[358]     Walzer (in al-Fârâbï 1985a, 365-366) and De Smet (1995, 275-276, 284).

[359]     The evidence for the existence of these intellects in al-Kindï’s philosophy is highly ambiguous; see Adamson (2007a, 60). Since al-Kindï, unlike al-Fârâbï, equates eternity and the state of uncausedness (Adamson 2007a, 99-102), God is the sole existent in his system that can truly be said to be eternal. This would seem to exclude the existence of separate intellects that are eternal, but caused, as in al-Fârâbï’s metaphysics. At any rate, one does not find an explicit and detailed articulation of the separate intellects in al-Kindï’s works.

[360]     See notably the study in Russian by Demidcik (1975), Walzer (in al-Fârâbï 1985a), Maróth (1994 and 1995), De Smet (1995, 272-284), Genequand (“Introduction” in Alexander 2001), and Daiber (2004) for insight into al-Fârâbï’s use of Book Lambda and some late antique texts. In his commentary on Âra\ Walzer hypothesized that al-Fârâbï based his cosmological model on a nonextant Neoplatonic source, which would have provided him with an already-made cosmological and metaphysical syn­thesis (al-Fârâbï 1985a, 363, 365). However, because Walzer was unable to identify this putative source, his view has been rightly criticized (cf. Mahdi 1990a). As the following discussion will show, many extant sources from late antiquity can shed valuable light on the structure of al-Fârâbï’s theory of the orbs and intellects.

[361]    This, a priori, is far from certain. Ibn Rushd, for example, in his great commen­tary on the Metaphysics, Book Lambda, interprets Aristotle in a particular way by rec­ognizing only the intellects that inhere in the spheres; see Genequand (in Ibn Rushd 1984b, 40-41).

[362]    Thillet (2003), Bertolacci (2005b and 2006), and Geoffroy (2003).

[363]    Bertolacci (2005b, 246, note 56). Ibn Sïnâ also used this version; see Geoffroy (2003) and Janssens (2003).

[364] Ibn Rushd’s Tafsir was edited by Bouyges (1948); more recently Book Lambda has been translated in French by Martin (Ibn Rushd 1984c) and in English by Genequand (Ibn Rushd 1984b). I will be referring to Genequand’s translation in my analysis. In this version, Abû Bishr Matta’s translation together with Alexander’s commentary spans from textus 1 to 38 (from about 1069a18 to 1072b18 in the Greek text), at which point Ustath’s translation takes over (textus 39 to 58). Most of the cosmological-astronomical aspects of Aristotle’s account are therefore conveyed through Ustath’s translation.

[365] Badawi (1947, 1-11).

[366] Ibn Rushd (1984b, 170, textus 43).

[367] Ibn Rushd (1984b, 170, textus 43).

[368] Ibn Rushd (1984b, 184, textus 48).

[369] Badawï (1947, 5, my translation).

[370] Badawï (1947, 8). The passage immediately preceding the statement on the number of orbs is missing in the Arabic translation, as noted by Badawï. In this pas­sage, Aristotle provides details about Eudoxus’ and Callipus’ theories and explains why many more orbs than planets must be posited in order to properly account for the planetary motions.

[371] The reason I stress the word ‘could’ is because Arabic thinkers developed diver­gent interpretations of this text. Ibn Rushd shows much hesitation in his various trea­tises, but in Tafstr he seems to opt for only one separate unmoved mover, i.e., God, who is desired by the other intellects inhering in the celestial bodies; see Genequand (“Introduction” in Ibn Rushd 1984b, 40-41). As for Alexander, the evidence is ambigu­ous. Simplicius in his On the Heavens commentary (2004b, 269, 30-270, 27) criticizes Alexander for positing only one separate unmoved mover, a fact noted by Sorabji in his preface to the same volume (viii). Genequand (Ibn Rushd 1984b, 41) comes to the same conclusion and makes Mabadt a precedent for Ibn Rushd’s position, but Sharples (2003, 198-199) believes that the Greek works of Alexander maintained the existence of several unmoved movers. Upon closer examination, however, the passages from Alexander’s commentary on Metaphysics adduced by Sharples to prove this point seem to me to be very ambiguous. The question of the number of the separate unmoved movers in the Greek and Arabic Alexander deserves a detailed study.

[372] Al-Fârâbï (1938, 34) and McGinnis and Reisman (2007, 77).

[373] Ibn Rushd (1984b, 162).

[374] Ibn Rushd (1984b, 168).

[375] Al-Fârâbï (2001c, 102-103, my emphasis).

[376] Al-Fârâbï (2001c, 129).

[377] Al-Fârâbï (1999c, 38), McGinnis and Reisman (2007, 81, my emphasis).

[378] Al-Fârâbï (1938, 36, my translation).

[379]     Maróth (1995); but cf. Maróth’s (1994) longer analysis of the falâsifah’s cosmol­ogy, which provides valuable insight into the sources used by these thinkers.

[380] Alexander (2001, 21-22).

[381] Maróth (1995, 108).

[382]     For Quaestiones, see Alexander (1992b); for its reception in the Arabic context, see Fazzo and Wiesner (1993), Hasnawi (1994), and Sharples (2003).

[383]     See Dooley (“Introduction” in Alexander 1992a, vol. 1, 3), Alexander (2001, 22, note 38), and Sharples (2003). Only the first five books are by Alexander; the other nine were composed by the twelfth-century commentator Michael of Ephesus.

[384] Maróth (1995, 106, 108).

[385] Cf. Alexander (2001, 66-71, 87-88, and 90 ff.).

[386]     For Genequand, see Ibn Rushd (1984b, 41) and Alexander (2001, 14): “Thus, on balance and in spite of some uncertainties, the overall evidence definitely weighs against the hypothesis of a plurality of separate movers.” See also Endress (2002) and Sorabji (2005, vol. 2, 340-341), who simply underlines the ambiguity without taking sides. It should be noted that this reading of Mabadi’, i.e., that there is only one separate unmoved mover that is identified with God, does not completely agree with the infor­mation that can be found in Alexander’s other works preserved in Greek. As was said before, Sharples (2003, 199) believes that the Greek Alexander upheld the theory of several separate unmoved movers.

[387] Alexander (2001, 10, 92-95).

[388] Quaestio 1.25.25-30: “There are several spheres of the divine body, and the first and outermost is moved in a simple and single movement by desire for that being; of the seven after it too each is moved by desire and appetition for some being.” See also Sorabji (“Preface” in Simplicius 2002, x), Simplicius (2005, 472,8 ff. and 474,5 ff.). It is surprising that Maróth does not mention the Quaestiones at all in his discussion, as it represents an important source for Alexander’s cosmology.

[389] Bodnár (1997, 196-200). Bodnár writes: “My contention then is that Alexander after talking about the sphere of Saturn, Jupiter etc., could keep the possibility open to talk, on occasion, about the very same entity as a bundle of different spheres, in what­ever pattern they are arranged by a viable astronomical theory” (198). Cf. with the previous discussion of the celestial bodies in chapter 2, 1.

[390]     For the Arabic excerpts, see Badawï (1947, 12-21) and the translation by Brague (in Themistius 1999).

[391] Maróth (1995, 109-110).

[392] Badawï (1947, 19) and Themistius (1999, 103).

[393]     This is also Bodnár’s (1997, 203) conclusion and it is acknowledged by Brague (Themistius 1999, 102). This being said, there is one odd feature in Themistius’ com­mentary. At one point (88) Themistius seems to make a distinction between the orb of the fixed stars and the outermost orb, which, following Aristotle (L1072a22-23), he calls the “first heaven.” However, for Aristotle the “first heaven” is the orb of the fixed stars. There are, I think, two possible explanations for this discrepancy: either Themistius interpreted Aristotle through Ptolemy’s astronomical model as exposed in Planetary Hypotheses, which posited an additional starless orb; or the Arabic author responsible for the translation or adaptation of Themistius’ paraphrase modified this passage in light of his own understanding of cosmology, which was probably based on the Ptolemaic model.

[394] Bodnár (1997, 198).

[395] Alexander (2001, 92-95).

[396] Ibn Sina (2005, 317,2-15, translation revised).

[397] Ibn Sina (2005, 317,20-25, translation revised).

[398] Ibn Sina (2005, 317,30-33).

[399] This being said, the differences between al-Fârâbï and Alexander are also signifi­cant: Alexander posits eight main orbs, whereas al-Fârâbï posits nine orbs; Alexander may have adhered to a homocentric astronomical model, whereas al-Fârâbï was clearly an exponent of the Ptolemaic one. Moreover, Mabadi cannot account for the very unique function that al-Fârâbï ascribes to the separate intellects. The complex theory of twofold and threefold intellection of the souls and separate intellects found in al-Fârâbï’s cosmology is completely absent from Mabadi. On the other hand, the cen­tral concepts discussed in Mabadi in connection with motion, namely, impulse (ishtiyaq), inclination (mayl), imitation (iqtida) and assimilation (tashabbuh), are not developed in the Fârâbïan corpus, although they play an important role in Ibn Sïnâ’s account of celestial motion in Shifa.

[400] Grignaschi (1969, 185-186) noted interesting parallels between al-Fârâbï’s writ­ings and a work by Simplicius. Walzer (al-Fârâbï 1985a, passim) also refers to Simplicius on several occasions in his commentary on Ara\ See also Gatje (1982), Stone (2001), and Wisnovsky (2003b, passim). As Hugonnard-Roche (2003, 289) writes: “On ne trouve pas d’attestation d’une traduction arabe du commentaire de Simplicius [on On the Heavens] chez les bibliographes arabes, mais on ne devrait pas pour autant en con­clure trop rapidement que l’ouvrage ait été totalement inconnu: des recherches restent à faire sur ce sujet” See also Vallat (2004, 368).

[401] CAG, vol. 7, 435,1-5; translated by Mueller (in Simplicius 2004a, 435,1-5, trans­lation slightly revised). The Greek reads ev ÓKráo^aipov êvàç KÓopov for “one cosmos with a system of eight spheres.”

[402] See the previous section on Alexander and Bodnár (1997).

[403] Simplicius (2004a, 462, 20-25, translation slightly revised).

[404] Simplicius (2005, ch. 2.10-12). However, as Sorabji notes in the preface (1-2), Simplicius ascribes the invention of the eccentrics to Pythagoras.

[405] Simplicius (2004a, 456, 22).

[406]     Simplicius (2004b, 270, 15 ff., translation slightly revised) and CAG, vol. 7, 270, 15 ff. for the Greek.

[407] For a clear statement of this view, see Simplicius (2004b, 271,12-20), as well as Sorabji’s preface in the same work (x); and Hankinson (“Introduction” in Simplicius 2002, 7). For discussions of final and efficient causality in late antique Neoplatonism and Arabic philosophy, see the relevant studies in Aristotle Transformed, edited by Sorabji, Wisnovsky (2002, 2003a, and 2003b), and Bertolacci (2005a and 2006).

[408] Al-Farabi (1938, 34).

[409] Badawï (1947, 19) and Themistius (1999, 103).

[410] Al-Fârâbï (1985a, 101-135 and 1985b, 61-76).

[411] Al-Fârâbï (1938, 34-35).

[412] See chapter 3, 2.6.1-2 and Janos (2010a) for an analysis of how al-Fârâbï applied Neoplatonic theories on causation and intellect to the unmoved movers of his cosmology.

[413] See Walzer (in al-Fârâbï 1985a, 365-366) and De Smet (1995, 276-277).

[414] Ibn Sïnâ (2005, 325,20-23).

[415] Marmura translates this term in the singular, although the Arabic is kurat. This has the unfortunate effect of changing the entire meaning of the sentence, since Ibn Sïnâ’s point here is based precisely on the distinction between the main orbs of the planets and the other subordinate orbs and spheres they contain.

[416] Ibn Sïnâ (2005, 325,30-326,8, translation revised).

[417] And this would be true regardless of whether one adheres to a homocentric or Ptolemaic model. What is important here is the attribution of one mover per orb and motion, regardless of whether these orbs are counteracting orbs, eccentrics, etc.

[418] This point will be examined in more detail in chapter 4, which is devoted to celestial motion.

[419] Ibn Sïnâ definitely inherited al-Fârâbï’s approach, for as he explains on several occasions, the number of unmoved movers or separate intellects can be elucidated through the art of astronomy and therefore through observation. The question of the number of unmoved movers is therefore intimately tied to the question of the number of perceived planetary motions and celestial bodies; see Ibn Sïnâ (2005, 14-15; 326, 7-8).

[420] Al-Fârâbï (1938, 35), McGinnis and Reisman (2007, 77, translation revised). The Arabic reads: wa-idh muharrik al-sama l-ula la maddata wa-la fl maddah lazima daruratan an yakuna ‘aqlan fl jawharihl fa-huwa yaqilu dhatahu wa-dhat al-shay' alladhl huwa mabda wujudihl. This citation shows convincingly that al-Fârâbï had already developed his theory of celestial intellection during the period of composition of this treatise. In turn, this indicates that Mahdi’s claims about the specificity of the cosmological doctrine of Ára' and Siyasah is unfounded, since the same theories appear in other non-“political” works by al-Fârâbï, such as Fl l-‘aql; for Ára' and Siyasah, see al-Fârâbï (1985a, 100-105, 116-117 and 1964, 52).

[421] Al-Fârâbï (1964, 40).

[422] See D’Ancona (1995, especially 53-73, 73-97, and 121-155).

[423] With regard to these points of doctrine, Proclus himself was dependent on Plotinus’ discussion of intellect in Enneads. See, among other sections, 5.1.5, 5.3.11, 5.3.12, 5.3.15, and 5.4.2.

[424] Proclus (1963, 167,20-25)

[425] Badawi (1977a, Proposition 4, 6) and Taylor (1981, Proposition 4, 289, 10-13).

[426] Thillet and Oudaimah (2001-2002, Proposition 19).

[427] Endress (1973, 35-36 in the Arabic text, my translation).

[428] Badawi (1977a, Proposition 7).

[429] Badawi (1977a, Proposition 12, 15,2).

[430] Al-Fârâbï (1964, 40).

[431] Endress (1973, 35 of the Arabic text): in ‘alima ma fawqahu ‘alima dhatahu aydan.

[432] Badawï (1977b, 172) and Lewis (1959, 309, translation revised).

[433] Taylor (1981, Proposition 7, 296, 1-5, translation slightly revised).

[434] Endress (1973, 35 of the Arabic text).

[435] See for instance al-Fârâbï (1985a, 100 and 1985b, 61).

[436] Al-Fârâbï (1964, 40) and McGinnis and Reisman (2007, translation slightly revised).

[437] Al-Fârâbï (1985a, 100-101 and 1985b, 61).

[438] For a discussion of‘learned ignorance’ in Theology of Aristotle, see Adamson (2002a, 88 ff.).

[439] Badawi (1977b, 101) and Lewis (1959, 75, translation slightly revised). See also Adamson (2002a, 94 ff.). Cf. with Proclus’ discussion of actuality and potency in Propositions 77-79 of Elements.

[440] See for instance Enneads 5.3.15, and for Mahd al-khayr, Badawi (1977a, Proposition 4, 6-8, Proposition 8, 11-12 and passim).

[441] Adamson (2002a, 94-102). As Adamson notes, the Arabic term quwwah and the equivalent Greek term Svvaprq should be translated as “power” rather than as “potentiality”

[442] Al-Fârâbï (1985a, 70-71 and 1985b, 46-47).

[443] Al-Fârâbï (1964, 34).

[444] The scholarship on the Agent Intellect in al-Fârâbï’s philosophy is broad and includes among other works: Finnegan (1957), Rahman (1958), Walzer (1974), Lucchetta (in al-Fârâbï 1974) Davidson (1972 and 1992), Hamzah (in al-Fârâbï 2001b), Geoffroy (2002), and Vallat (“L’intellect selon Fârâbï: la transformation du savoir en être,” forthcoming).

[445] Al-Fârâbï (1964, 34): wa-amma l-‘aql al-fa“al fa-innahu yaqilu l-awwal wa-l- thawanikullaha wa-yaqilu dhatahu.

[446] Yet al-Fârâbï gives no compelling explanation as to why the Agent Intellect is the tenth intellect and why the series of intellects cannot continue beyond this number.

[447] Al-Fârâbï (1938, 27) and McGinnis and Reisman (2007, 75).

[448] Al-Fârâbï (1964, 33).

[449] Al-Fârâbï (1964, 31).

[450] Al-Kindï and Abu Sulaymân al-Sijistânï (d. 985 CE) also upheld the doctrine of the ensoulment of the orbs. Al-Sijistânï, like al-Fârâbï, equates superlunary soul and form. In his treatise entitled Maqalah fi anna l-ajram al-‘ulwiyyah dhawat anfus natiqah, al-Sijistânï (1974a, 370, my translation) asserts that “the soul [of the celestial bodies], which is their form, move them through volition” (fa-l-nafs, allati hiya suratuha, tuharrikuha bi-l-iradah). It is not possible to know whether al-Sijistânï derived the equation between form and soul from al-Fârâbï’s works or from another text which would have served as a common source, such as Alexander’s Mabadi‘. At any rate, it shows that the identity between soul and form in a cosmological context was widespread among Baghdad philosophers.

[451] Al-Fârâbï (1985a, 59 and 1985b, 38).

[452] Al-Fârâbï (1964, 36-37): fa-inna l-suwar laysa laha qiwam bi-dhawatiha wa-hiya muhtajah ila an takuna mawjudah fi mawdu.

[453] Al-Fârâbï (1964, 37-38) and McGinnis and Reisman (2007, 85, translation slightly revised).

[454] Al-Fârâbï (1938, 20) and McGinnis and Reisman (2007, 73): fa-idha kanat hahuna mawjüdat hiya suwar la fi mawadd wa-lam takun qattu suwaran fi mawadd.

[455] Al-Fârâbï (1938, 24) and McGinnis and Reisman (2007, 74, translation revised): wa-l-‘aql al-fa“al alladhi dhakarahü Arista ta lis fi l-maqalah al-thalithah min kitab al- nafs huwa sürah mufariqah lam takun fi l-maddah wa-la takünu aslan.

[456] Al-Fârâbï (1999e, sec. 66, 142-145).

[457] Al-Fârâbï (2001c, 127).

[458] See for example the excerpts of Proclus arabus in Endress (1973, 12-21), many of which aim to prove the existence of spiritual forms (suwar rühaniyyah). As Adamson (2002a, 140) notes, form plays an important role in the ontology of Theology of Aristotle and is sometimes used to refer to the intelligible world of soul and intellect; see Badawï (1977b, 163) and Lewis (1959, 395) for the statement that God first originated form (sürah) and then created the intellects and souls “through the mediation of this form” (bi-tawassut tilka l-sürah); see also Lewis (1959, 207, 281) for Theology of Aristotle and Sayings of the Greek Sage, and Endress (1973, 12-21) for the Proclus arabus. In the early Arabic tradition, immaterial and intelligible forms are also a hallmark of

the Pseudo-Empedoclean and Ismâ'ilï currents, which made extensive use of works such as Theology of Aristotle. Sometimes, form is said to be the first thing created by God and the principle that subsequently fashions the universe; see Altmann and Stern (1958), Jolivet (1995), De Smet (1995, 219 and 1998). Although al-Fârâbï does not adhere to these metaphysical theories, it is not unreasonable to speculate that he may have been influenced by the emphasis they place on form.

[459] In his discussion of the human intellectual faculties in Fl l-‘aql (1938, 22), al-Fârâbï explains that each level of the human intellect may be conceived of as “form” for the intellect below it and as “substrate” for the intellect above it. Like substrate, form is a concept that appears both in al-Fârâbï’s cosmology and noetics, and one which is used to describe the various faculties of the intellect. Walzer’s conclusion (in al-Fârâbï 1985a, 336) that “the separate intellects are then, in his [al-Fârâbï’s] view, without forms as well,” is therefore not valid if one takes into account Fl l-‘aql.

[460] The following discussion is based chiefly on the first section of Àra (al-Fârâbï 1985a, 56-89 and 1985b, 37-55), which is al-Fârâbï’s most systematic treatment of theology.

[461] Al-Fârâbï (1985a, 70-71 and 1985b, 47). On the other hand, al-Kindï resisted this identification; see Adamson (2007a, 72).

[462] See Propositions 2, 4, and the end of Proposition 8 of Mahd al-khayr in Badawï (1977a) and Taylor (1981), as well as Adamson (2002a, 124 ff.) for Theology of Aristotle. With regard to the One’s relation to intellect, however, Mahd al-khayr seems quite faithful to the Greek texts. See Proposition 8: “and the First Cause is not an intellect, nor a soul, nor a nature, but rather It is above the intellect” (Taylor 1981, 299, transla­tion slightly revised).

[463]    Al-Fârâbï (1985a, 58-59 and 1985b, 38-39). For a discussion of the concept of pure being in Theology of Aristotle, see Adamson (2002a, 124 ff.). For a discussion of existence (mawjudlwujud) and al-Fârâbï’s original contribution to this topic, especially in his K. al-huruf, see Menn (2008).

[464] The First’s simplicity is also stressed by Mahd al-khayr in Proposition 20: “It is simple (basil') to the utmost degree of simplicity” (Taylor 1981, 317, translation slightly revised). It is interesting that al-Fârâbï follows the Proclus arabus in distinguishing between these two aspects of unity.

[465] Al-Fârâbï (1985a, 59 ff. and 1985b, 38 ff.).

[466] Al-Fârâbï (1985a, 66 and 1985b, 44).

[467] For a list of the other epithets applied to the First, such as haqq, hayy, hakim, etc., see al-Fârâbï (1985a, 72-75, 1985b, 46-49, and 1964, 49-51). Interestingly, the term Allah is virtually absent from al-Fârâbï’s metaphysical treatises. This says a lot about the Second Teacher’s philosophical project, which was aimed more at continuing the Greek tradition of reflection on the principles (apyai/mabadi) and causes (amm/asbab/ ‘ilal) of the universe, than at creating a system of thought compatible with the Islamic revelation.

[468] This explains why some homonymous terms may be ascribed chronologically first to things in this world and then to the First, although they apply to the First in a prior sense. Al-Fârâbï’s position clearly relies on the concept of analogy (qiyas) (see al-Fârâbï 1985a, 84 and 1985b, 53), although his short remarks make it difficult to determine what role this concept plays in this context and how it relates to contempo­rary kalam conceptions.

[469] Al-Fârâbï, whose sensitivity to the issue of divine unity must have been stimu­lated by these theological developments as well as by his philosophical training with Christian scholars, clearly marks his stance vis-à-vis this thorny problem. Not only does he reject the attribution of physical or anthropomorphic features to God, but in addition he holds a unitary theory of the divine essence that excludes the existence of attributes that would be distinct from God’s essence and co-eternal with it. While his view bears a striking resemblance to the Mutazilite position, as Walzer (in al-Fârâbï 1985a, 346-348) and especially Rudolph (2007) have shown, this connection can only be regarded as relative, given that al-Fârâbï upholds other metaphysical theses that would have been unacceptable to this theological group, in particular his views on the causative activity of the intellects and his rejection of atomism.

[470] Al-Fârâbï (1964, 34) and McGinnis and Reisman (2007, 83). In making God cog­nizant of all the effects that derive from His essence, it is possible that al-Fârâbï is fol­lowing Themistius’ interpretation of Aristotle’s Prime Mover in his paraphrase of Book Lambda; see Brague (in Themistius 1999, 37-38).

[471] See Sorabji (“Introduction” in Philoponus 1987, 8). Ammonius’ treatise is men­tioned by Ibn al-Nadim (1970, vol. 2, 610) in Fihrist under the title Exposition of Aristotle's Doctrines about the Creator. For the reception of this work in the Greek- Arabic background, see Mahdi (1967), Verrycken (1990a), Bertolacci (2005a), and D’Ancona (2006).

[472] See Badawi (1947, 21, my translation) and Brague (in Themistius 1999, 37), who suggests that this view relies on some of Plotinus’ comments on intellect in Enneads. See also Pines (1987), who discusses the impact of Themistius’ theory on Arabic intel­lectual history, although the author says nothing about al-Farabi.

[473] It is unclear whether according to Themistius, or rather according to the pre­served Arabic and Hebrew versions of his text, the knowledge of the First Principle consists of universals alone or also includes particular things. By being at the begin­ning of the causal chain, the First could know what lies at its end. However, in the absence of specific statements to this effect, the first option seems more likely.

[474] An interpretation as to why these texts uphold such a view will be given in chapter 3. Here I focus mainly on the emanationist works.

[475] Ibn Sïnâ (2005, 288,4), who writes in Metaphysics of Shifa: “the Necessary Existent apprehends intellectually all things in a universal way; yet, despite this, no individual thing escapes His knowledge. ... As for the manner of this, it [takes place] because, when He intellectually apprehends His essence and apprehends that He is the principle of every existent, He apprehends the principles of the existents [that proceed] from Him and what is generated by them.” See also Marmura (1962).

[476] Al-Fârâbï (1971b, 89-90 and 2001a, 55-56).

[477] I am not sure to which extent the slightly divergent proposition to a) given above, i.e., that whatever the First contemplates or reflects upon must necessarily come into existence, is true in al-Fârâbï’s philosophy. Apart from the single piece of evidence in

Siyasah that what the First “intellects [is], in a certain way, all of the existents,” nothing would validate such a view. The statement from Siyasah is furthermore problematic insofar as it does not seem to square comfortably with al-Fârâbï’s general views on the causation of the intellects as described in this same work. Indeed, the main impression one gets from reading the various pages al-Fârâbï devotes to these entities is that their causative activity operates without their cognizance of the lower effects, which are therefore to be seen as metaphysical by-products. In that sense, while (self-)intellection necessarily results in causation, it is not accompanied by the cause’s necessary knowl­edge of the effects that issue from it.

214      See Metaphysics, 12.7.1072a22-24.

215      Al-Fârâbï (1964, 52, 1985a, 118-119, and 1985b, 68).

[480] Al-Fârâbï (2001a, 45).

[481] The latter work in particular opens with a list of principles (mabadi), among which figure the intellects (thawanï), soul (nafs) and matter (maddah) (al-Fârâbï 1964, 31).

[482] Al-Fârâbï (2001c, 129).

[483] I leave the questions open at this point of whether al-Fârâbï achieved this synthe­sis of Aristotelian and Neoplatonic material with a clear perception of the differences between these philosophical traditions and with the cognizance of the true origin of the Neoplatonica arabica. This question will be examined in more detail in chapter 3 in connection with creation and causation.

[484] For an enlightening discussion of causation and multiplicity in the works of Plotinus and Proclus, see Rosemann (1996, ch. 2, 63-103) and Steel (2010). Insight into al-Fârâbï’s views on causation and his relation to the Proclus arabus can be gained from the studies of Maróth (1994, 196-215), Janos (2010a), and Vallat (“Al-Farabi’s argu­ments for the Eternity of the World,” forthcoming). For a comparison with Ibn Sïnâ, see Daiber (2004) and Wisnovsky (2002, 2003a, and 2003b).

[485] See Rosemann (1996, 63-103). As this author aptly puts it, “causality manifests the self-reflexivity of being” (90). This holds not only for Plotinus and Proclus, but also for al-Fârâbï, who partly makes vertical causality in the immaterial realm a product of the self-contemplation of the intellects.

[486] This is because the intellection of this first effect is itself dual and thus introduces a small degree of multiplicity in its essence. Al-Fârâbï’s theory that multiplicity is intro­duced with the first effect proceeding from the First follows the Neoplatonica arabica closely. In Mahd al-khayr, for instance, the author states that “originated being [intel­lect], although it is one, becomes multiple, it receives multiplicity” (Badawï 1977a, 6 and Taylor 1981, 289).

[487] Al-Fârâbï (1964, 40-41).

[488] Al-Fârâbï (1964, 53).

[489] Al-Fârâbï (1964, 40, 53).

[490] Apart from the many remarks dealing with unity and multiplicity that appear in his emanationist treatises, al-Fârâbï’s interest in this metaphysical topic can also be inferred from his authorship of a treatise entitled K. al-wahid wa-l-wahdah. This highly theoretical work discusses in detail the various ways in which something may be said to be one and simple, as well as the various ways in which multiplicity emerges from unity. According to Mahdi (al-Fârâbï 1989, preface) and Walzer (al-Fârâbï 1985a, 339), this work is chiefly an elaboration on some passages of Aristotle’s Metaphysics, Book Delta, while for Vallat (2004, 15, note 1) it may be regarded as a commentary on Book Nu. It is clear in any case that al-Fârâbï is approaching these issues through the media­tion of the Neoplatonic metaphysical tradition, which also delved into the problem of unity and multiplicity at length. As the views expressed in this short treatise are highly abstract, it is difficult to connect them with the cosmological exposition that appears in al-Fârâbï’s emanationist treatises, especially since this work has not been the object of detailed study.

[491] Al-Fârâbï (1964, 44-45) and McGinnis and Reisman (2007, 89).

[492] Mahd al-khayr, and Propositions 4 and 20 in particular, upholds a similar view on the First and most likely represents al-Fârâbï’s direct source of inspiration.

[493] Al-Fârâbï (1989, 48).

[494] Al-Fârâbï (1989, 51-52).

[495] Al-Fârâbï (1989, 51).

[496] As for instance in Ihsa’ and Ara' (al-Fârâbï 1949, 100 and 1985a, 68 respectively).

[497] Al-Fârâbï (1964, 44) and McGinnis and Reisman (2007, 89).

[498] This idea is vital to the Neoplatonists, for whom “what is produced must always be of the same kind as its producer” (Enneads 3.8 [30] 5, 24, quoted and discussed in Rosemann 1996, 89-90); see also Steel (2010). It is also to be found in Mahd al-khayr (Badawi 1977a, Proposition 11, 14), which states: “The primary [principles, al-awail] are all in one another in the mode appropriate for one to be in the other.” The notion of a fundamental similarity between all things surely underlies al-Farabi’s belief in the harmonious order or arrangement of the existents, conveyed through the Arabic terms tartib and martabah. The existents, while similar in some respects, are nevertheless arranged hierarchically according to their degree of perfection and the extent to which they embody the concepts of existence and unity. It should be noted that this concept of similarity is mostly to be associated with the intellectual principles in al-Farabi’s metaphysics and cannot as easily be applied to the causation of the celestial bodies, which are also and problematically described as effects of the separate intellects. This point represents one of the idiosyncracies and perhaps shortcomings of al-Farabi’s theory of causation: how can the bodily orbs be said to be caused by immaterial intel­lects, without even the mediation of soul? The Greek Neoplatonists had made soul the mediator between intellect and corporeality, but the falasifah make both the souls and bodies of the orbs directly dependent on the separate intellects. Although this represents a major problem with respect to their theories of causality, al-Fârâbï, and more surpisingly Ibn Sïnâ, do not address this issue in any satisfactory way.

[499] The relation between the concepts of perfection and final causality has been thor­oughly discussed by Wisnovsky (2002 and 2003, 108-112). In spite of their differences, Proclus and al-Fârâbï agree on the key idea that the perfection of the celestial souls and intellects and their causative activity derive from their intellective act of reversion toward the prior principles.

[500] See the thought-provoking article by Vallat (“Al-Farabi’s arguments for the Eternity of the World,” forthcoming). As Vallat (18) writes: “Farabi regards the final cause as sufficient reason for the existence of its effects, which plainly reduces efficient causality to the final one.” Although this idea is interesting, the evidence in al-Fârâbï’s corpus does not in my view lend itself to such a conclusion. Al-Fârâbï clearly states that the First and the separate intellects are causes of existence (wujud), implying that they must be efficient causes (see al-Fârâbï 1964, 31, 40-41, 52). Moreover, in his Fusul mabadi, al-Fârâbï (1968, 79) states that the First is the efficient (awwalfail), final (ghayah), and formal (surah) cause of all the existents (li-sair al-mawjudat). Finally, Vallat’s argument weakens the strong connection between intellection and demiurgy articulated by Proclus and fully endorsed by al-Fârâbï. Efficient and final

[501]     Al-Kindi (1950-53, 219-220 and 257). Both of these Arabic terms possess basic, non-technical meanings, but they were also appropriated by early Arabic intellectual movements influenced by Greek thought. The root t-y-n, which is of Quranic origin, usually connotes concrete, physical matter. The term tin appears several times in the Qur’an (e.g., 17:61, 38:76, etc.), where it is usually translated as clay; see Wolfson (1947-48). In contrast, ‘unsur, whose primary meaning is ‘race’ or ‘origin,’ assumed a wide variety of senses in a philosophical context and can refer to the concrete elements or to a spiritual kind of matter; see the articles by Netton and Gardet in EI2.

[502]     Al-Farabi (1970, sec. 156, 159).

[503]     For an interesting discussion of ‘unsur and of its place in the Pseudo-Empedoclean tradition, see De Smet (1998); see also Rudolph (1989, 37) and Jolivet (1995). Al-Kindi (1950-53, 166) uses this term in a somewhat idiosyncratic fashion to refer to “the mat­ter of everything,” a definition possibly influenced by Pseudo-Empedoclean ideas. Cf. Wolfson (1947-48).

[504]     The plural form mawadd occurs in many places in the Farabian corpus: al-Farabi (1964, 41, 1938, 19, 1970, 99-100, 1991, 34, and 1992, 63). Ibn Sina also uses this plural, as in Najah (1985, 312,13). It is difficult to perceive any difference in meaning between maddah and hayüla. Unlike hayüla, which is a transliteration of the Greek nTh, maddah is an Arabic term whose original meaning is ‘stuff’ or ‘substance.’ One is tempted to distinguish between a notion of physical, corporeal matter (maddah) and one of mate­rial potency (i.e., matter as potency, hayüla), but this distinction does not seem to be vindicated by the textual evidence in any consistent fashion. One of the reasons for this is that in the sublunary world, there is an almost perfect equation between matter and potency.

[505]     For example, in Ihsa’ and Radd, maddah designates Aristotle’s aether; see al-Fârâbï (1949, 96) and Mahdi (1967, passim).

[506]     This is true not only of al-Fârâbï’s philosophical treatises, but also, and more sur­prisingly, of his account of Aristotle’s philosophy in Falsafat Aristii ta lis and of his defense of aether in Radd.

[507]     The question of how to interpret Aristotle’s aether is controversial and puzzled most of the late antique commentators, just as it puzzles modern historians. Exactly what kind of matter aether is, the role it plays in celestial motion, the extent to which it is reconcilable with the theory of unmoved movers in Book Lambda, and whether there are several grades of aether are questions that are still unclear; for more informa­tion, see Jaeger (1948), Moraux (1963 and “Introduction” in Aristotle 1965), Strohmaier (1996), and Guthrie (2000, xv ff.). Throughout intellectual history, evidence gleaned from various Aristotelian texts was assembled to defend very different interpretations. Aristotle calls aether the “first body” and often discusses it as if it were another element, albeit with different properties, as in On the Heavens 1.2-4. Moreover, the celestial bod­ies are visible, and Aristotle equates visibility and materiality. These points suggest that Aristotle conceived of aether as something material and corporeal. But in Metaphysics 12.2.1069b25, he suggests that the heavens may have matter that should be understood exclusively as potency for motion in place, while at 8.4.1044b5-8 he suggests that some natural and eternal beings, i.e., the celestial bodies, may have no matter, or, again, only matter for motion in place. This ambiguity in the Aristotelian doctrine was used as a starting point for subsequent Peripatetic and Neoplatonic elaborations on the question of celestial matter.

[508]    Al-Fârâbï (1949, 34). This passage and the one preceding it are in brackets in this Arabic edition and do not appear in all manuscripts.

[509]    Al-Fârâbï (1961a, 99,5-11 and 1969, 104, translation slightly revised).

[510]     Davidson (1992, 48, 63-64) has already noted this particularity of al-Fârâbï’s interpretation of aether.

[511]     Al-Fârâbï (1972, 273), Mahdi (1967, 254, translation slightly revised).

[512]     Al-Fârâbï (1985a, 120, translation slightly revised, and 1985b, 69). The use of analogy in this passage suggests that Walzer’s translation of the previous sentence wa-hadhihi tujanis al-mawjudat al-hayulaniyyah as “these [celestial bodies] belong to the same genus as the material existents” is an inadequate literal rendition of the Arabic text. As Siyasah (al-Fârâbï 1964, 31) clearly states, the heavenly bodies belong to another genus from that of the sublunary existents. A more accurate translation of tujanis would be “resemble” or “are like.”

[513]     Al-Fârâbï (1985a, 120-123 and 1985b, 70-71): the substrates do not “prevent their forms from thinking and from being intellect in their essences.”

[514]     Al-Fârâbï (1964, 31).

[515]     Al-Fârâbï (1964, 53).

[516]     Al-Fârâbï (1964, 41).

[517]     Al-Fârâbï (1985a, 109 and 1985b, 64).

[518]     Al-Fârâbï (1985a, 114-115 and 1985b, 67).

[519]     Al-Fârâbï (1985a, 58-59 and 1985b, 38, my emphasis).

[520]     Al-Fârâbï (1985a, 123, translation slightly revised, and 1985b, 70).

[521]     Al-Fârâbï (1938, 33). A few lines below, al-Fârâbï mentions that the celestial bod­ies provide the Agent Intellect with both the matters (mawadd) and the substrates (mawdüat) on which it acts (al-Fârâbï 1938, 34). By substrates, al-Fârâbï probably has in mind the faculties of the human intellect that are actualized by the Agent Intellect and which are not properly speaking material.

[522]    This is also Druart’s (1999, 218b) conclusion: the celestial bodies, she writes, “have neither form nor matter in the proper sense and, therefore, are not subject to the hylo- morphic composition.”

[523]    Al-Ghazâlï (1997, 73-76).

[524]    Al-Ghazâlï (1997, 4-5).

[525]    This lack of discernment is, of course, in line with the polemical character of the work; on this issue, see Griffel (2005).

[526]    Maimonides (1963, vol. 2, 309). For an analysis of Maimonides’ theory of celestial matter, see Glasner (2000, especially 320-323).

[527]    Maimonides (1963, vol. 2, 309).

[528]    Sambursky (1962, 154 ff.) and Pines (1979, vol. 1, 179-180).

[529]    These fragments were published by Birkenmajer (1935).

[530]    This, at any rate, is how Maimonides seems to understand al-Fârâbi’s argument; see the general context in Maimonides (1963, vol. 2, 302 ff.) on eternity and creation.

[531]    In Ibn Rushd’s Talkhis (1984a, 183, 15-17, my translation); cf. Endress (1995, 36).

[532]    This is also how Wolfson (1929, 596) understood this passage.

[533]     Ibn Rushd’s statement that “there is no disagreement among the commentators [al-mufassirin]” indicates that he may be referring to one of al-Fârâbï’s commentaries, possibly the latter’s no longer extant commentary on On the Heavens. However, since the view that the heavenly bodies lack a material substrate is also clearly developed in the mature emanationist treatises, it is also possible that Ibn Rushd had these works in mind.

[534]     I borrow the expression ‘curricular works’ from Reisman (2005, 69, note 9) to refer to those works in which al-Fârâbï exposes the doctrine of other philosophers, especially Aristotle, and in which he describes the scientific curriculum he inherited from the Alexandrian tradition.

[535]     This dual conclusion is quite close to the way in which Themistius interpreted Aristotle’s aether. In a passage of his paraphrase of Book Lambda preserved in Hebrew, Themistius (1999, 122) writes: “Il faut en effet, ou bien, que l’on dise qu’ils [the celestial bodies] n’ont pas de matière du tout, ou que l’on dise que la matière qui est la leur est autre que la matière des choses qui admettent la génération et la corruption.”

[536]     These principles are enumerated at the beginning of Siyasah; see al-Fârâbï (1964, 31).

[537]     Al-Fârâbï (1985a, 122-123 and 1985b, 70).

[538]     Siorvanes (1987, 234-237, 239-246).

[539]     Al-Fârâbï (1971b, 78 and 2001a, 45).

[540]     See Fi l-'aql, for example (al-Fârâbï 1938, 22).

[541]     Walzer in his commentary on Àra (al-Fârâbï 1985a, 370, and 375-376) went so far as to ascribe a theory of intelligible matter to al-Fârâbï: “Al-Fârâbï is quite aware that Aristotle had introduced a fifth element, aether, being the element from which the stars are made, but he deliberately abandoned the Peripatetic dogma by substituting for aether the ‘quinta essentia,’ the neo-Platonic ‘spiritual intelligible matter’, the noete hyle, and making it in turn the ‘cause’ of the four elements.” But this interpretation is not without its problems. First, al-Fârâbï does not use the standard expressions associated with theories of intelligible matter in the Arabic tradition, such as ‘unsur awwal and hayula ula wahmiyyah. 'These terms appear, for example, in the doxography of Pseudo- Ammonius (Rudolph 1989, 37) and the K. al-islah of Abu Hâtim al-Râzï (1998, 39) respectively. In the first work, which ascribes the doctrine of intelligible matter to Empedocles, ‘unsur awwal is described as “the first of the simple intelligible [things]” (awwal al-bastt al-maqul). Second, Walzer seems to have misunderstood the exact status of intelligible matter in the Neoplatonic legacy that he claimed was bequeathed to al-Fârâbï. He unjustifiably equates intelligible matter with celestial matter, thus passing over the fact that for most Neoplatonists intelligible matter is not the matter of the heavens. According to Plotinus, for example, the heavens are made of a pure kind of fire, but intelligible matter belongs to the intelligible world that is emanated directly from the One and represents a proto-stage of the formation of the Intellect. Hence, for Plotinus, intelligible matter pertains to the level of the Intellect, whereas celestial matter is emanated from the Soul and is situated below it in the hierarchy of being. This is also how most thinkers in the Arabic tradition seem to have understood intelligible matter: they make it an emanation of the First Cause, sometimes even, as in the case of the Doxography of Pseudo-Ammonius, the very first intelligible being to proceed from God. The entry on Empedocles in this work reads: fa-abda‘a l-shay al-basit alladhi huwa awwal al-basit al-maqul wa-huwa l-‘unsur al-awwal (Rudolph 1989, 37). That Walzer’s theory contains a flaw in this regard cannot be ignored.

[542]     On the Heavens 1.9.278a11 ff. (translated by Stocks in Aristotle 1941). See also Metaphysics 1.8.990a1-5.

[543]     In Philoponus’ Against Aristotle, as reported by Simplicius in his On the Heavens commentary, 133,21-29. It is likely that Philoponus’ criticism is addressed to Proclus and other Neoplatonists, who often describe the heavens as being immaterial (avkov).

[544]     See al-Kindï (1950-53, vol. 2, 55), Atiyeh (1966, 73-74), and Adamson (2007a, ch. 4).

[545]     Al-Kindi (1950-53, 169). Al-Kindi further defines 'unsur as the “matter of all matter,” a formula which is tantalizingly reminiscent of the Pseudo-Empedoclean sources, but which in this context probably refers to the physical, concrete matter of all corporeal things. Al-Kindi also uses the plural ‘anasi r to refer to the four elements fire, air, earth, and water in his K. fi ibanah, 219-220. That al-Kindi uses the same term to signify both terrestrial elements and the matter of the heavenly orbs is interesting, and may betray the influence of Philoponus, who held the view that the heavens were made of the same elements as sublunary beings, albeit of a purer kind.

[546]     See Ibn Sina’s Al-sama wa-l-‘alam in Shifa (1983-1986, 15,6; 30, passim; 31,2-3), Risalat al-‘ulwiyyah (id. 1908, passim), Najah (id. 1985, 313), the Metaphysics of Shifa (id. 2005, 312, 324, 330, 331, 334), and M. Rashed (2004, 41). For Maimonides, see Wolfson (1929, 103, 605-606) and Glasner (2000).

[547]     For an overview of this exegetical tradition, see Sambursky (1962, 124-127, 154 ff.), Wildberg (1988), Verrycken (1990b), and M. Rashed (2004).

[548]     Mahdi (2001, 4) writes that “the cosmology and the politics presented in them [Ára and Siyasah] differ in the two works.” In spite of Mahdi’s claim, al-Fârâbï’s descrip­tions of the heavenly bodies show a remarkable degree of consistency. This suggests that these treatises were composed during the same period.

[549]     See Dunlop (in al-Fârâbï 1961b, 9-17) and Alon (2002, vol. 2, 824-826), who notes that Dunlop, Najjar, Rosenthal, and Walzer all agree that these works are al-Fârâbï’s last compositions; see also Galston (1990, 4, note 2), who provides a clear overview of past scholarly opinions on the topic, as well as Reisman (2005, 54-55) and Gutas (1982a); finally, Vallat (“L’intellect selon Fârâbï: la transformation du savoir en être,” 7, forthcoming) considers Ára, Siyasah, and Fusül to be late compositions.

[550]     As far as I know, al-Kindï does not use the concept of substrate (mawdu') in a cosmological context.

[551]     Physics 1.6.189a35; On Generation and Corruption 2.1.329a30-33; Metaphysics 1.2.983a30, 7.3.1029a20-26, and 12.2.1069b3-8.

[552]     to 7«p èv rotç Qeiotç ñnoKeípevov oô% wop CAG, vol. 1, 22.2-3, translated into English by Dooley (in Sorabji 2005, vol. 2, 369); ènet Kat to kvkXo^opikóv nôua ^Voikov pév, où urp' w.p to toÓtm ñnoKeípevov, CAG, vol. 1, 169.18-19, translated into English by Dooley (in Sorabji 2005, vol. 2, 369).

[553]     eniznrqoai xiç av npoç touto nepi xœv eroœv xœv ev toit Oetoiç oœpaoiv. xawa yàp owe ewXa owe q>9aprà Kai %œpioxà xp ènivoia tou ñnoKeipevou awoîç oœpaxoç, CAG, vol. 1, 375.37-376.2; translated into English by Dooley (in Sorabji 2005, vol. 2, 369).

[554]     De mixtione, 229.3-9, translated into English by Todd (in Sorabji 2005, vol. 2, 366).

[555]     Bodnár (1997, 190).

[556]     CAG, vol. 5, 14.12-15, in the Latin version, translated into English by Sorabji (in Sorabji 2005, vol. 2, 369, translation revised). This statement could be the one Ibn Rushd had in mind when discussing the concept of substrate among the commentators in his Middle Commentary on On the Heavens.

[557]     Themistius 1999, 10.12, 122: “Il faut, en effet, ou bien, que l’on dise qu’ils [the celestial bodies] n’ont pas de matière du tout, ou que l’on dise que la matière qui est la leur est autre que la matière des choses qui admettent la génération et la corruption.”

[558]     Siorvanes (1987, 234-237, 239-246).

[559]     My analysis of the link between al-Fârâbï and the Greek commentators should ideally be complemented by a study of al-Fârâbï’s interpretation of On the Heavens. There is a twofold problem, however: first, al-Fârâbï’s commentary on On the Heavens has not survived; second, there is no reliable edition of the Arabic translation of this work made by Ibn al-Bftrïq. Yet it is likely that a close examination of the doctrines conveyed in the Arabic On the Heavens could yield interesting information concerning the cosmology of the falasifah in general and al-Fârâbï’s theory of celestial substance in particular. An indication of this is Endress’ statement (2007, 346) that Ibn al-Bitriq’s version “gave a specifically Neoplatonic slant to the Aristotelian text: rendering Aristotle’s 9etov nóua by al-jirm al-karm or al-jirm al-ruham, ‘the noble, spiritual body.’ ” For more information on the Arabic On the Heavens, see Endress (1966).

[560]     Not only does Aristotle describe aether as the “first body,” but in On the Heavens, 1.9.278a11 he clearly correlates perceptibility and materiality when speaking about the heavens. Indeed, without matter, the motion of the orbs would be difficult to explain. Simplicius argues in his commentary on On the Heavens (CAG, vol. 7, 133,29 ff.) that by “immaterial,” these philosophers really mean to say that celestial matter is different from and “surpasses” the matter of generation and corruption. However, this interpre­tation seems to be influenced by his own view on the topic, which makes a serious concession to the ‘materialistic’ understanding of celestial matter as defended by Philoponus.

[561]     See Fazzo (2002, 113 ff.). Fazzo provides an in-depth analysis of Alexander’s views on celestial matter in Quaestiones. Although she emphasizes the complexity of the topic and acknowledges the contradictions between Alexander’s views in his commentary on Metaphysics and in this work (123), she does not attempt to explain this discrep­ancy. But it should be stressed that the authorship of Quaestiones is uncertain, and so this raises the possibility that the theories expressed in them are not those of Alexander. See also Bodnár (1997, 190-191, and notes 3 and 4). In any case, only fragments of Quaestiones were translated into Arabic, and there is no indication that 1.10 and 1.15— the two sections that focus on the question of celestial matter in most detail—were among the passages translated. On the other hand, the translation of at least parts of Alexander’s commentary on Metaphysics is attested by Ibn al-Nadïm. The aim here is not to provide a detailed account of Alexander’s and Themistius’ views, but rather to show that they could have served as a starting point for al-Fârâbï’s own elaboration.

[562]     In his commentary on On the Heavens, CAG, vol. 5, 14,12-15; cf. Sorabji (2005, vol. 2, 369).

[563]     CAG, vol. 1, 22,2-3, translated by Dooley (in Sorabji 2005, vol. 2, 369). See also Fazzo (2002, 123). Alexander does not specify in this passage what the nature of this substrate is. But since he equates the nature of the celestial bodies with their soul, it may be hypothesized that his notion of substrate should be construed in light of his psychology. Accordingly, it could be somewhat similar to the potential intellect in humans, which, while immaterial, acts as a substrate for the intelligible forms.

[564]     In Ft l-‘aql, al-Fârâbï explains that the “substrates [mawduat] on which the Agent Intellect acts are either bodies or powers [quwan] in bodies” (1938, 33-34, my transla­tion). From this passage, it may be inferred that the concept of substrate is broader than the concept of body and that some substrates may be in bodies without necessarily being material. Accordingly, al-Fârâbï claims that each faculty of the human soul may be seen as a “substrate” (mawdu) for the faculty above it, including the various levels of the intellect (1938, 22).

[565]     For Alexander, see Bodnár (1997, 190, note 1); for al-Fârâbï, see chapter 4 of this study on celestial motion.

[566]     Badawï (1987, 114, 117-118) and Luna (1989, 250). Some aspects of this trans­mission, however, are complicated. First, there is no way of knowing if the idea of an immaterial heaven was developed in Alexander’s commentary on On the Heavens, since it has survived neither in Greek nor in Arabic. As for the works by Alexander previously discussed, Ibn al-Nadïm mentions only Alexander’s and Themistius’ com­mentaries on Book Lambda of Metaphysics, and al-Fârâbï in Aghrad confirms that his knowledge of their commentaries was limited to this book. He writes: “there is an incomplete commentary on Book Lambda by Alexander of Aphrodisias and a com­plete commentary by Themistius” (McGinnis and Reisman 2007, 78). There is, there­fore, no direct evidence that al-Fârâbï had access to Alexander’s entire commentary on Metaphysics, although this possibility cannot be excluded.

[567]     Ibn al-Nadïm (1970, vol. 2, 606).

[568]     Aristûtâlïs (1964, vol. 1, 139) and McGinnis and Reisman (2007, 123, my empha­sis, translation slightly revised).

[569]     The similar terminology, and especially the term shibh, used by Abû Bishr and al-Fârâbï to compare the celestial substance to sublunary matter and their agreement that the heavens are not strictly speaking material indicate a direct link between these two thinkers on the issue of celestial matter.

[570]     Wildberg (1988, 3). For information on the excerpts of Philoponus’ works pre­served in Arabic and their impact on Islamic thought, see Kraemer (1965), Davidson (1969), Pines (1972), Hasnawi (1994), Wisnovsky (2001), Hugonnard-Roche (2003, 288-289), and M. Rashed (2004).

[571]     For an in-depth treatment of this topic, see Pines (1936) and Dhanani (1994).

[572]     Abu l-Barakât al-Baghdâdï, for example, believed that the heavens are composed of several matters, like Maimonides. For the former, see Pines (1979, vol. 1, 170-180, vol. 5, 214-215), and for the latter, Glasner (2000).

[573]     The remaining fragments of On Changing Beings have recently been analyzed by M. Rashed (2008); for Radd, see Mahdi (1967, 236).

[574]     For al-Râzï’s metaphysics, see Pines (1936, 49), Gaudefroy-Demombynes (1941), Fakhry (1968), and McGinnis and Reisman (2007, 44-49), who translated later Arabic accounts on al-Râzï’s philosophy.

[575]     This view shares affinities with the prime matter of the Ikhwân al-Safâand of many Ismâ'ilï thinkers. Although prime matter in their philosophy does not consist of atoms, it represents the material matrix out of which all the heavenly and terrestrial existents are made. At first glance, al-Râzï’s doctrine of matter appears to be close to the kalam doctrines of occasionalism and atomism, but it diverges from them radically in defining prime matter as an eternal, uncaused substance that lies outside the creative power of God.

[576]     In the Timaeus (31B-32B, and especially 40A) the heavens are said to be made of a pure version of the four elements with a preponderance of fire.

[577]     This work is mentioned by al-Qiftï in Tarikh al-hukama (al-Qiftï 1903, 280) under the title Al-radd ‘ala l-Razi and by Ibn Abï Usaybiah (1965, 608) under the title Kitab al-radd ‘ala l-Razi fi l-‘ilm al-ilahi; see also Najjar (2004, 31).

[578]     For Philoponus’ conception of prime matter, see de Haas (1997) and the relevant sections in Sorabji (2005, vol. 2); for his theory of celestial matter, see Sambursky (1962, 154 ff.), Wildberg (1988, 187-236), and M. Rashed (2004).

[579]     Wolfson (1929, 100-104), Hyman (1977 and his comments in Ibn Rushd 1986, 29-32); and Stone (2001).

[580]     For a brief overview of prime matter in Arabic philosophy, see Gardet EI2. The idea that prime matter is one of the highest ontological principles can be found in many Ismâ'ïlï, Pseudo-Empedoclean, and early doxographic sources. In some cases, prime matter is even described as an intelligible principle or an intelligible form ema­nating directly from the One or the Intellect. See Abu H âtim al-Râzï (1998, 30-31); the entry on Empedocles in the Doxography of Pseudo-Ammonius (in Rudolph 1989, 37). Jâbir ibn Hayyân’s view seems quite unique, although it also posits one source for all matter. He makes substance or dust (al-haba) the stuff out of which everything is made (see Haq 1994, 55). Theology of Aristotle also presents a similar view: “all bodies, by reason of their being bodies, are of one matter [min hayüla wahidah]”; “... because the matter of all bodies is one” (Badawï 1977b, 126 and Lewis 1959, 183-185). A quick glance at these sources suffices to stress the gap between their conception of prime matter and al-Fârâbï’s.

[581]     Al-Fârâbï (1964, 55).

[582]     Al-Fârâbï (1938, 33-34).

[583]     That prime matter is restricted to the sublunary world is explicitly stated in Siyasah: fa-l-maddah al-ula hiya bi-l-quwwah jami al-jawahir allati tahta l-sama (al-Fârâbï 1964, 54).

[584]     The causedness of prime matter in al-Fârâbï’s and Ibn Sïnâ’s philosophies was already noticed by Duhem (1913-59, vol. 4, 474, 488-490), who nevertheless does not explain its relation to the matter of the heavenly bodies. See also Davidson (1992, 47-48).

[585]     Al-Fârâbï (1964, 58). This bi-polar ontological hierarchy with the First at one end and prime matter at the other is reminiscent of Proclus.

[586]     This conclusion may be reached in spite of the fact that scholars still disagree on the exact nature of prime matter in Aristotle’s philosophy. For an incisive discussion of this question, see Charlton (1992, 129-145), who also provides a useful summary of the previous scholarship on the topic (146-147).

[587]     In Philoponus (1987, 22).

[588]     Al-Fârâbï’s treatise Radd establishes a correlation between aether and circular motion (see al-Mahdi 1967, 253-254), which is nonetheless made on behalf of Aristotle. The Second Teacher’s aim in this treatise is clearly apologetic, i.e., to explain Aristotle’s theory of the elements and defend it against what he sees as an unjustified attack mounted by Philoponus. More will be said about this treatise in section 2.1.2.

[589]     It should be noted, however, that Ptolemy himself perceived no contradiction between aether and the observed diversity of planetary motions, since he refers to and endorses a variant of aether in his astronomical works; see for instance Almagest 1.3 H14.

[590]     For the philosophical background to these elaborations, see Verrycken (1990a) and Sorabji (2005, vol. 2, 164-168), and for the Arabic context, Bertolacci (2005a) and Wisnovsky (2003b and 2005).

[591]     Lameer (1994, 23-39) and M. Rashed (2008, 55-58; 2009). As an alternative to al-Fârâbï’s authorship, Rashed proposes to attribute Jam' to either one of the two Ibn Adï brothers, Yahyâ and Ibrâhïm, but more likely to the latter, who was well acquainted with the Second Teacher. I arrived at a similar conclusion in an earlier article (Janos 2009) regarding the potential role of Yahyâ ibn Adï in the composition or compilation of Jam' and Jawabat, and I thus partly share the ongoing scholarly skepticism regarding the authorship of these works. However, unlike Rashed, I also entertained in this article the parallel hypothesis that these works could have been composed by al-Fârâbï him­self during the early Baghdad phase of his life. This hypothesis will be further explored in the following discussion. As for Lameer, he discusses the authenticity of three works in his book: ‘Uyun, Jam', and Jawabat. While he defends the authenticity of ‘Uyun, he considers Jam' completely spurious, and argues that Jawabat somehow reflects al-Fârâbï’s doctrine and may be the work of a student or a later scribe imbued with Fârâbïan philosophy. My own assessment of these sources is diametrically opposed to that of Lameer. I believe that a close examination of the cosmology and metaphysics of ‘Uyun indicates that it should be attributed to Ibn Sïnâ’s circle if not to the shaykh al-rais himself (see appendix 1). On the other hand, I believe that Jam' and Jawabat are to be connected with al-Fârâbï, either as authentic treatises composed by the Second Teacher or as later redactions, which, nevertheless, convey his original ideas.

[592]     See notably Mallet’s response to Lameer (in al-Fârâbï 1999e, 37 ff.), Martini Bonadeo (in al-Fârâbï 2008, 28 ff.), D’Ancona (2010), and Endress (in the preface to al-Fârâbï 2008, x-xi, xiii). The latter seems to regard Jam' as one of al-Fârâbï’s early works, although he does not provide any arguments to support this view.

[593]     This evidence consists, first, of the very ‘Fârâbïan’ themes discussed in this work, such as the various types of discourses and their correspondance to various groups in society, the comparison between religion and philosophy, the religious function of philosophy, and the proper use of certain groups of technical terms, to mention only a few (al-Fârâbï 1999e, 136-141); second, of the concept of philosophical harmoniza­tion, which, in spite of the claim made by some scholars, is in fact typical of al-Fârâbï’s approach to philosophy (for explicit statements to this effect, see the end of Tahsil and the beginning of Falsafat Arislulalis in al-Fârâbï 2001c, 50 and 71 respectively, as well as Endress 1991 and Martini Bonadeo’s introduction in al-Fârâbï 2008). This harmo­nizing approach is obviously a continuation of the late antique Neoplatonic program, and was a main feature of the thought of Porphyry, Ammonius, and Simplicius, among others (see for instance Baltussen 2010 on Simplicius); third, of the many textual paral­lels between Jam' and some of al-Fârâbï’s other works, especially his logical treatises (see, for instance, Mallet’s notes in al-Fârâbï 1999e, 161); and fourth, of the unanimous ascription of this treatise to al-Fârâbï by Arabic historiographers and Ibn Sïnâ. Moreover, there are the affinities between the cosmological views articulated in Jam' (especially with regard to the creation of the world and matter) and those put forth in other works attributed to al-Fârâbï, notably Jawabat, as well as some of his logical trea­tises. This point will be examined in depth in the following pages and integrated in an overarching developmentalist hypothesis. It must be admitted that since the Arabic tradition unanimously ascribes these treatises to al-Fârâbï, and since there are obvious doctrinal parallels between them and the Second Teacher’s other works, the onus of proof lies with those who challenge their authenticity. The above remarks are merely meant to remind one of the risk incurred in rejecting Jam' from the Fârâbïan corpus, regardless of whether one accepts the developmentalist framework outlined in the forthcoming discussion.

[594]     Thus, while M. Rashed (2009) argues that the cosmological doctrines of Jam' and Jawabat are radically different from those articulated in al-Fârâbï’s emanationist works and therefore clearly point to the spuriousness of these treatises, Martini Bonadeo (al-Fârâbï 2008, 194 ff.) and D’Ancona (2010) are of the opinion that these doctrines are reconcilable with the emanationist framework developed by al-Fârâbï. As will appear clearly later on, I agree with M. Rashed on this point, but unlike him, I do not take this as an indication of the spuriousness of Jam' and Jawabat.

[595]     Janos (2009a); cf. M. Rashed (2009). The present section on al-Fârâbï’s ‘creation­ist’ treatises builds on my article, but also departs from it in many ways, as some of my views on key concepts, especially on the relation between time and creation, have been modified.

[596]     This expression literally means “not from something,” and it has sometimes been contrasted to min la shay. For insight into, and a particular interpretation of, these concepts in the Greek, Jewish, and Islamic contexts, see Wolfson (1970 and 1976, 355 ff.). See also Lizzini (2009) for the Arabic tradition.

[597]     Al-Fârâbï (1999e, 129,14-17).

[598]     Al-Fârâbï (1999e, 128-129 and 136-137, my translation): wa-l-‘alam mubda‘ min ghayr shay in fa-malahu ila ghayr shay in.

[599]     Al-Fârâbï (1999e, 135).

[600] Al-Fârâbï (1999e, 130-131): wa-hunaka tabayyana anna l-hayula abdaaha l-bari ... la ‘an shay, wa-annaha tajassamat ‘an al-bari‘ jalla jalaluhu wa-‘an iradatihi thumma tarattabat. The citations from Theology of Aristotle in Jam' may have been culled from the Proclus arabus; for a discussion of this point and relevant references to the secondary literature, see Aouad (1989, 582).

[601] See for instance Timaeus 37D: “he brought order to the universe,” and 53B: “the god fashioned these four kinds [i.e., the elements] to be as perfect and excellent as pos­sible.” Al-Fârâbï mentions Timaeus on several occasions in Jam'. He invokes the author­ity of Plato, for instance, to explain the necessary existence of an efficient cause for the world’s creation (1999e, 132-133). The Platonic connection may also be seen in al-Fârâbï’s use of the term Uriah, which may have been influenced by the matter or receptacle (ÉKpayeiov) of Timaeus 49A and 50C, and which, to my knowledge, is not used by al-Fârâbï in his other works (1999e, 133-135). However, tinah could also derive from the Quranic tin, 3:49, 38:76, etc.

[602] Al-Farabi (1999e, 131, 137).

[603] Al-Farabi (1992, 317-319).

[604] Philoponus (1987, 1141,15-30).

[605] Philoponus (1987, 1142,21-25).

[606] Philoponus (2005b, 158,25-159,1).

[607] In addition to the excerpt of Theology of Aristotle cited above, one may enumerate the following features: the description of God as an efficient cause (‘illah failah) and the mention of the treatise by Ammonius on this subject; and a common language of creation expressing “absolute creation all at once and not over a period of time” (ibda dafatan bi-la zaman). See also Zimmermann (1986, 178 ff.) and Mallet (in al-Fârâbï 1999e, 50 ff.).

[608] The idea put forth by some scholars, especially Mallet EI2, Martini Bonadeo (al-Fârâbï 2008, 194-199), D’Ancona (2010, 889), and Lizzini (2011, 142, note 3), that the cosmology of Jam' and Jawabat is based on the concept of eternal emanation and is reconcilable with al-Fârâbï’s later metaphysical works is undermined by this crucial difference. As was made clear, the author of these works argues that the world is tem­porally finite and will come to an end, whereas al-Fârâbï’s doctrine of causation as expressed in Ara' and Siyasah is to be understood within an eternalist framework. In addition, the terminology used in these works to describe God and creation differs significantly. The main allegiance of the author of Jam' and Jawabat was not to the Neoplatonica arabica—even though he draws on this corpus—but rather to the Philoponian tradition and its rejection of the thesis of eternity. Hence, while I uphold the authenticity of Jam' and Jawabat, I at the same time recognize their specificity in the Fârâbïan corpus and separate them from the later emanationist works.

[609] Badawï (1977a, 4-5).

[610] Such an interpretation was proposed by Fattal (2008, 99 ff.), who argues that al-Fârâbï in section 74 of this work treats intellect as a hypostasis or as a separate entity distinct from the divine essence on the Neoplatonic model. However, in this passage, ‘intellect’ is discussed in the context of human noetics and not as a separate entity that would be distinct from both human beings and the divine essence.

[611] Al-Fârâbï (1999e, 147).

[612] Al-Fârâbï (1999e, 149-151).

[613] Al-Fârâbï (1999e, 133): ajza' l-alam al-jismaniyyah minha wa-l-ruhaniyyah.

[614] Wildberg (1988 and in Philoponus 1987) has collected and translated all the known fragments of Philoponus’ Against Aristotle.

[615] It is interesting that the debate thus centers on the notion of skopós (aim or inten­tion) of the work, which was also a notion important to Simplicius and many other Greek thinkers. The skopós of On the Heavens was particularly debated in late antiquity, as is apparent from Simplicius’ survey of the issue in the prologue to his On the Heavens commentary.

[616] See Mahdi (1967) and al-Fârâbï (1972).

[617] Mahdi (1967, 238).

[618] Mahdi (1967, 253).

[619] Martini Bonadeo (al-Fârâbï 2008, 192-193); cf. Janos (2009b, 237 ff.).

[620] Mahdi (1967, 252).

[621]     Mahdi (1967, 236): “He [al-Fârâbï] upholds Aristotle’s position that the world as a whole is not subject to generation and destruction. And he reconciles this position with the doctrine of the creation of the world by proposing with Ammonius that Aristotle’s doctrine of movement and time does not exclude the possibility that the world as a whole, together with time, were created from nothing by a God who is the world’s final and efficient cause”

[622] Ibn Rushd mentions this treatise on several occasions in his corpus. The relevant passages have been collected by Steinschneider (1869/1966, 119-123), but they provide little insight into the original work. M. Rashed (2008) on the other hand furnishes a detailed study of these excerpts and is able to reconstruct some of al-Fârâbï’s original arguments.

[623] In On the Heavens 1.3.270a12-35 Aristotle explains that the first body or aether is both ungenerated and indestructible, while at 1.3.270b1 ff. he describes its divine nature and refers to the empirical evidence showing that no change takes place in the heavens. See also Wildberg (1988, 12 ff.) on the connection between aether and eternity.

[624] Mahdi (1967, 253); M. Rashed (2009, 78-79).

[625] Wildberg (1988, 14-15).

[626]     These passages indicate that al-Fârâbï was sensitive to this problem even with regard to the question of the world’s eternity, which he mentions explicitly in one of his examples in K. al-jadal (1985c, vol. 3, 81,15-82,4, and ch. 1, 3.1 of this book).

[627]     This fact seems to have puzzled R. Sorabji, who writes (in Philoponus 1987, 20): “Surprisingly, he [al-Fârâbï] thinks that Philoponus is wrong to ascribe to Aristotle belief in the eternity of the physical world.” A similar conclusion, but in connection with motion, can be made about al-Fârâbï’s other critical writings on Philoponus, such as On Changing Beings. As M. Rashed (2008, 36) writes, “there is no evidence that al-Fârâbï tried to give a positive proof of the eternity of the heavens [in On Changing Beings]” a fact which M. Rashed describes as a “curious absence.” This being said, how­ever, al-Fârâbï definitely seems to defend the eternity of motion and time in this work.

[628]     See Martini Bonadeo’s commentary (in al-Fârâbï 2008, 192-194) and D’Ancona (2006, 401-405). Cf. the similar line of thought followed independently by Janos (2009b, 237 ff.) and M. Rashed’s criticism (2009, 78 ff.).

[629] Al-Fârâbï (2001a, 154).

[630] Mahdi (1967, 253) and note 124.

[631] Al-Fârâbï (1999e, 130-131).

[632]     As Mallet notes (in al-Fârâbï 1999e, 180, note 2), this may be a reference to On the Heavens 3.2.301a10 ff.

[633]     See al-Kindï’s treatise entitled On the Proximate Efficient Cause in McGinnis and Reisman (2007, sec. 12.3, 5) and Adamson (2007a, 86-88).

[634]     The parallels between al-Kindï and al-Fârâbï on this topic naturally raise the question of influence, which is rendered more complex by the fact that they had access to similar sources, which included, in addition to the Aristotelian corpus, works by Alexander and pseudo-Alexander, Theology of Aristotle, and other texts from the Neoplatonica arabica. Although al-Fârâbï does not mention al-Kindï by name, it is undeniable that his views as expressed in Jam', Jawabat, and Radd bear some resemblance to al-Kindi’s cosmological doctrines. More specifically, al-Kindi’s works may have been the source for al-Farabi’s reconciliation of a version of aether and crea­tion during this period of his life. However, the possibility that the two thinkers inde­pendently reached a similar position by relying on identical sources cannot be excluded.

[635] At first glance, creation ex nihilo and the Arabic On the Heavens would seem to have little in common, but a detailed study of the doctrinal variations between the Greek and Arabic versions is required in order to answer this question. If one may rely on the edition prepared by Badawi, aether is described as follows: “it is necessary to consider that this noble body [aether] is neither generated nor corrupts”; and “as for this first noble body it did not originate from anything” (wa-'ala hadha l-mithal bi-‘aynihïyanbaghi an yutaqada anna hadha l-jirm al-karim ghayr kain wa-la fasid, andfa-amma hadha l-jirm al-awwal al-shariffa-lam yatakawwan min shay albattatah) (in Badawi 1961, 139-140). The first quotation closely follows the original text of On the Heavens at 270a13 ff., which reads: “It is equally reasonable to assume that this body will be ungenerated and indestructible” (translated by Stocks in Aristotle 2001). But it is possible that some Arabic readers understood the gist of these passages and espe­cially the term “ungenerated” not in the sense that aether is an eternal and uncaused substance, but rather that it is a substance that is not generated over a period of time, as are certain sublunary bodies, for instance, and that it is not a substance generated out of or from (min) something else. In other words, it would seem that, in spite of stressing the ingenerabillty and incorruptibility of aether, these passages could be rec­onciled with the doctrine of creation all at once and in no time. Judging from al-Kindi’s dual theories of creation and aether, it is most likely in this fashion that he read On the Heavens.

[636] This interpretation of Radd naturally raises the question of al-Fârâbï’s knowledge of the contents of On the Heavens. It is possible that some of the crucial passages in al-Fârâbï’s version of the Arabic On the Heavens connecting aether with eternity were left out, adapted, or modified by the translators, so that the compatibility between aether and creation was foreshadowed in this text. A clearer knowledge of the Arabic versions of On the Heavens accessible to al-Fârâbï would in any case go a long way in explaining the formation of his cosmogonical views. The problem is that the Arabic translations of On the Heavens have not yet been properly edited, and little work on this seminal text has been conducted. The edition published by Badawï (1961) is gener­ally considered unreliable. Endress (1966) represents the only general study of the transmission of On the Heavens and its reception in the Arabic world. Further research on this subject is a desideratum.

[637] Gutas (1983).

[638] Al-Fârâbï (1949, 99-101).

[639] Bertolacci (2006, 76, and 79 ff.).

[640] Consequently, Druart’s (2005, 334) suggestion that al-Fârâbï is exposing in the third, theological part of the Ihsa survey all the metaphysical issues that he plans to tackle and that he believed were left unaddressed by Aristotle seems improbable. If this were true, then it would imply that al-Fârâbï believed Aristotelian metaphysics to be limited exclusively to the general study of existents and their accidents and to the search for the first principles of the sciences, and never to have included theology and the immaterial existents as part of its subject matter, even though it represents the ultimate objective of this science in al-Fârâbï’s view. But as the above division of the text shows, sub-section 1 of part three, which deals with theological matters and the imma­terial beings and whose inquiry culminates with the postulation of the First, is clearly a summary of Book Lambda. More generally, al-Fârâbï never explicitly criticizes Aristotle’s alleged metaphysical shortcomings in any of his works. Finally, there are strong reasons to believe, as Jam' has already indicated, and as will be shown shortly in the case of Ihsa' as well, that al-Fârâbï regarded the inquiry into procession or the downward movement away from the First as belonging to Aristotle’s metaphysics as well. As a result, the reason why al-Fârâbï dwells on the theological part of metaphysics is precisely because he thought it had been covered in depth by Aristotle and repre­sented the crowning achievement of this philosopher’s system.

[641] Mallet (in al-Fârâbï 1999e, 183, note 3) interprets this passage of Jam' as referring to the “last” book of Metaphysics, by which I assume he means Book M, whose contents are described by al-Fârâbï in Aghrad (1999c, 38,5-6). While possible, this suggestion seems highly unlikely, first, because al-Fârâbï has just mentioned and discussed 'Theology of Aristotle in the preceding section as a genuine Aristotelian work, and sec­ond, because Books M and N focus mostly on mathematical objects and the forms. Hence, one hardly sees how, in al-Fârâbï’s view, these books could have provided an adequate and detailed discussion of the relation between the individual substances and God, especially since al-Fârâbï follows Aristotle in rejecting the extramental existence of mathematical objects and locates the forms in the divine essence in Jam'. The com­parative table above shows that the parallels between Jam' and Ihsa’ cannot be merely coincidental. Since the Theology of Aristotle underlies the metaphysical account pro­vided in Ihsa’, the same would appear to be true for Jam' as well, which otherwise explicitly ascribes this work to the Stagirite. Hence, the evidence overwhelmingly indicates that al-Fârâbï is referring to Theology of Aristotle and perhaps to other works from Neoplatonica arabica when he mentions the descent from the First in this passage of Jam'.

[642] It is, I believe, in reaction to the works of some of the first scholars of Islamic intellectual history, such as B. Carra de Vaux and T. de Boer, that Mahdi, Druart, Galston, and others, made adamant efforts to argue that al-Fârâbï clearly distinguished Aristotle’s true writings from the Neoplatonica arabica and had a lucid conception of Aristotelian metaphysics. This reaction is understandable, as it may have seemed improper to uncritically endorse a thesis associated in many ways with a biased and Eurocentric kind of scholarship. But the evidence adduced above indicates convinc­ingly that, in spite of obvious shortcomings, the view of these early scholars should be taken seriously. At least during his ‘early Baghdad phase,’ al-Fârâbï attributed Theology of Aristotle and other Neoplatonic works to Aristotle and perceived Aristotelian meta­physics as a comprehensive discipline dealing with both the ascent to the First and Its creation of the other existents.

[643] With regard to Ihsa, the above analysis thus agrees with the conclusion of Gutas (1983, 260), reached through a study of the logical contents of this work: “Logic and grammar, philosophy and religion, are shown by al-Fârâbï to be complementary parts of the same system, not posited as contradictory parts in two different systems.”

[644] Badawï (1977b, 135,11-12 and passim).

[645] Al-Fârâbï (1999c, 35,11-12).

[646] Bertolacci (2006, 65 ff.).

[647] Al-Fârâbï (1999c, 34,8-9). This again is the view of those scholars who divide the Fârâbïan corpus into ‘Aristotelian’ and ‘Neoplatonic’ works.

[648] Al-Fârâbï (1999c, 35) and McGinnis and Reisman (2007, 79). This statement would seem excessive if al-Fârâbï were limiting God’s role to that of a final cause.

[649] The meaning and translation of the Arabic term huwiyyah have long been debated by scholars (see Goichon EI2). This term appears frequently in the Ustâth translation of Metaphysics and in the Neoplatonica arabica, where it is sometimes applied expressly to God (see Adamson 2002a, 124 ff.). In many cases it seems to refer to a kind of ‘unity of existence,’ which the First possesses absolutely, and which all the other beings possess in a derived sense and as a result of the power of the First; see for instance Mahd al-khayr (Badawï 1977a, Proposition 17, 19). McGinnis’ and Reisman’s (2007, 81) translation of ithbat huwiyyatiht as “It establishes its identity” does not, in my view, capture the true sense of this statement, nor does it emphasize the important connection with the ontology articulated in the Neoplatonica arabica. Because of the many parallels between this corpus and al-Fârâbï’s creationist treatises, there can be little doubt that, as in Jam' and Ihsa’, he is in this case as well relying on some of these texts, both in his use of the term huwiyyah and in his defining God as a principle of existence for the lower beings. Al-Fârâbï’s use of this word strengthens the hypothesis that he had access to a recension assembled in the Kindï-circle, which combined texts from the Neoplatonica arabica and the Ustâth translation.

[650] Al-Farabi (1999c, 38,2-4).

[651] Adamson (2002a, 154, and note 59).

[652] The idea that the immaterial beings were created and are also subject to destruc­tion is difficult for us to imagine, given that they lie beyond time and, hence, that their activity transcends temporal generation and corruption. But if the developmentalist hypothesis defended here is correct, one must acknowledge the possibility that al-Fârâbï did adhere at one point in his life to the theory of the absolute creation and destruction of both the material and intelligible levels in the sense that neither is actually eternal. Since the underlying assumption is that al-Fârâbï very gradually evolved from a crea­tionist model to one of eternal causation at the very end of his life, a transitional period containing certain tensions or even contradictions from our modern viewpoint cannot be excluded.

[653] See notably Atiyeh (1966), Jolivet (1993) and Adamson (2002b and 2007a).

[654] Al-Kindi (1998, 145,12; 147,4; 169,13).

[655] Al-Kindi (1998, 145,18-19; 169,7; 171,5).

[656] Al-Kindi (1998, 145,12). I am following Adamson (2003, 59) for the translation of ‘an lays as “from non-being.”

[657] See for instance al-Kindi (1998, 143,13-14; 155,10-12).

[658] Al-Kindi (1998, 179,19-23; 181,6-7; 189,6-9).

[659] Al-Kindi (1998, 187,14-15,20-22; 189,1).

[660] Al-Kindi (1998, 141,11-15).

[661] Al-Kindi (1998, 155,11-12).

[662] For the connection between Philoponus and al-Kindi on creation, see Davidson (1969), Adamson (2003), and Janos (2009a, 10-11). One key difference is al-Kindi’s view that the heavens are made of a special incorruptible element, as Philoponus rejected this idea and famously criticized Aristotle’s theory of aether.

[663] Saadia Gaon (1891, 1,3-5; 11,16-17; 34,8-9 of the Arabic text and 1976, 41 ff.).

[664] Wolfson (1959) provides an overview of the different interpretations concerning Israeli’s theories of creation and emanation. Much of the disagreement centered on the artificial opposition of creation ex nihilo and emanation, which Wolfson reconciles in his article. But see the reply by Altmann (1979), and for a more recent treatment, Levin and Walker (2008).

[665] Altmann and Stern (1958, Fragment V, 91; sec. 8, 126; sec. 6, 46,22-24).

[666] Wolfson (1959, 12): “What we have here in Israeli is a theory of a volitional and presumably also non-eternal process of emanation in which the first emanated being is described as having been created ex nihilo” Levin and Walker (2008) agree with Wolfson on Israeli’s rejection of eternity.

[667] Altmann and Stern (1958, Definitions 42 and 49, pages 66 and 77 respectively). Scholars have emphasized the many parallels between al-Kindi and Isaac Israeli, including their views on creation; see Altmann and Stern (151 ff.) and Levin and Walker (2008): “Although explication of the nature of God is absent in the surviving fragments of Israeli’s philosophical corpus, it is apparent that Israeli, like the Muslim philosopher al-Kindi before him, combined the Neoplatonist notion of God as the source of emanation of all things, with the idea common to the monotheistic religions, of a willful Creator who created the world in time. In blending these two conceptions, these philosophers rejected the Aristotelian conception of the eternity of the world, as well as the idea of eternal emanation of some of the Greek Neoplatonists.”

[668] See Aristûtâlïs (1964, vol. 1, 110-211). This edition also contains the notes of Yahyâ ibn Adï, Ibn al-Samh, and Abû l-Faraj ibn al-Tayyib. Part of Mattâ ibn Yûnuscommentary has been translated into English, first by Lettinck (1994) and subsequently by McGinnis and Reisman (2007, 122-128). See also Hasnawi (1996) for a study of the excerpts conveyed by Abû Amr al-Tabarï, one of Mattâ ibn Yûnusdisciples.

[669] Arislnlalis (1964, vol. 1, 138, 140-141, 147, and 151).

[670]     The use of these terms would be utterly unaccountable if Matta ibn Yûnus believed, as Brown (1972, 44-45) seems to claim, that God is only a final cause of motion, and not a real efficient cause of existence. Brown argues that the concept of “efficient nature” (al-tabi‘ah al-fa“alah) this Christian thinker adopts deprived God of true efficient agency, and that this is what triggered Ibn Sina’s later criticism. In fact, Matta ibn Yûnus clearly subordinates this “efficient nature” to the agency of God, stating that it is spread in the world “on account of the creator” (min qibal al-khallaq, 147). Matta ibn Yûnus’ digression on efficient nature seems to be merely an extension, as Brown also notes, of Alexander’s views, as they appear for instance in Mabadi‘ (Alexander 2001, 113). Moreover, the disagreement referred to by Brown between Matta ibn Yûnus and Ibn Sina as expressed in the latter’s commentary on Book Lambda (Badawi (ed.) 1947, 26) seems to focus on how the modality of “necessity” (darurah) can be applied to celestial motion, i.e., whether the circular motion of the heavens is necessary due to another being or due to its very nature. But this issue does not in any way entail Matta ibn Yûnusdenial that God is an efficient cause for the world’s existence. In this sense, Brown’s article seems to be conflating several different issues. One should remember that Ibn Sina based his entire metaphys­ics on subtle modal distinctions, such as ‘possible’ and ‘necessary,’ which he developed or which were not used in such an elaborate form by his predecessors. In any case, we know very little about Ibn Sinas controversy with the Baghdad school, and with Matta ibn Yûnus in particular, so that it seems unreasonable to draw far-reaching conclusions concerning the latter’s philosophy from the Avicennian sources.

[671] Aristûtâlïs (1964, vol. 1, 141, 148).

[672] Aristûtâlïs (1964, vol. 1, 167-169).

[673] Aristiipilis (1964, vol. 1, 148).

[674] Aristiipilis (1964, vol. 1, 141).

[675] It is possibly partly in reaction to these early interpretations of potential infinity and to their accommodation within a creationist model that Ibn Sina decided to pro­vide a more refined conceptual distinction between potential and actual infinity; on this point, see M. Rashed (2005, 298-302). Indeed, Ibn Sina redefines the meaning of these concepts in his philosophy and seems to have adhered to a “weak version” of the world’s actual eternity, perhaps in an attempt to distance himself from these early thinkers and their ambiguous interpretation of potential infinity.

[676]     See Pines (1972). This short treatise focuses on Philoponus’ argument from the finitude of bodies and their power. The gist of this argument as reported in the sum­mary is as follows: “If the world is a finite body ... and if the forces of every finite body

are finite ... then the world must have been created in time and have come into exist­ence after not having existed” (Pines 1972, 323-324). This simplified proof relies on some of Aristotle’s comments in Book 8 of Physics, which it employs against the eter­nity thesis of the Stagirite by establishing a direct equation between finitude and crea­tion. What is particularly noteworthy for our purposes is the attitude that the author of this summary displays vis-à-vis the notion of an infinite power. According to him, the fact that the world receives the infinite, divine power does not in any way imply its eternity, for the crucial distinction according to him rests on having an infinite power inherently or by nature versus being the recipient of an external power, infinite or not. In the latter case, contingency and creation must be posited regardless of the duration during which this power acts; see Pines (1972, 324). Interestingly, this connects with al-Kindi’s views on creation, finitude, and the indeterminate temporal duration of the world. It suggests that although Matta ibn Yûnus posits an infinite power in his expla­nation of the world and motion, this does not necessarily imply a corollary belief in the eternity of the world. Indeed, he could very well, like the author of this summary and al-Kindi, have reconciled the doctrine of infinite power with the doctrines of creation ex nihilo and the temporal finitude of the world. Hence, the fact that the notions of finitude-infinity are often subsumed within a larger cosmogonical paradigm leads to various subtle transformations in their meaning depending on a thinker’s overarching aim.

[677] On the other hand, al-Kindi, al-Farabi, and probably Matta ibn Yûnus do not endorse Philoponus’ critique of the Aristotelian theory of aether and his view that the heavens are composed of a perishable substance, since they all uphold the incorrupti­bility and immutability of celestial matter. Al-Kindi is to my knowledge the first thinker in Islam to combine a variant of the aether theory with the notion of the world’s crea­tion and temporal finitude. In the case of Matta ibn Yûnus, this view is reported by Abû ‘Amr (AristCitalis 1964, vol. 1, 166, and Hasnawi 1996), according to whom Matta ibn Yûnus included the study of the “fifth body” (al-jirm al-khamis) in the physical inves­tigation. This is one of the many technical terms used by Arabic thinkers to refer to aether or a variant of this theory. There is unfortunately no way of learning more about how Matta ibn Yûnus conceptualized this celestial substance.

[678] Lettinck (1994, 129, 197, 201, 208, and passim).

[679] In this view, there would be essential parallels between the cosmological doc­trines of al-Kindi and at least some of the Baghdad Peripatetics, such as Matta ibn Yûnus and al-Farabi in some of his works. While the secondary literature has rightly stressed the different philosophical outlook of these thinkers, few in-depth studies have been carried out on the cosmological and metaphysical doctrines of the Baghdad Peripatetic thinkers (except al-Farabi), and so it is unclear to what extent their cosmo­logical system relates to that of al-Kindi. The present analysis suggests that the connec­tion might be stronger than previously thought. What is more, the creationist doctrines discussed above should also be compared anew to those of al-Farabi’s later works and Ibn Sina’s philosophical summae. Here again one would find many points of agree­ment. All of these thinkers agree that creation itself is atemporal, since time is con­comitant with body and motion and is measured by the heavenly revolution. The main difference would lie in the fact that al-Kindi, Saadia Gaon, possibly Matta ibn Yûnus in his commentary, and al-Farabi in Jam', uphold the temporal finitude of the world and its future destruction by God, whereas the mature al-Farabi and Ibn Sina do not. These thinkers would also agree that during its existence (finite for the former, infinite for the latter), certain phenomena such as heavenly motion and sublunary generation and corruption are regular, continuous, and potentially perpetual, meanings conveyed by the term daim. Although this term is ubiquitous in their works, it possesses different semantic nuances depending on how they construe the notion of potential infinity. Finally, they all uphold the similar view of a celestial substance that is unchangeable and incorruptible and therefore also potentially eternal. As far as I can see, then, three key criteria of differentiation between these views can be identified. First, the presence or absence of a clearly articulated thesis of the world’s beginning and destruction and of its temporal finitude. This thesis is articulated explicitly by al-Kindi in his works and by al-Farabi in Jam' and Jawabat, and it may very well underlie Matta ibn Yûnusviews in his Physics commentary, although he does not make any explicit statements to this effect. On the other hand, al-Farabi in his later treatises and Ibn Sina in his main philo­sophical works are silent about a beginning and an end to the world’s existence. Moreover, they interpret the Last Judgment and the resurrection of the bodies allegori­cally. Second, these thinkers’ interpretation ofpotential and actual infinity. For instance, the proposition of the potential infinity of motion and time is interpreted by al-Kindi as meaning that the world is not eternal and as the opposite to actual infinity. For al-Kindi, potential perpetuity or infinity does not imply eternity, but finitude. In con­trast, for Ibn Sina, potential infinity implies eternity, and with regard to the world, Ibn Sina is even willing to apply to it a “weak version” of actual infinity; see M. Rashed (2005, 298-302). Third, the better known opposition between divine will and neces­sary causality, discussed extensively by al-Ghazali in his Tahafut al-falasifah, for instance. I am perfectly aware that in presenting the following interpretation I am departing quite markedly from most accounts on creation in medieval Arabic thought and from the common tendency to oppose both al-Kindi and Ibn Sina to the Christian Peripatetics. While it is true that there are crucial differences between these thinkers, it appears that some of these differences have been unduly exaggerated, while others have barely been noted. As the previous analysis shows, their views on creation, time, and infinity are extremely intricate and require a careful, case by case examination.

[680] Badawi (1977a, 243-247). The Arabic title of this treatise is: Maqalah Abl l-Khayr al-Hasan ibn Suwar al-Baghdadi fl anna dalll Yahya l-Nahwi ‘ala hadath al-‘alam awla bi-l-qubul min dalll al-mutakallimln aslan.

[681] Badawi (1977a, 247).

[682] This is the view I myself reached in a previous article; see Janos (2009a, 6). Additional research into the creationist theories of early Arabic authors has led me to reconsider this position.

[683] Badawi (1977a, 246): lam yalzam an yakuna l-jism qadiman. Ibn Suwar also endorses the Arabic adaptation of Philoponus’ proof from the limited power of bodies, which ends with the conclusion: “hence, the world is not eternal [laysa bi-sarmadiyyin]”

[684] Badawi (1977a, 247).

[685] Again, I must stress that my interpretation of the view of creation exposed, e.g., in Ibn Suwar’s treatise, departs from that of many other scholars, who infer from the statement of the atemporality of creation and from the qualification of God as a cause (sabab) that what we are dealing with here is essentially an account of eternal creation or causation similar to the one articulated later by al-Farabi in his mature treatises as well as by Ibn Sina. I believe, for my part, that this conclusion should be resisted. For these creationist thinkers seem to be using the term sabab in a looser way, and

without the implication that the world is necessarily an eternal effect emitted by God. Indeed, as can be seen clearly in the cases of al-Kindi, of Isaac Israeli, and of al-Farabi in Jam', the idea that God is a cause of the world’s existence is juxtaposed with the ideas that God willed the world to exist, that the world is temporally finite, that it has a beginning and an end, and that it originated from nothing or non-being and will return to non-being. Accordingly, these thinkers’ emphasis on the instantaneity and atempo- rality of creation is not meant to express a doctrine of eternal creation—whatever this is supposed to mean—but rather the more simple and relevant point that God’s act of creation did not elapse over a period of time and hence cannot be compared to the way in which bodies are generated in time. In this regard all of these thinkers provide the standard example of a sublunary body, such as a plant, which requires time to be gener­ated and grow. In my view, this basic argument is primarily aimed at the literalist read­ing of the creationist account in the Old Testament and the Qur’an championed by some traditionalists, according to whom God’s creation of the world extended over several days. Clearly, al-Kindi, al-Farabi, and Ibn Suwar are opposing this view. However, far from being a statement of eternal creation, theirs is a clarification of the way or mode in which God originated the world, which draws on philosophical notions, but ultimately aims to provide a correct exposition of the fundamental reli­gious tenets of creation ex nihilo and of the world’s temporal contingency. In this case, then, atemporality should not be correlated with eternal creation.

187     On Ibn Adi and creation and how this thinker fits in the context under discus­sion, see M. Rashed (2009) and Janos (2009a, 7-8).

[687] Al-Farabi either cites the Quran explicitly or refers to it implicitly on numerous occasions in Jam‘ (1999e, sec. 59, 137; sec. 67, 145) and Jawabat (1992, 315). It is not surprising that we also find this juxtaposition of the ‘creationist paradigm’ and heavy reliance on scripture in al-Kindi’s treatises and in Saadia Gaon’s commentary on the Book of Creation. This method of reconciling philosophy with religious doctrine seems to have been a defining feature of the ‘Kindi-circle,’ as it is also found in the works of his disciples; on this point, see the interesting article by Rowson (1990, especially 65 ff.). No such intention can be found in al-Farabi’s later works, at least when it comes to his metaphysical and cosmological theories.

[688] There are, of course, notable differences as well, particularly al-Farabi’s redefini­tion of theology as only one part of metaphysics. But even this point should not be overemphasized. For as the account in Ihsa’ clearly shows, theology and the study of divine things occupy the most important place in the metaphysical project and also represent its culmination and overarching aim.

[689] See Zimmermann (1986, 131), whose study represents the most sustained attempt to reconstruct the genealogy of Theology of Aristotle and its original form in the Kindi-circle. This hypothesis also seems substantiated by the fact that al-Farabi relied on Ustath’s version of Metaphysics, which was originally part of this file; see Endress (1997a) and Bertolacci (2005b).

[690] At any rate, it was Wolfson’s (1959, 12) view that this thinker defends a thesis of non-eternal creation.

[691] Adamson (2002a, 145, and note 59).

[692] Adamson (2002a, 145).

[693] The brevity of the metaphysical descriptions of Ihsa’ and Aghrad prevents any decisive conclusions in this regard, but this could very well be the view put forth in these works, i.e., that the corporeal and immaterial worlds were created all at once by God and will also perish. This would account for the postulation of various immaterial existents and for the strong creationist language and emphasis on divine omnipotence found in these works. The fact remains that on stylistic and doctrinal grounds, they are closer to the creationist treatises than to the emanationist ones.

[694] This conclusion has also been reached by other scholars with regard to al-Fârâbï’s logical treatises, many of which presumably belong to this ‘early Baghdad phase’ as well and display a similar approach. As Gutas (1993, 48, 50) writes, al-Fârâbï’s aim was to “acclimatize Greek philosophy to Arab/Muslim society” and to “incorporate Greek sci­entific methodology, i.e., Aristotelian logic, into Islamic sciences.” As the above analy­sis showed, the same may be said about his theology and cosmology.

[695] It remains unclear to what extent al-Fârâbï’s own interest in the relation between religion and philosophy—apparent throughout his corpus, but formulated in different ways depending on his philosophical period—was indebted to his Christian teachers and the time he spent in the learned Syriac circles in Baghdad. Some scholars have argued that the main political concepts and themes found in al-Fârâbï’s works and traditionally defined as ‘Fârâbïan’ par excellence may not have been elaborated by al-Fârâbï himself and were widespread in the cosmopolitan and multi-religious envi­ronment that was ninth- and tenth-century Baghdad, although they flourished espe­cially in the Christian circles; see Watt (2007) and Griffith (2007).

[696] The question remains why al-Fârâbï is almost completely silent about Aristotelian metaphysics in Falsafat Aristu ta lis. The hypothesis that the work is incomplete has been put forth, but it is more likely, in my view, that al-Fârâbï intended to expound on this science in other treatises, as in his K. al-wahid wa-l-wahdah (al-Fârâbï 1989). Ibn al-Qiftï (1903, 280) also attributes a K. fi l-‘ilm al-ilahi to the Second Teacher, which is nonetheless not extant.

[697] Al-Fârâbï (2001c, 102 and 129 respectively and 1961a, 130,13-14).

[698] Al-Fârâbï (2001c, 128).

[699] In spite of this, anyone reading Falsafat Aristíttdits will be struck by the discretion with which the issue of the eternity of the world is treated. Neither in the section on On the Heavens with respect to aether, nor in the section on Physics with respect to time and motion does al-Fârâbï emphasize this central Aristotelian tenet. It is possible to explain this oddity by arguing that al-Fârâbï is concealing Aristotle’s eternalist doctrine for ideological or political reasons. But this interpretation seems unconvincing, for the concept of eternity does appear briefly in several places in this work, although in no case is it the subject of an extensive discussion. Had it been al-Fârâbï’s primary inten­tion to conceal the doctrine of eternity, he would have omitted these passages alto­gether. Rather, one may offer another interpretation. Falsafat Aristittdlts is actually quite representative of al-Fârâbï’s approach to the problem of creation and eternity, which fully acknowledges the difficulty of this problem and is reluctant to provide elaborate positive proofs to support it. As was intimated in chapter 1, 3.1, al-Fârâbï perceived the question of the eternity of the world as an aporia that could not be answered in any general way, but which required careful analysis of its various compo­nents or aspects. The initial problem—in this case the world’s eternity—has to be divided into individual issues or problems, and these issues should in turn be exam­ined one by one by resorting to the appropriate discipline. Falsafat Aristittdlts, like these other Fârâbïan works, seems to implicitly adopt this approach.

[700] Galston (1977) and Druart (1987a) are the main exponents of this view. According to them, Falsafat Aristittdlts is al-Fârâbï’s Peripatetic work par excellence and shows no contamination of Neoplatonic doctrine.

[701]     Al-Fârâbï (1961a, 122 and 2001c, 122). In a very Neoplatonic manner, al-Fârâbï writes (1961a, 129,9-10) that Aristotle had to examine whether this Agent Intellect should not be regarded as the “cause of the existence of soul and of psychological things” (sababflwujud ... al-nafs wa-l-ashya l-nafsaniyyah).

[702]     Al-Fârâbï (2001c, 128-129). The structure of this entire part of the treatise is revealing. It proceeds from an analysis of nature, to soul, to intellect, and arranges these concepts in a neat hierarchical order, betraying a Neoplatonic framework. This is sup­ported further by the doctrinal parallels between this work and the emanationist treatises.

[703] On this point, see also Vallat (2004, 129 ff.).

[704] Naturally, there is the possibility that al-Fârâbï could be defending the view of the potential infinity of time and motion in a way similar to al-Kindï and possibly Mattâ ibn Yunus, and thus that he would not uphold the eternity of the world in this treatise. However, its many parallels with the emanationist works and particularly the language of causation one finds in it suggest otherwise.

[705] Al-Fârâbï (1981b, 62-63, my translation). In this convoluted passage, al-Fârâbï seems to be referring to the First as al-wujüd, a term normally used to express the universal concept of existence, and which, to my knowledge, is not employed in a simi­lar way in his other treatises. The general meaning of this quotation is nevertheless clear, as it oulines the rank and essential priority and posteriority of the thawant.

[706] Cf. al-Fârâbï (1985a, 101-105, 112-115 and 1985b, 61 ff.).

[707]     Al-Fârâbï (1981b, 63). Studying the activity ofthese intellects will also enable the philosopher to acquire “knowledge of the most remote causes of the existents” (ma'rifat al-mawjüdat bi-aqsa asbabiha).

[708]     The passage in question (al-Fârâbï 1938, 34-35), which is a valuable piece of evidence, was already briefly mentioned in chapter 1 and will be further discussed in chapter 4 with regard to celestial motion.

[709] Druart (1987a, especially 25), where the author claims that the last sections of Fl l-‘aql “do not speak of emanation.” Indeed, the term fayd does not appear here, but this passage explicitly speaks of the final and efficient causation of the separate intellects and stresses their status as causes of existence for the celestial orbs, which is a major elaboration on Aristotle’s cosmology. As will be argued shortly, al-Fârâbï did not develop a special concept of “emanation” that can be distinguished from his general theory of efficient and final causation.

[710] Al-Fârâbï (1985a, 88-89, 94-97, translation revised, and 1985b, 55 ff.).

[711] Janssens (1997) and Lizzini (2011).

[712]     See for instance Goichon (1938, 290-291), who translates fayd as “débordement,” “écoulement,” “flux”; cf. Madkour (1934, especially 73 ff.), Walzer (in al-Farabi 1985a, 354-355), Fakhry (2002, 77 ff.), Druart (1987a and 1992), Netton (1989, 114-149), Hasnawi (1990), and Lizzini (2011), whose book is largely devoted to this concept in Ibn Sina’s philosophy, but also contains interesting information on al-Farabi.

[713]     Al-Farabi’s terminology of causation overlaps with that of Neoplatonica arabica, especially Proclus arabus, and there can be little doubt that he relied partly on this cor­pus to elaborate his metaphysical vocabulary. I will not address the question here of whether these works attribute different meanings to these roots, and will limit the anal­ysis to al-Farabi. For further insight into this issue and comparative analyses, see Hasnawi (1990), Janos (2010a), and Lizzini (2011, passim). The root f-y-d appears in most of the Arabic Neoplatonic works, as in Theology of Aristotle (Badawi 1977b, 27, 61 and passim) and Mahd al-khayr (Badawi 1977a, 2, 7, and passim). It is unclear how al-Farabi came to adopt the root l-z-m as the main verbal construction of his mature metaphysics. This root appears only sparsely in Mahd al-khayr (Badawi 1977a, Proposition 1, 4 and Taylor 1981, 284-285), although it seems to convey a meaning close to the one expressed in al-Farabi’s works: “And when the second cause detaches itself from its effect, the First Cause does not separate Itself from it, because the act of the First Cause is greater and stronger in terms of entailment [or necessity, a'zam wa- ashadd luzuman; Taylor’s translation of luzuman as “adherent to” seems to weaken the meaning of the sentence] vis-à-vis the thing than the act of its proximate cause.” In both Mahd al-khayr and al-Farabi, this root seems to express logical entailment and necessary causality.

[714] Indeed, the sun and source analogies, as used for instance by Plotinus in Enneads 1.7.1, are absent from al-Fàràbï’s metaphysical descriptions of the First. It should be noted that the other terms frequently used to express the concept of emanation in the Neoplatonica arabica and in the Arabic works influenced by this corpus, especially the terms inbijas and inbi'ath, are absent from al-Fàràbï’s treatises. On the other hand, al-Fàràbï (1986, 81) uses the rarer verb hadatha ‘an in one instance in his metaphysical account of Fusul mabadi‘. At first glance this might appear more surprising, since this term was commonly used in the theological tradition to express creation ex nihilo in time, and since it also appears in al-Fàràbï’s early creationist works. But in this case as well, al-Fàràbï seems to use it synonymously with the other verbal constructions to express eternal causation, and it is thus virtually impossible to perceive any significant variation in meaning.

[715]     This is one of the rare doctrines shared both by al-Fàràbï’s creationist works and his late metaphysical treatises, but atemporal creation or causation means something quite different in both instances. As we have seen, in the case of Jam' and Jawabat, it is merely meant to distinguish God’s creation from the accounts given in scriptures, which describe the time period during which God created the various parts of the world, and which was construed literally by many Christians and Muslims. Atemporal creation is, moreover, combined with the notion of the temporal finitude of the world, i.e., that the world has both a beginning and an end. In the late metaphysical works, in contrast, it is merely meant to qualify a causal activity that is essentially tied to the intellection of the immaterial beings and that unfolds in an atemporal sphere.

[716]     This tension, I believe, is also a direct outcome of the historical development of al-Fârâbï’s metaphysics as argued in this book. It will be exacerbated by the following discussion of the causation of the separate intellects.

[717]     The term divine (ilaht) should, especially from this point onward, be understood as applying to all the immaterial entities of al-Fârâbï’s cosmology, and not just to the First. This is the sense conveyed in Tahstl (1981b, 63), when he defines the separate intellects as the “divine principles” (al-mabadi‘ l-ilahiyyah).

[718] See Janos (2010a) and chapter 2, 2.1-2.

[719] Al-Fârâbï (1985a, 100-101, 1985b, 61, and 1964, 32).

[720] Cf. Goichon (1938, 364-365) with respect to Ibn Sïnâ’s metaphysics.

[721] Al-Fârâbï (1964, 31).

[722]     Al-Fârâbï (1964, 31-32) and McGinnis and Reisman (2007, 82, my emphasis). The verbal construction hasala ‘an is also used in this work in a similar context and

conveys virtually the same meaning as lazima ‘an.

[723] Al-Fârâbï (1964, 53). This is, to my knowledge, the only occurrence of the root f-y-d in connection with the separate intellects and the celestial bodies in al-Fârâbï’s works. Yet, this single occurrence is sufficient to show that Walzer’s claim (in al-Fârâbï 1985a, 355-356) that this term possesses a special meaning and that al-Fârâbï reserves it to express the creation of the first effect by God is incorrect. This root also appears in Mahd al-khayr (Badawï 1977a, Proposition 4, 7; Proposition 23, 24; Taylor 1981, 290, 321) and Liber de causis II (Thillet and Oudaimah 2001-2002, Proposition 12, 330­331), sometimes in connection with the principle of intellect, but it seems to serve merely as a way to emphasize its role in mediation. McGinnis and Reisman (2007, 94) do not translate the terms yafidu min that appear in al-Fârâbï’s Siyasah as “emanate from,” but as “bestow the existence of,” thus transforming the verbal construction into a transitive one. This choice, however, seems unjustified, for in this case the verbal form would have to be yüfidu. At any rate, McGinnis and Reisman’s translation rightly avoids, in my opinion, the term ‘emanation’ and thus implicitly questions the singular­ity of this concept in al-Fârâbï’s philosophy.

[724]     Badawï (1977a, 5-6, 19). For insightful discussions of the concept of mediation in Mahd al-khayr and Liber de causis, see D’Ancona (1995), andin Theology of Aristotle, Adamson (2002a, 137 ff.).

[725]     As mentioned above, the fundamental meaning attached to these verbs is one of atemporal causation expressing a necessary connection between a cause and its effect. Although the translation offada ‘an as “to emanate” will be preserved in this book for the sake of terminological diversity and to avoid repetitions, no special metaphysical meaning will be attributed to this root, and it will be treated as a synonym to lazima ‘an and the other terms expressing causation and logical entailment. The fact that al-Fârâbï does not limit the root f-y-d to the First, and the fact that it carries no special meta­physical meaning invalidate the attempt made by some scholars to divide the Fârâbïan corpus into Neoplatonic and Aristotelian works. For if emanation is collapsable into the more fundamental concept of efficient causation, then this concept also appears in works deemed ‘Aristotelian’ by these scholars, such as Ft l-‘aql and Falsafat Arisl.ul.(ilis to a lesser degree. In any case, al-Fârâbï’s allegiance to Neoplatonism should not be limited to this issue. In light of recent studies on al-Fârâbï’s noetics and metaphysics, such as Geoffroy (2002), Vallat (2004), and Janos (2010a), as well as the many parallels between al-Fârâbï’s doctrines and Proclus arabus that are highlighted in this study, one may justifiably call some aspects of al-Fârâbï’s metaphysics and noetics Neoplatonic, regardless of the place of ‘emanationism’ in it.

[726] In this respect, al-Fârâbï also differs from other Arabic thinkers who adapt their terminology according to their metaphysical hierarchy. This is the case of al-Kirmânï, for instance, who reserves the term ibda when speaking about God’s creation, but uses other terms to describe the causation of the intellects; see De Smet (1995, 147 ff.).

[727] In this connection, the two references to al-Fârâbï given by De Smet (1995, 116, note 100) in the context of his discussion of ibda' cannot be relied upon: both Daawa and ‘Uyun are likely to have been composed in the Ibn Sïnâ circle—but then De Smet himself calls ‘Uyuns author “Ps.-Fârâbï.”

[728] Al-Fârâbï (1964, 41) and McGinnis and Reisman (2007, 87).

[729]     This point is further strengthened by the fact that al-Fârâbï also uses other terms derived from the root w-j-d in connection with God’s creation of the world, as can be seen for instance in Àra' (al-Fârâbï 1985a, 88-89 and 1985b, 55). Here again, we observe that a verb expressing causation or creation is applied to the First and the separate intellects with an identical intention and meaning.

[730] Thillet and Oudaimah (2001-2002, Proposition 23, 346-347).

[731] One should bear in mind that Proclus, unlike al-Fârâbï, generally does not describe the highest entity of his metaphysics, i.e., the One, as an intellect. A compel­ling, and in some ways overlapping, analysis of causality with regard to the First and the thawani is given by Vallat (“Al-Farabi’s arguments for the Eternity of the World,” forthcoming). However, I do not concur with Vallat on one point. The author argues that the thawani should be regarded as autonomous existents, which “do not depend on the First for their own subsistence” (19; see also 15, 17). Vallat also concludes that al-Fârâbï’s intellects are in fact comparable to Proclus’ authupostata. While this inter­pretation agrees with my own argument in connecting al-Fârâbï’s separate intellects with the metaphysical beings of Proclus’ philosophy, it, on the other hand, seems to go too far in stressing their complete autonomy. Vallat’s claim seems to be under­mined by the equation al-Fârâbï establishes between the subsistence of the thawani and their intellection of the First. It is their sustained contemplation of the First, which is their main object of intellection, which enables them to exist and subsist actually qua intellective beings, and in that sense their subsistence directly depends on It. Their intellection, which expresses the cosmic movement of reversion toward the First and thus Its role as a final cause, is also what enables the thawani to cause the existence of lower beings, so that both their own existence and their causing existence in other entities are equally tied to their act of contemplating the First. Vallat’s conclu­sion is all the more difficult to accept, since he simultaneously stresses the primacy of final causality in al-Fârâbï’s metaphysics. As chapter 2 argued, and as the present discussion also shows, efficient and final causality are two sides of the same coin in al-Fârâbï’s metaphysics. In any case, the above analysis raises a new question: on what grounds can one distinguish the First from the thawani, given that they possess a com­mon immaterial nature and cause the existence of other beings in a similar way through their intellection? A brief answer is that these immaterial entities can be differentiated in two crucial regards. First, their essences possess a varying degree of simplicity. While the First is absolutely simple, the thawani are affected by a small degree of multiplicity (kathrah). Second, the First is not subject to any higher cause, even a final cause, whereas the thawani owe their actual state to higher efficient and final causes. It is chiefly on these two points that one may distinguish the various causes of al-Fârâbï’s metaphysics.

[732]     The connection between causation and intellection is stressed in al-Fârâbï’s ema- nationist treatises, Àm and Siyasah, as well as in Fi l-‘aql (1985a, 100-105, 116-117, 1964, 52, and 1938, 35 respectively).

[733] Proclus (1963, 174,8-9).

[734] Opsomer (2000 and 2001) and Dillon (2000, 344-345).

[735] Indeed, God is presented as the sole innovator of the world, and a whole array of traditional Arabic terms is used to describe his demiurgic power, such as al-mubdi‘, al-badi‘, and al-khaliq, as in Theology of Aristotle (Badawï 1977b, 24-27 passim).

[736] Taylor (1981, Proposition 3, 287,12-15).

[737] Thillet and Oudaimah (2001-2002, Proposition 22).

[738] Badawï (1977b, 134-135 and 167 ff. passim) and Lewis (1959, 281, 291).

[739]     This, naturally, does not imply that al-Fârâbï read Proclus’ works in Greek, but it underlines the important fact that he approached these works critically and adapted and transformed their contents. This also raises the question of which kind of compila­tion or edition of Proclus’ works al-Fârâbï had access to, which might not have been exactly the same as the ones handed down to us by the Arabic tradition.

[740] Syrianus (2006, 80,12-13).

[741] Syrianus (2006, 117,28 ff.).

[742] Syrianus (2006, 119,22-25).

[743] Syrianus (2006, 106,32-107,2).

[744]     D’Ancona and Taylor (2003, 637) minimized the impact of the Proclus arabus on falsafah, but recent contributions building on Maróth (1994) are slowly chang­ing this view with respect to al-Fârâbï’s and Ibn Sïnâ’s philosophies: see Daiber (2004), Janos (2010a), and Vallat (“Al-Farabi’s arguments for the Eternity of the World,” forthcoming); cf. also D’Ancona (2000). This conclusion is also supported by Zimmermann’s (1986, 178) remark that al-Fârâbï’s quotations from Theology of Aristotle in Jam' rely instead on passages culled from Proclus’ Elements, as Vallat (2004, 73) also shows. The major doctrinal parallels between al-Fârâbï and the Proclus arabus high­lighted in the previous analysis are also strengthened by terminological similarities, such as the common use of the term al-thawani, which means “secondary intellects” in Mahd al-khayr, and which al-Fârâbï uses to refer to the nine cosmic intellects (see Badawï 1977a, Proposition 9, 13, and passim). For a case study of how a tenth-century Arabic thinker assimilated material from the Proclus arabus, see Wakelnig (2006). Hence, the impact of Proclus on Arabic thought is still difficult to delineate with preci­sion, but the evidence for it is gradually accumulating.

[745] Zimmermann (in al-Fârâbï 1981a, cx) holds that “al-Farabi neither was nor wanted to be above Islam. His aim in studying philosophy was to create an Islamic philosophy.” Zimmermann adds in a note: “This aim found magnificent expression in his political philosophy,” a statement with which Mahdi would undoubtedly have agreed. This view may be true when applied to al-Fârâbï’s early works, but it is very debatable when applied to the whole of the Fârâbïan corpus. First, and with respect to the metaphysics and cosmology of his later philosophical works, we have seen that al-Fârâbï’s theories are at odds with the main Islamic tenets on creation and contin­gency. There is no apparent effort on his part to harmonize his doctrines on causation with contemporary views on divine creation, to such a point that it is unclear whether the concept of divine creation has any real meaning in his metaphysics. But even with respect to al-Fârâbï’s political thought as expressed in the emanationist works, Zimmermann’s statement seems misleading. For al-Fârâbï’s views are based on the fun­damental premise that religions imitate philosophy, and thus that their capacity to con­vey true knowledge depends on the social and cultural factors existing at a particular time and on the level of dialectical sophistication reached by the religious community of that time. In that sense, religions and philosophy have a relative, not essential, con­nection, a view which finds further support in al-Fârâbï’s conception of history and the gradual development of human knowledge. Hence, if al-Fârâbï focuses on Islam in his ‘political’ works, it is primarily because Islam happened to be the main religious para­digm during his time and thus offered the best prospects for elaborating an ideal reli­gious society. In fact, Zimmermann himself (cxii) adds later on that “al-Farabi sees individual religions as different expressions of universal truths and never explicitly claims superiority for Islam.”

[746] Al-Farabi (1981b, 63).

[747] Al-Fârâbï (1964, 55) and McGinnis and Reisman (2007, 96; see also 95).

[748] Ibn Sïnâ (1951, 430/174, 1985, 313-314, and 2005, 330,39-331,4). Al-Fârâbï’s position that the heavenly bodies are composed of different principles and yet that only one cause is posited for their existence was obviously problematic for Ibn Sïnâ, who revised his predecessor’s model in light of his elaborate theory of causality. The result was that two distinct causes are assigned to the heavenly bodies in Ibn Sïnâ’s cosmol­ogy, one for the soul and another for the matter of the orbs. But his cosmology may nevertheless be problematic in this respect: how can immaterial beings, i.e., the sepa­rate intellects, cause material effects?

[749] This depends on whether one relies on the commentary on Metaphysics or on Quaestiones. In the latter work, Alexander seems to argue for the existence of a celestial matter that is different from the sublunary matter. See chapter 3, 1.3.1 on substrate (ñnoKeipevov) in the Greek commentatorial tradition.

[750] Alexander (2001, 17-19, 52-53).

[751] Al-Fârâbï (1964, 53, my translation): wa-jawhar kull wahid min al-samawat murakkab min shay'ayn: min mawdu' wa-min nafs. The use of the adjective murakkab here is noteworthy, because it was standardly employed in physics to signify the com­posite nature of sublunary bodies. In this case, the term suggests a parallel between the sublunary hylomorphic beings and the celestial bodies, both being composed of a duality of principles.

[752] Al-Fârâbï (1985a, 123, translation slightly revised, 1985b, 70).

[753] Al-Fârâbï (1964, 53).

[754] Simplicius in his commentary on Physics; see CAG, vol. 10, 1358,38-1359,3.

[755] Al-Fârâbï (2001a, 53 and 1971, 87).

[756] Al-Fârâbï states this relation explicitly in Ft l-‘aql, in the context of his discussion of the separate intellects: “it [the separate intellect] has a principle [i.e., a cause], since whatever is divisible has a cause that makes it a substance” (al-Fârâbï 1938, 35 and McGinnis and Reisman 2007, 77). For a comparison of al-Fârâbï’s and Proclus’ theories of causality and its relation to perfection, see Wisnovsky (2003b, 109-112).

[757]     This hierarchy is clearly expressed by al-Fârâbï in Àra (1985a, 114-115 and 1985b, 67).

[758] Ibn Sïnâ describes the celestial soul as “corporeal” (jismaniyyah) in Shifa (2005, 312,5-6). In Ibn Sïnâ’s cosmology, the sphere-souls are not properly speaking intellects and do not have pure intellection, due to their material and corporeal dimension. Rather, they are primarily characterized by imagination (takhayyul); see Ibn Sïnâ (1983-86, 383,14 ff., 387, 5).

[759] Alon (2002, 810-811).

[760] Al-Fârâbï (1938, 12) and McGinnis and Reisman (2007, 71).

[761] Al-Fârâbï (1938, 13-14, my translation).

[762] For another description of the potential intellect as material intellect, see al-Fârâbï (1985a, 198-203, and passim, 1985b, 101 ff.).

[763] Al-Fârâbï (1938, 22) and McGinnis and Reisman (2007, 74).

[764] Al-Fârâbï (1985a, 174-175 and 1985b, 92). Apparently, Themistius developed a similar analogy; see Duhem (1913-59, vol. 4, 386, 397).

[765] As we learn from al-Fârâbï’s (1938, 13-15) discussion, the difference between the potential intellect and other ‘regular’ material substrates is that the former entirely fuses with the form it receives and becomes indistinguishable from it, whereas the lat­ter only receive forms on their exterior surface, i.e., these material substrates do not fuse completely with their forms in that the material cause and the formal cause remain distinct (e.g., the shape and the matter of a wooden bed). Al-Fârâbï’s description of the potential intellect is indebted to the Aristotelian notion that thought and object of thought become one in the act of intellection.

[766] Al-Fârâbï (1964, 34) and McGinnis and Reisman (2007, 83, translation slightly revised).

[767] The idea that al-Fârâbï’s psychology and noetics are a bridge between the cosmo­logical and human levels has already been noted by some scholars, including Madkour (1934, 145), Lucchetta (in al-Fârâbï 1974), and Hamzah (in al-Fârâbï 2001b, 45). However, these scholars have focused chiefly on the Agent Intellect and not on the heavenly souls. Moreover, although my argument agrees with their basic view of an ontological link between the superlunary and sublunary souls, it goes further in posit­ing a conceptual and methodological transfer of human noetic and psychological notions to the cosmic level.

[768] Returning momentarily to the discussion of transfer (naqlah) provided in chapter 1, it is likely that al-Fârâbï would have considered the term “substrate” a trans­ferred term (ism manqui) from psychology, assuming that this science was elabo­rated chronologically before cosmology. Interestingly, modern studies have shown that al-Fârâbï’s noetics, like his cosmology, was influenced to some extent by the work of Alexander of Aphrodisias, on which see Fotinis (in Alexander 1980), Shroeder (1989), and Blumenthal (1996); for the various levels of intellect, see Gilson (1929), Rahman (1958), and Davidson (1992). In spite of Finnegans thesis (1957) that al-Fârâbï was not influenced by Alexander’s psychology, there are convincing reasons to think that the opposite is true. Jolivet (1977, 218, note 33) rightly calls for a revision of Finnegan’s position, and Geoffroy (2002) reinstates Alexander’s On the Soul commen­tary as one of the crucial sources in al-Fârâbï’s theories of human intellection; cf. the sections on al-Fârâbï in Davidson (1992). The above analysis also confirms this. The idea that the potential intellect is a ‘material’ intellect, which can best be defined as a substrate for forms, finds an exact parallel in the psychological writings of the Greek commentator. As far as we know, Alexander is the first philosopher to have described the potential intellect as a material intellect; see Alexander’s commentary on On the Soul (1980, 105). Whether al-Fârâbï’s theory of celestial substrate was inspired by Alexander’s writings on noetics and psychology in addition to the already discussed passages of Alexander’s commentary on Metaphysics is a point worth consid­ering, and, in my view, a likely one. According to Genequand (in Alexander 2001, 6), Alexander was the first to provide a systematic treatment of the celestial souls by apply­ing concepts taken from On the Soul, an approach which represents an interesting precedent to that of al-Fârâbï. And according to Steinschneider (1869/1966, 117), al-Fârâbï composed a commentary on Alexander’s On the Soul, which would stand as yet another connection between the two thinkers. If that is the case, then Alexander and al-Fârâbï’s method of studying the celestial bodies would be very similar indeed. However, in spite of these parallels, these two thinkers visibly had different philosophi­cal priorities and aims when addressing the parallels between human and heavenly intellection. For Alexander, it was to stress the divinity and life-power of the celestial bodies in order to better explain their impact on the sublunary world, a view that fits well with his theory of celestial providence. Al-Fârâbï, on the other hand, focused chiefly on the problem of celestial matter and substance and its relation to causation, as well as the concept of intellection as a source of perfection. Hence, in this case as well, the use al-Fârâbï makes of these psychological theories and the way in which he inter­weaves them with other metaphysical concepts testify to his creative approach to cosmology.

[769] M. Rashed (2009, 76-78). A developmentalist hypothesis with regard to Jam'has already been suggested by Endress “(in al-Fârâbï 2008, Prefazione, x-xi), whose view Rashed expressly addresses in this section of his article. It is true that Endress does not provide any argument to support his position. Furthermore, it should be noted that Druart (1987a) had already entertained the hypothesis of an evolution in al-Fârâbï’s philosophy, but rejected it as unconvincing, due to the lack of a solid chronology of his works. For reasons that will appear clearly in the next paragraphs, I believe that both Druart and M. Rashed have underplayed the few vital chronological indicators in our possession.

[770] Gutas (2002, 2003, and 2004b) and Vallat (2004, 85 ff.).

[771] See notably Mahdi (in al-Fârâbï 2001c, introduction to the 1961 edition, 5-6) and Galston (1977). Although Mahdi’s interpretive framework had a lasting influence and was subsequently adopted by many scholars, mention should be made especially of Druart’s thesis as articulated in a series of articles on al-Fârâbï’s metaphysics (1987a and 1992). Building on Mahdi, Druart offered a compelling classification of al-Fârâbï’s corpus and an elegant interpretation of his philosophical program. According to Druart, al-Fârâbï’s corpus can be divided into the “Aristotelian works,” the “program­matic works,” and “original works.” In the first, al-Fârâbï objectively summarizes Aristotle’s philosophical ideas and does not include any Neoplatonic elements. In the “programmatic works,” al-Fârâbï outlines his metaphysical project, which he intended as the completion of what he perceived to be Aristotle’s unfinished metaphysics by providing a detailed account of procession or the beings brought into existence by the First. Finally, in his “original works,” al-Fârâbï carries out this project by relying on the Neoplatonica arabica. Druart’s classification rejects Mahdi’s dichotomy between exo­teric and esoteric works and the political premise it implies, but it accepts Mahdi’s division between ‘Aristotelian’ and ‘Neoplatonic’ works in al-Fârâbï’s corpus. It is also based on the premise that al-Fârâbï limited Aristotle’s investigation of divine matters to Book Lambda of Metaphysics and that he was aware of the spurious nature of the Neoplatonica arabica, upon which he nevertheless drew extensively to achieve his own metaphysical project.

[772] The results concerning al-Fârâbï’s tendency to interpret Aristotle in light of late antique and Neoplatonic texts, even in his summaries of Aristotelian philosophy, are supported by several recent contributions: see for instance Geoffroy (2002) and Vallat (2004, 85 ff.).

[773] There are other problems with Mahdi’s approach, which can only be alluded to here. To begin with, one must accept the fundamental assumption concerning the existence of a full-fledged political philosophy in medieval Islam, a view which has been effectively criticized by Gutas (2002). Perhaps even more problematic is the fact that Mahdi’s approach construes al-Fârâbï’s metaphysics and cosmology solely through the lens of political theory, in effect subordinating these disciplines to politics. But Vallat (2004) showed convincingly that al-Fârâbï’s metaphysics is not subordinated to his politics, but rather that it is his politics that is subordinated to his metaphysics and modeled on it. The present book has further strengthened the view that al-Fârâbï’s cosmology and metaphysics deserve to be studied in their own right and contextual­ized within the history of late antique philosophy and that they are not merely deriva­tive of his political theories. Finally, a quick word should be said with regard to the dialectical interpretation championed by Galston in her monograph on al-Fârâbï. Galston’s thesis (concisely formulated at 1990, 220) is that al-Fârâbï had a “masterplan” he intended to realize in his various writings and whose aim was to induce dialectic knowledge in the reader. I must admit that I find it hard to imagine that al-Fârâbï could have written entire treatises containing views and ideas that he did not uphold, merely to entice his students to use dialectical reasoning. Moreover, it seems to me that if this had been al-Fârâbï’s overarching philosophical aim, as Galston argues, then he would have provided the contrasting views within the same works and in a systematic way, and not in different works, in a scattered manner, and during a period of time that presumably stretched over several decades; cf. Vallat (2004, 85 ff.).

[774] Al-Fârâbï (1981a, 92) and the corresponding passages in id. (1960b).

[775] Al-Fârâbï (1999b, 53).

[776] Al-Fârâbï (1981a, 92,27 ff.). Adamson (2006, 179 ff.) provides an interesting dis­cussion of the topic of divine foreknowledge in his study on al-Fârâbï’s reply to Aristotle’s “Sea-Battle argument” in On Interpretation 9. However, the conclusions he draws (185-186) with regard to al-Fârâbï’s position on this issue and its religious impli­cations cannot, in my opinion, be accepted, as they require one to understand the opposite of what al-Fârâbï asserts. This whole passage from K. al-‘ibarah shares obvious parallels with Jam' and may be fruitfully compared to its emphasis on the divine knowl­edge of particulars.

[777] Al-Farabi (1971b, Aphorism 86, 89-90).

[778] See al-Farabi (1981a, 204, notes 3-4). The doctrinal and terminological parallels between Jam' and some of al-Farabi’s logical works have already been noted by Mallet, who highlights the overlap between Jam' and K. al-‘ibarah, K. al-jadal, Nass al-tawti’ah; see al-Farabi (1999e, 160-161, 168, 176).

[779] Al-Farabi (1985c, vol. 2, 161) and M. Rashed (2009, 74-75).

[780] Rescher (1963, 34-35) and Lameer (1994, 13-20). Parts of the contents of this work in any case overlap with K. al-qiyas; see the editions of these treatises in al-Farabi (1985c, vol. 2).

[781] Al-Farabi (1985c, vol. 2, 45).

[782]     Al-Farabi (1985c, vol. 2, 82, 88 ff.); see also the translation by Rescher (in al-Farabi 1963, 74, 85-87).

[783] A variant of this argument focusing on the heavens (sama’) instead of the world ( alam) also appears in K. al-qiyas (al-Fârâbï 1985c, vol. 2, 36-37). This argument from composition has been extensively discussed in Davidson (1969 and 1987).

[784] This is the opinion of Davidson (1987, 134-35), for instance, who writes with regard to the argument of the compositeness of bodies: “Alfarabi, a dyed-in-the-wool Aristotelian [!], could not by any means have accepted the conclusion”; and that this argument from accidents is “cited undoubtedly without approval by Alfarabi.”

[785] Al-Fârâbï (1985c, vol. 2, 68).

[786] Much has been made of the alternative title sometimes attached to this work in the Arabic manuscript tradition: Kitab al-mukhtasar al-saghir fi l-mantiq ‘ala tariq al-mutakallimin. But this title, together with the introductory section that precedes the actual treatise, is clearly an addition to the original text inserted by a later scribe. Indeed, al-Fârâbï’s text proper begins with the break: qala Abu Nasr (al-Fârâbï 1985c, vol. 2, 68,12). As Lameer (1994, 13-20) points out, this work is fundamentally a sum­mary of al-Fârâbï’s K. al-qiyas, and there is in any case much overlap between the two works. Al-Fârâbï explicitly states in the opening section of the work (68, 12 ff.) that he regards the contents of the treatise, if not the actual examples, as genuinely Aristotelian. Hence, K. al-qiyas al-saghtr is a much more fitting title. Brague’s (1996, 94) analysis of this passage and his claim that al-Fârâbï’s intention in this work is to discuss dialectic and juridical matters is undermined by the foregoing remarks, especially given that he cites from the preface as if it were by al-Fârâbï himself.

[787] Al-Fârâbï (1992, sec. 43, 349-350).

[788] Al-Asharï (1987, 55, 58) in Risalah ahl al-thaghr attributes to “the philosophers [al-falasifah]” the proof based on “substances and accidents [jawahir wa-a‘rad]” intended to establish the existence of God and the creation of the world; see also Gimaret (1990, 220-221). This proof, according to Davidson (1987, 135), is the very one exposed at length by al-Fârâbï in his K. al-qiyas al-saghtr. And as Davidson (1969) also showed, this proof was adopted by many early philosophers writing in Arabic in the ninth and tenth centuries, such as al-Kindï and Saadia Gaon, who was a contempo­rary of al-Fârâbï. This raises the question of why Davidson so promptly dismisses the possibility that al-Fârâbï endorsed it.

[789] Finally, and for the sake of comprehensiveness, K. al-maqulat contains yet another passage in which al-Fârâbï exploits the issue of the creation and eternity of the world to illustrate a logical point (1985c, vol. 1, 124,17-21). In this passage, al-Fârâbï intends to explicate the law of non-contradiction by supplying examples of various kinds. He explains that the statements “the world is created” and “the world is eternal” are both false if the world does not exist, just as qualities predicated of Zayd are false if Zayd himself as subject does not exist. Immediately after, al-Fârâbï reiterates a similar cosmological example, stressing that the assertions “every [or each] world [kull ‘alam] is created” and “each world is not created” are either true or false depending on whether the world (posited in each case) actually exists. One cannot infer much about al-Fârâbï’s personal views on creation from this passage of K. al-maqulat, except the fact that the Second Teacher cherished cosmogonical examples in his didactic expositions in his early logical works.

[790] See al-Fârâbï (1999e, sec. 59, 136 ff.). The implication of this passage is not only that religion and philosophy do not differ in their fundamental premises, but also that philosophy can be of use to religion in clarifying key points of doctrine, such as divine omniscience, absolute creation out of nothing, etc. This is also how a later Arabic thinker, Ibn al-Sïd al-Batalyûsï (d. 1127 CE), construed Jam'. He writes (Elamrani- Jamal 1996, 160): “Al-Farabi rapporte que tous les philosophes de la Grèce, Aristote et les autres, pensaient qu’il n’y avait pas de différence entre la philosophie et la Loi reli­gieuse quant au but recherché.” Keeping the audience and social context of Jam' in mind, this message seems primarily intended to the author’s contemporary Muslim readers, a view which seems supported by the implicit Quranic references given throughout this passage. Yet the argument is not specifically addressed to Islam and can also apply to other religious communities. In this respect, this treatise should be construed in light of the ideas on the harmony between religion and philosophy preva­lent in tenth-century Baghdad, especially in the Christian philosophical circles; see Watt (2007) and Griffith (2007 and 2008).

[791] For a specific example, see the discussion of tamthïl in Jawabat (al-Fârâbï 1992, 349-350) and K. al-qiyas (id. 1985c, vol. 2, 36 ff.); but Jam' and Jawabat in general con­tain a wealth of passages dealing with logical points and linguistic issues, which should be connected to the logical treatises.

[792] It should be pointed out that nothing would have prevented al-Fârâbï from pos­sessing his own students during this period, as the extent of his involvement with the Christian thinkers cannot be assessed with any precision.

[793] In the summary of Âra\ which was not written by al-Fârâbï himself, but which faithfully conveys his view on the subject, and in Fusul mabadi‘ ara' (al-Fârâbï 1985a, 38-39 and 1968, 79), al-Fârâbï describes the “thing which should be believed to be God [Allâh],” as well as the “existents which should be believed to be the angels.” This implies that common religious notions can be applied to the philosophical principles (the First, the separate intellects) that are discussed in these works and that religion merely serves a mimetic and symbolic function aimed at the non-philosophical crowd, an approach which is typical of al-Fârâbï’s emanationist treatises.

[794] A passage in Fusul further illustrates this point. Having identified the First Principle in the context of a metaphysical discussion, al-Fârâbï calls it “the divinity” (al-ilah), not Allâh. Fusul, like Âra and Siyasah, consistently refers to the supreme metaphysical entity as the “first principle” or the “first cause.” One exception appears in Aphorism 87 (al-Fârâbï 1971b, 91), where it is described as “Allah ta ala" But this seems to be a later scribal insertion, as is suggested by the alternative reading in another manuscript, al-rabb, and by the fact that these formulas do not have other occurrences in this work and in the metaphysical sections of the emanationist treatises.

[795] There are of course exceptions. Al-Fârâbï is said to have dictated a commen­tary on Posterior Analytics to Ibrâhïm ibn Adï during his stay in Aleppo; see Gutas (1982a, 210).

[796] Although al-Fârâbï’s early studies with the Christian thinkers of Baghdad repre­sents a crucial piece of biographical information for the developmentalist hypothesis, further research must be conducted in order to clarify this connection, especially al-Fârâbï’s potential debt to these thinkers’ cosmology. The analysis of Mattâ ibn Yunus’ commentary on Physics provided in an earlier section is a step in this direction, although it can only yield hypothetical results.

[797] Gutas (1982a, 210).

[798] Dunlop (in al-Fârâbï 1961b, 9-17).

[799] Al-Fârâbï (1999e, 124-125), where the author broaches the question of the eter­nity and creation of the world (qidam al-‘alam wa-hudüthuhü). Terms from the root h-d-th are used throughout this passage (124-129) to express the creation of the world with time and ex nihilo and in opposition to the concept of eternity.

[800] Assuming, of course, that the work was not misattributed to al-Fârâbï; see GAL, I, 235.

[801] The idea of an evolution in al-Farabi’s philosophy has rarely been evoked by scholars, but one exception is the view of Street (2004, 536 and 542) with respect to al-Fârâbï’s logic: “Alfarabi’s attitude to Aristotle seems to have become clearer over time, and in consequence his position changes from one work to another,” and: “Alfarabi modified his logical doctrines throughout his life.” Although the developmentalist hypothesis has not been the object of much scholarly attention in the case of al-Fârâbï, it has received serious consideration with respect to other thinkers. Bertolacci (2001, 259) detects “an evolution in Avicenna’s knowledge of Aristotle’s Metaphysics” See also Wisnovsky (2003b, ch. 9 and 14), who argues for a developmentalist account of Avicennan metaphysics, as well as Gutas (2001) with respects to Ibn Sïnâ’s theory of hads. See also Adamson (2007a, 188, and ch. 1, passim) for al-Kindï.

[802] The question of whether this shift was partly triggered by al-Fârâbï’s reliance on a new recension of texts from the Proclus arabus, or whether he developed a new inter­pretation and way of reading the same texts should be left open for the time being. Suffice it to say that the manuscript history and the diffusion of the various works forming the Neoplatonica arabica in the early Arabic context is highly complex and poorly understood, especially during the period that goes from the time of al-Kindï, when many of these works were compiled, to the time of al-Fârâbï; see Zimmermann (1986). Accordingly, it is plausible that al-Fârâbï had access to different parts of this corpus during his creationist or early Baghdad phase and during his late Baghdad phase. For instance, he may in the former case only have had access to certain excerpts or to a particular compilation (al-Kindï’s ‘metaphysics file’?) that did not emphasize an eternalist framework, and which could therefore be easily accommodated with—and indeed be used to strengthen—a creationist and non-eternalist position. Following this rationale, al-Fârâbï would at a later stage have consulted a fuller version of these texts, or different texts, which contained a more comprehensive scheme of eternal causation and which enabled a new interpretation of Aristotelian cosmology in light of Proclean theories of causation and intellection. The previous remarks nevertheless remain hypothetical.

[803] See Mahdi’s (in al-Fârâbï 2001c, introduction to the 1962 edition), Galston (1977), Druart (1987a), and Butterworth (2001, 122).

[804] In this connection, it is worth recalling that both Theology of Aristotle and Mahd al-khayr were attributed to Aristotle in the Arabic tradition. The former was widely known in Arabic as Uthulujiya Aristii ta lis and opens with the following statement: “The first chapter of the book of Aristotle the philosopher, called in Greek “Theologia,” that is, discourse on divinity” (Adamson 2002a, 27). The latter work is mentioned as one of Aristotle’s works in the incipit of some manuscripts. This is the case, for instance, with the incipit of the Leiden manuscript, which reads: “In the name of God, the Merciful, the Compassionate. My success is only through God! The Book of Aristotle’s Exposition on the Pure Good” (Taylor 1981, 282). Due to his direct involvement in the compilation and revision of Theology of Aristotle, it is possible that al-Kindï knew the true Neoplatonic origin of this work, which he nevertheless perceived as a useful com­plement to Aristotelian metaphysics. As Zimmermann (1986) has shown, however, by al-Fârâbï’s time the corpus had undergone considerable transformation, so that the same conclusion cannot be made in his case.

[805] Al-Fârâbï (1938, 34-36).

[806] Ibn Sïnâ (2005, 316,30 ff.). There has been a general tendency in modern scholar­ship, partly as a reaction to earlier scholarly conceptions on the topic, to argue that the Arabic philosophers, especially al-Kindï, al-Fârâbï, and Ibn Sïnâ, were aware of the true origin of Theology of Aristotle and Mahd al-khayr, or at least that these works were not composed by Aristotle. But it should be stressed that the evidence used by these schol­ars to support this claim is sparse and difficult to interpret and also appears unconvinc­ing when compared to the much more substantial evidence supporting the contrary position. For an overview of this issue with regard to al-Kindï and Ibn Sïnâ, see Adamson (2002a and 2008b) and Aouad (1989, 583-586) respectively. As argued throughout this chapter, I believe that this view cannot be convincingly maintained in the case of al-Fârâbï. Although the discussion remains open with regard to al-Kindï and Ibn Sïnâ, I am inclined to a similar conclusion in their case as well.

[807]     See the insight given by Morrison (2007), who focuses primarily on the theologi­cal tradition, as well as Saliba (2007, 171-193); for a case study of Ibn Sina’s views on celestial motion, see Janos (2011).

[808]     This dialogue was most likely not composed by Plato, although it is often included in editions of Plato’s complete works.

[809]     A locus classicus of this debate is Simplicius’ commentary on On the Heavens, which not only identifies and discusses some of the crucial issues, but also conveys valuable information on various other thinkers, including Ptolemy, Alexander, and Ammonius.

[810]     As Hugonnard-Roche (2007, 289-291) notes, Ptolemy and other Greek scientists were already studied by Syriac authors during the sixth, seventh, and eighth centuries. The Syriac cosmological corpus contained works such as De mundo and Alexander’s On the Principles of the Cosmos (Mabadi), the latter of which was used by al-Fârâbï in its Arabic version. It is interesting that some of these works were somehow attributed to Aristotle in the Syriac tradition, although al-Fârâbï surely knew the real author of Mabadi’, since the name of Alexander appears explicitly at the beginning of the Arabic translation.

[811]     See Ibn al-Qiftï (1903, 279-280).

[812]     Walzer had already noticed that one of the characteristics of al-Fârâbï’s cosmology is that it does not provide a detailed and comprehensive account of celestial motion (in al-Fârâbï 1985a, 363). While true to some extent, this statement should be qualified in light of the fragmentary nature of the Fârâbïan corpus.

[813]     Al-Fârâbï (2001c, 102-103, 1985a, 124-125, and 1985b, 71). I have already dis­cussed the philosophical assumptions underlying such a view in the section on meth­odology. It is worth reiterating that the philosophical belief in the perfection of the superlunary bodies and the superiority of the circular shape entails that all heavenly motions be circular, despite their differences in velocity and direction.

[814]     Al-Fârâbï (1985a, 118-119 and 1985b, 69).

[815]     Al-Fârâbï (1964, 55). The problem of how this outermost orb imparts motion to the other orbs preoccupied the minds of many philosophers and astronomers: is it through direct physical contact, through soul, or through a power that acts at a dis­tance? Whatever the cause, this ninth starless orb was often made responsible for the general westward motion of the entire heavens. This idea, however, was not accepted by everyone and was criticized as early as the ninth century by Muhammad ibn Müsâ ibn Shâkir (d. 873 CE); see Saliba (1994b; 2007, 92-93). Several centuries later, Qutb al-Dïn al-Shïrâzï elaborated a model consisting of only seven main orbs, while al-Nïsâbürï added another orb for the fixed stars but rejected the outermost starless orb (Morrison 2007, 84-85). Ibn Rushd and the Ikhwân al-Safâ’ also rejected it and regarded the heavens as a single animated being moving with one motion; for insight into this issue, see Ragep (1993, 409). Al-Fârâbï for his part uses the term quwwah to describe the influence of the outermost orb on the other orbs without specifying the source from which this power derives. More will be said about this concept shortly.

[816]     Al-Fârâbï (1985a, 128-129 and 1985b, 73).

[817]     On the Heavens 1.9.279a15 and 2.4.287a24-27 and al-Fârâbï (1964, 34, 65). The eternity of the celestial bodies’ intellection, rather than their motion, is stressed in the first passage of Siyasah, but the two concepts are intricately connected, as the celestial bodies according to al-Fârâbï move as a result of the contemplation of higher princi­ples. In this regard, and according to al-Qiftï (1903, 280), al-Fârâbï composed a work entitled Kitab fi anna harakat al-falak sarmadiyyah, which has not survived. The idea that time issues from celestial motion also appears in Jam' (al-Fârâbï 1999e, 128-129), which is otherwise known for its exposition of a creationist view.

[818]     Ptolemy (1987, 92) and Morelon (1993, 18-19, 56-57).

[819]     Al-Farghânï, for instance, who came from the same region as al-Fârâbï, discusses the two heavenly motions in his work entitled Jawami' ‘ilm al-nujum wa-usul al-harakat al-samawiyyah (1986, 15 ff. and 45 fl2.). This work was quite influential in both the Arabic and Latin worlds and was used as an astronomical handbook for centuries subsequent to the author’s death.

[820]     Goldstein (1967, 36).

[821]     The theory that the heavens move as a cosmic animal possessing several yet syn­chronic motions and the question of how this theory relates to the ninth orb are dis­cussed in Ragep (1993, vol. 2, 409) and Saliba (1994b, 118-121, and note 19). It is unclear at this stage how Ptolemy conceptualized this issue, as a systematic edition and analysis of Planetary Hypotheses is required in order to answer this question.

[822]     Al-Fârâbï (1964, 55) and McGinnis and Reisman (2007, 96).

[823]     Al-Fârâbï (1985a, 121 and 1985b, 69); but see more generally al-Fârâbï (1985a, 128-131, 1964, 55, and 1960, 102).

[824]     This point should be taken as yet another indication of al-Fârâbï’s adherence to the Ptolemaic model, for there can be little doubt that the Second Teacher is here implicitly referring to the eccentric and epicyclic devices, whose positions vis-à-vis the earth are constantly changing due to the fact that they do not have the earth as their center. This means that the planets are sometimes closer to the earth, at other times farther away, depending on the position of the eccentrics and epicycles, and thus that from the viewpoint of a human observer the speed with which they revolve around the earth also appears to change.

[825]     The relation between the celestial nature and other concepts such as soul and inclination in the ancient cosmological context is very intricate, and I can only offer a glimpse here into its history. For more information, see Sambursky (1962), Wildberg (1988), Sorabji (1988), Verrycken (1990b), and Pearson (1999). Sorabji (2005, vol. 2, ch. 1, especially 33-56) conveniently compiles some of the most relevant excerpts from the primary sources.

[826]     See Wildberg (1988, 240 ff.) and Pearson (1999).

[827]     Both views are exposed in Simplicius’ On the Heavens commentary (2004a, 380,1,30 ff.).

[828]     For this reason, Wolfson’s (1929, 77-78) distinction between two types of accounts of celestial motion in the medieval period, one based on soul, the other based on nature, appears artificial due to the equivocity of the term ‘nature’ and the overlapping of these two concepts.

[829]     Mahdi (1967, 253-254).

[830]     Al-Fârâbï (2001c, 102-103, my emphasis).

[831]     Al-Fârâbï (1985a, 105, 132-133, translation revised, and 1985b, 62, 75).

[832]     Ibn Sïnâ (2005, 308,33-35).

[833]     Goldstein (1967, 36). As Ragep (1995, vol. 2, 380) and Pingree and Haq EI2 explain, regularity or homogeneity appears to have been the most important criterion in the astronomical tradition for ascribing natural motion to the celestial bodies.

[834]     For a discussion of Ptolemy’s theory of celestial motion, see Sambursky (1962, 133 ff.) and Murschel (1995).

[835]     Goldstein (1967, 36,6-7).

[836]     See Ibn Sïnâ (2005, 307-308 and especially 308,13-20). But Ibn Sïnâ’s position is somewhat ambiguous, since in other instances he seems intent on ascribing some kind of nature (tabïah) to the heavens; see Ibn Sïnâ (1983-86, 382, 383; cf. id. 2005, 308,18­20, 25 ff.) and Hasnawi (1984). The point seems to be that the principle endowing the celestial bodies with motion is not natural, but that motion itself when realized in the celestial bodies may be conceived of as something natural. For a discussion of this distinction in al-Thsi’s astronomy, see Ragep (1993, vol. 2, 380).

[837]     Al-Fârâbï (1961a, 97,6).

[838]     The term tab' is used repeatedly by al-Fârâbï in other contexts in Ára; see Walzer (in al-Fârâbï 1985a, 393-394).

[839]     Al-Fârâbï (1999d, 6 and 1930, 7). The latter text, in particular, shows many simi­larities with Ibn Sïnâ’s doctrine and should probably be attributed to his circle.

[840]     Indeed, these two works contrast natural motion to psychological motion in a way reminiscent of Ibn Sïnâ’s argumentation and which finds no parallel in al-Fârâbï’s extant works; see Ibn Sïnâ (2005, 307 ff.).

[841]     If we accept the above hypothesis that al-Fârâbï’s use of tabiah in the Àra passage may be informed just as much by the astronomical tradition as by the philosophical one, then it is not surprising that it says nothing about the ultimate causes of celestial motion; on causality in the hay ah literature, see Ragep (1995, vol. 1, 45-46, and vol. 2, 380).

[842]     Al-Fârâbï (1981a, 94,10, 1960b, and 1964, 55). Al-Fârâbï also uses quwwah frequently in his discussion of the human soul, where it usually means faculty, as in al-quwwah al-natiqah, ‘the rational faculty.’

[843]     See for instance Timaeus 38D and Epinomis 986B-C.

[844]     Murschel (1995, 38-39).

[845]     Endress (2002, 23). The relevant passages in Aristotle are: Physics 3.5, 8.6 and 8.10, and Metaphysics 12.7.1073a3-11.

[846]     Badawï (1977b, 38 ff.), Lewis (1959, 65 ff.), and D’Ancona (2003, 250).

[847]     That the celestial bodies are free of potentiality in the sense of possibility is made clear when al-Fârâbï, referring to Aristotle’s view, writes: “as regards agents, possibility is in such agents as—unlike the heavenly bodies, which perform an action of perma­nent motion—are not in action permanently” (1981a, 93,24). It would seem, then, that al-Fârâbï distinguishes between a possibility of action, which the heavenly bodies lack, and a possibility of existence, which the heavenly bodies have in virtue of their causes, i.e., the separate intellects.

[848]     Ibn Sïnâ also discusses quwwah in his cosmology (2005, Book 9, ch. 2, passim). In Ibn Sïnâ’s system of celestial kinematics, quwwah is connected with inclination (mayl) and intention (ma'na). “Power” says Ibn Sïnâ, “imparts motion only through the mediation of inclination. Inclination is the idea [ma'na] sensed in the mobile body” (2005, 308,20-21). See Janos (2011) for a more detailed discussion of this topic.

[849]     Al-Fârâbï (1981a, 94,10 and 1960b).

[850]     See the article by de Boer in EI2. Al-Tahânawï gives an almost identical descrip­tion of how quwwah relates to celestial motion, but in addition he calls it the “origin of an act” (mabda l-fi‘l) and a “cause” (sabab).

[851]     Al-Fârâbï (1964, 55) and McGinnis and Reisman (2007, 96).

[852]     Ptolemy (1987, 92, 98-99, 103).

[853]     Murschel (1995, 38).

[854]     Ptolemy holds that “the planets are ensouled (mutanaffisa) and are moved with a voluntary motion” (Murschel 1995, 39). What kind of psychological faculties the orbs have according to Ptolemy is nevertheless unclear and requires more detailed research.

[855]     Al-Fârâbï (1964, 34).

[856]     Al-Fârâbï (1999d, 6). Again, it should be stressed that this treatise may not be authentic, but further research into its contents is a desideratum to settle this point.

[857]     Al-Fârâbï (1938, 34) and McGinnis and Reisman (2007, 77).

[858]     Al-Fârâbï (1985a, 119-123 and 1985b, 69 ff.).

[859]     Al-Fârâbï (1964, 52). In spite of these statements, al-Fârâbï does not develop the concept of imitation (iqtida and tashabbuh), which play an important role in the systems of many Greek and Arabic thinkers. For example, Alexander mentions them several times in Mabadi (2001, 54-55, 70-71). Abu Sulaymân al-Sijistânï (1974a, 370; 1974b, 374-375) in his treatise on the celestial bodies explains that the souls of the planets desire (yatashawwaqu) the virtues (fadail) of the higher principle and “move the celestial bodies through will in order to imitate the First Cause” (tuharrikuha bi-l-iradah li-l-tashabbuh bi-l-‘illah al-üla).

[860]     Ibn Rushd (1984b, 148).

[861]     Ibn Rushd (1984b, 151). That the principle that is “intellectual representation” is a principle of motion is stressed by Ibn Rushd in his commentary on the same page: “the principle of this motion in the celestial body is intellectual representation. He [Aristotle] says that to make it known that the principle of this motion is not imagination, nor sense perception, but intellectual representation and the desire moving this body locally comes from the intellectual representation.”

[862]     Badawï (1947, 5).

[863]     One can see that making intellection the main principle of celestial motion sig­nificantly facilitated the task of explaining the plurality and diversity of the celestial motions. In comparison, the aether theory developed in On the Heavens appears much more rudimentary. It is challenging to imagine how one homogenous and unchanging element may be responsible for a variety of motions, if it is assumed that aether is the main cause of motion. In contrast, the concept of intellection provides more leeway to develop a nuanced and flexible theory of celestial kinematics, as can be witnessed by al-Farabi’s and Ibn Sinas works. Aristotle himself may have also realized this, hence his introduction of the unmoved movers in Book Lambda.

[864]     This proposition, however, is difficult to reconcile with al-Fârâbï’s statement in Siyasah to the effect that the general westward motion of the heavens is due to the influence of the outer orb, which is said to transmit a power (quwwah) to the other lower orbs. The problem is that if the First is a universal mover, and if all the orbs derive a common motion from their contemplation of the First, then it seems superfluous to posit a transmission of power from the outermost orb to the other inner orbs to explain the regular diurnal motion of the heavens. This motion might just as well be explained by the common contemplation and desire of the orbs for the First. This overlap is not properly accounted for by al-Fârâbï and Ibn Sïnâ. It is noteworthy that the idea that the First may move several orbs simultaneously, accepted straightforwardly by both al-Fârâbï and Ibn Sïnâ, was perceived as a puzzle by some of the ancient commentators; see Simplicius’ report on Alexander in his commentary on On the Heavens, 270,9-12.

[865]     Walzer stresses this point twice in his commentary (see al-Fârâbï 1985a, 352 and 363, and note 169).

[866]     Janos (2011).

[867]     Ibn Sïnâ (2005, 325,31-326,1, translation revised). The exact same passage appears in Najah (Ibn Sïnâ 1985, 310), and mention of emanating powers from the celestial souls can also be found in another passage of this work (1985, 296).

[868]     Although it is not stated explicitly in this passage, Ibn Sïnâ includes the eccentrics and epicycles in this number and ascribes them to Aristotle as well. This becomes clear when one compares this passage to the similar, albeit longer and more complete,

account that appears in Mabda (Ibn Sïnâ 1984, 67-68). On this issue, see Janos (2011).

[870]    Ibn Sïnâ (1984, 67-68, 1985-1986, 648-649, and 1983-1986, 45 ff.).

[871]    On this point, see Gutas (1988, especially 98-145).

[872]    Goldstein (1967, 42).

[873]    Danesh-nameh provides a clear explanation of how both the celestial souls and the separate intellects can be called “movers” of the orbs; see Ibn Sïnâ (1986, 242-243).

[874]    Goldstein (1967, 36, 40-41); see also Murschel (1995, 38-39).

[875]    Goldstein (1967, 40-41). For more information on the concepts of “action at a distance” and “moving soul” (al-nafs al-muharrikah) in hay’ah, see Ragep (1993, vol. 2, 409-410). Ragep’s discussion focuses on al-Tüsï’s astronomy, but it is strikingly close to what we find in Ptolemy and Ibn Sïnâ. This raises the possibility of a direct continuity of the concept of psychological power in the works of these thinkers.

[876]    Murschel (1995, 39).

[877]    Ibn Rushd (1958, 134, sec. 22).

[878]    Ibn Rushd (1958, 134, sec. 22).

[879]    For this parallel, see Janos (2011).

[880]    In Ibn Sina (1957-60, vols. 3-4, 618-19).

[881]    There are other important differences, which I cannot discuss here. For instance, Ibn Sina applies Aristotle’s theory of the unmoved movers to Ptolemy’s models of plan­etary motion consisting of eccentric orbs and epicyclic spheres, and he also attributes such models to Aristotle.

[882]    De Smet (2008).

[883]    Al-Farabi (1985a, 114-115 and 1985b, 67).

[884]     One should remember that the orb of the fixed stars and the outermost orb have two motions and a single motion respectively, which means that no eccentrics or epi­cycles are needed to account for their simple motion; more on this model below.

[885]     This will shortly change, however. An edition and French translation of Book 2 is being prepared by R. Morelon, who already published Book 1 (Morelon 1993), and J. Ragep and A. Jones are working on a new edition and English translation of this important text.

[886]     Metaphysics 12.8.1073b25-27.

[887]     Al-Fârâbï (1964, 55); see also the section on quwwah above.

[888]     See Ibn Sïnâ (1984, 71 and 1983-1986, 45 ff.); cf. al-Tûsï (in Ibn Sïnâ 1957-60, vols. 3-4, 618-619). For an analysis of these passages, see Janos (2011).

[889]     It is perplexing that the text has the plural form kurat, since the description con­cerns the orb of the fixed stars, which is unique and which is otherwise referred to in the singular in this passage. This oddity can be explained either by an editing mistake or by Ibn Sïnâ’s potential reference to the hypothesis that the stars are fixed on various smaller orbs within the main orb of the fixed stars.

[890]     Ibn Sïnâ (1984, 71).

[891]     Ibn Sïnâ (1984, 68).

[892]     Other hints seem to support this interpretation. First, al-Fârâbï’s use of the term jumlah to refer to the various orbs and spheres associated with a planet as a coherent ‘group’ or ‘system.’ This concept would be difficult to understand if each orb and sphere was completely independent and possessed its own principle of motion that was dis­tinct from that of the planet. Second, al-Fârâbï’s belief that the heart is the main seat of the inner senses and the soul in animals also lends weight to this hypothesis, since al-Tüsï mentions explicitly (in Ibn Sïnâ 1957-60, vols. 3-4, 618-619) that the expo­nents of this kinematic model compare the planet and its soul to the heart of the animal and make it the source from which motion originates, while they compare the various corporeal devices associated with it to the limbs or muscles. It is notable that, unlike Ibn Sïnâ, al-Fârâbï followed Aristotle rather than Galen when it comes to assigning a corporeal location to the soul and the inner senses specifically; see al-Fârâbï (1985a, 175 ff. and 1985b, 92 ff.), where the heart is defined as the “ruling organ” in the animal body.

[893]     If one rejects this interpretation, then it becomes very difficult to understand how al-Fârâbï could account for the plurality of planetary motions by positing only ten separate intellects. Ibn Sïnâ and al-Th sï at any rate do not propose an alternative model that relies on only ten intellects. This point, for what it is worth, may be seen as addi­tional negative evidence that al-Fârâbï endorsed the model outlined above. One may propose an alternative interpretation, which also makes use of the ten-intellect theory, but rejects the special status given to the planetary souls: all the orbs and spheres of a group could be ensouled, and motion could be explained by the particular contempla­tion of these entities for the same separate intellect. This means that a separate intellect would be the common object of thought of several celestial souls contained within the same system, but their contemplation would differ on the basis of their varying place and status in the celestial hierarchy. That a single mover can be contemplated by vari­ous intellects is shown in al-Fârâbï’s cosmology by the status of the First, which is a universal object of thought and which is desired by all the celestial bodies and separate intellects below it. Thus, and by transposition, each separate intellect could be an object of thought for all the entities of its ‘group.’ While possible, this theory seems less con­vincing, and it finds no echo in the works of later authors who discuss celestial kinematics.

[894]     Al-Fârâbï (1985a, 170-171, translation slightly revised, and 1985b, 90): “These powers [quwan], then, which are in parts of the body like these [i.e., hands, feet, etc.] are all of them bodily instruments and subordinate to the ruling appetitive faculty within the heart.”

[895]     Al-Fârâbï (1985a, 174-177 and 1985b, 92-93).

[896]     Ibn Sïnâ (2005, 312,4 ff.).

[897]     One of these problems is how the inner senses relate to the rational faculty of the celestial bodies; see Janos (2011).

[898]    Al-Fârâbï (1960a, 102) and chapter 1, 2.1-3.

[899]     Al-Fârâbï (1964, 34).

[900]     Ibn Sïnâ (2005, 317,34-39).

[901]     In Ihsa’, al-Fârâbï subsumes the study of the various celestial motions under the subject matter of mathematical astronomy or ilm al-nujum al-tallmi; see chapter 1, 2.1.

[902]    Tusi begins Tadhkirah by explaining that “those of its [i.e., astronomy’s] principles that need proof are demonstrated in three sciences: metaphysics [ma bad al-tabiah], geometry, and natural philosophy” (Ragep 1993, vol. 1, 90). He then proceeds to a detailed account of the mathematical and physical principles (Ragep 1993, vol. 1, 41-46, 98 ff.), but the expected account concerning the metaphysical principles does not follow.

[903]    Indeed, while the mathematical and physical aspects seem to have been quite har­moniously reconciled by al-Tusi in his Tadhkirah—a fact which is attested at a basic level by the assumption of the corporeality of the orbs and spheres, including the eccentrics and epicycles—his work does not provide an extensive treatment of the metaphysical causes of celestial motion. Here again, one suspects that this omission is due to a disciplinary division and to the different skopós assigned to the various philosophical genres.

[904]    Al-Fârâbï (1985c, vol. 4, 68) and chapter 2, 2.2.3.

[905]    This view also appears in one of the surviving excerpts of Abu Bishr’s commen­tary on Physics; see AristCUâlïs (1964, 137) and McGinnis and Reisman (2007, 122).

[906]    This in turn explains why many ancient and medieval thinkers believed the orbs and spheres to consist of the same celestial substance as the planets, such as aether or another principle. Yet others held that because of their difference in visibility—the orbs being transparent, the planets opaque—different kinds of celestial matter had to be postulated. As we saw in chapter 3, 1.2.2., this view is attributed by Maimonides to al-Fârâbï himself in his Physics commentary.

[907] Ibn Sïnâ (2005, 307 ff., 317,3).

[908]     It is still unclear to me, however, whether the kinematic models or hypotheses, as they are often called (i.e., the eccentrics and epicycles), would stand as limmï proofs of motion in an astronomical context. It would perhaps be more precise to say that the eccentrics and epicycles are causes of motion only if they are defined as corporeal entities made of aether or some other celestial substance, and thus that they stand as proofs only insofar as astronomy overlaps on celestial physics or shares some of its principles. But if these same devices are conceived of in purely abstract or geometric terms, then their causal efficacy would be eliminated by the same token, as only the formal cause would remain. Hence, the question of the explanatory status of these planetary hypotheses would hinge on how a thinker defines astronomy and its relation to physics and whether he defines the eccentrics and epicycles as bodies or as geomet­ric figures. But even then, the implications of this point in the works of individual authors remain obscure and require further research.

[909] Adamson (2007a, 182-183).

[CMX]   In this regard, this study may also contribute to rectifying the misconception that al-Fârâbï’s cosmology was borrowed almost wholesale by Ibn Sïnâ. Not only did the two thinkers disagree on the fundamental questions of the number of separate intel­lects and on their mode of causation, but they in addition probably articulated very different interpretations of celestial motion. Hence, the cosmological divergences between their models are at least as significant as the similarities, if not more so, a fact which has not been sufficiently acknowledged in the secondary literature and which is bound to modify to some extent our perception of al-Fârâbï’s philosophical legacy. The influence of al-Fârâbï’s theories of celestial intellection, causation, and motion on thinkers other than Ibn Sïnâ, and especially on the Baghdad philosophical school of the tenth century, is still unclear. Further research on this important question seems a requisite to fully appreciate the fate that al-Fârâbï’s new cosmological and metaphysical model had in subsequent Arabic intellectual history.

[911]     While Da awa has to my knowledge never been studied before, the problem of the authenticity of Taltqat and ‘Uyün has attracted some scholarly attention. With regard to the former, Michot (1982) questioned its authenticity, but Àl Yâsin, who provided a new Arabic edition of this work in 1988, attributed it to al-Fârâbi; cf. Vallat (2004, 387), who leaves the question of its authenticity open. As for ‘Uyün, Goichon (1937, 226 ff.), Cruz Hernández (1950-51), Alonso Alonso (1959), and more recently Lameer (1994, 23-25), take it to be a genuine Fârâbian work. Serra (1993, 51) rejects al-Fârâbi’s authorship and ascribes it to Ibn Sinâ’s circle, while Vallat (2004, 383) classifies it as a genuine work but remains skeptical. In any case, this work has been studied mostly from a Latinist perspective as a result of its transmission to medieval Europe and little effort has been exerted to contextualize it in the classical Islamic period. All the subse­quent translations from the Arabic texts are my own.

[912]     Al-Fârâbi (1992, sec. 27, 383).

[913]     Al-Fârâbi (1992, sec. 2, 372).

[914]    Al-Farabi (1992, sec. 95, 400). This use of the plural form of the term maddah raises several questions. Is the author implying that the heavenly bodies possess differ­ent types or degrees of matter? Or that the heavens as a whole are composed of various different elements? No definitive answer can be given on the basis of these laconic statements.

[915]    The treatise, however, opens with these words: al-daawa l-qalbiyyah al-mansubah ila Aristu mujarradah ‘an al-hujaj li-Abi Nasr al-Farabi (al-Farabi 1930, 2). This raises the question of how medieval thinkers perceived the authorship of this treatise.

[916]    Al-Farabi (1930, 4-5): wa-huwa aydan wahid la kathrata fihi illa ‘ala l-wajh al-madhkur wa-yujadu ‘anhu min haythu huwa mumkin al-wujud ‘ aqil li-dhatihi l-falak al-a la bi-maddatihi wa-su ratihi allati hiya nafsuhu wa-innahu yujadu an hadha l-thani ‘ aql akhar.

[917]    Al-Farabi (1930, 2-4, and passim).

[918]    Al-Fârâbi (1930, 8).

[919]    Al-Fârâbi (1999a, 60-62).

[920]     As in Àra and Siyasah, the two terms nafs and ‘aql are used interchangeably to refer to the celestial souls; see al-Fârâbi (1992, sec. 27, 382-383; sec. 73, 393).

[921]     Al-Fârâbi (1992, sec. 43-44, 386-387, sec. 56, 389, and sec. 63, 391).

[922]     Al-Fârâbi (1992, sec. 27, 382-383).

[923]     Al-Fârâbi (1992, sec. 27, 382-383): ‘uqül al-kawdkib bi-l-quwwah la bi-l-fi‘l fa-laysa lahâ an ta'qila daf atan bal shay'an ba'da shay'in.

[924]     Al-Fârâbi (1992, sec. 27, 382-383).

[925]     Badawi (1977b, 101), Lewis (1959, 75), and Adamson (2002a, 94 ff.).

[926]     Again, this might be explained by the fact that quwwah in the Neoplatonica ara­bica often refers to ‘power’ and not to ‘potentiality’ in the Aristotelian sense.

[927]     Al-Fârâbi (1992, sec. 56, 389): al-falak wa-l-kawakib ta‘qilu l-awwal, and section 58, 389-390: wa-yakft ftha muharrik wahid.

[928]     See in particular al-Fârâbi (1992, sec. 55, 389 and sec. 78, 395-396).

[929]     Al-Fârâbi (1992, sec. 55, 389): al-falak ya‘qilu hadhiht l-ashya thumma yatakhayyaluha.

[930]     Al-Fârâbi (1992, sec. 78, 395-396): al-kawakib tatakhayyalu l-ashya, fa-yastru takhayyuluha sababan li-huduth ashya.

[931]     Al-Fârâbi (1992, sec. 78, 395-396):fa-yasiru takhayyuluhasababan li-huduth ashya kama anna harakataha takun sababan li-huduth ashya' ukhar. And: wa-qad tatakhayy- alu fa-tuhdithu shay'an la bi-tawassut al-harakah, aw ma a tawassut al-harakah.

[932]     See On Generation 2.10.

[933]     Al-Fârâbi (1992, sec. 78, 395-396).

[934]     The author does mention the Agent Intellect in another passage dealing with human noetics; al-Fârâbi (1992, sec. 78, 395-396).

[935]     Cf. Michot (1986) and Gutas (2006a and 2006b) on Ibn Sinâ’s theory of celestial imagination and its epistemological role.

[936]    Michot (1982).

[937]    Al-Fârâbi (1999a, sec. 9, 58-59).

[938]     Al-Fârâbi (1999a, sec. 7, 58).

[939]     Al-Fârâbi (1999a, sec. 8, 59).

[940]     Al-Fârâbi (1985a, 100-101 and 1985b, 61).

[941]     Al-Fârâbi (1999a, sec. 7, 58). It is possible that the author intended this treatise to be a condensed account or summary of his cosmology, in which case he would not have bothered to explain the intellection and causation of the superlunary beings in detail. In that sense, the theory of twolfold intellection upheld in ‘Uyün is not a suffi­cient reason to exclude the possibility of Ibn Sinâ’s authorship or that it was composed in the Avicennan circle. The Avicennan connection seems further supported by the particular terminology used in this work, such as “possible” and “necessary of exist­ence,” etc.

[942]     Al-Fârâbi (1999a, sec. 10, 59-60).

[943]    Al-Farabi (1992, sec. 27, 382-383).

[944]    Al-Farabi (1992, sec. 56, 389).

[945]    Al-Farabi (1992, sec. 55, 389).

[946]    Al-Farabi (1992, sec. 56, 389): al-falakwa-l-kawakibtaqilul-awwal, fa-yastafizzuha l-iltidhadh bi-hadha l-taaqqul fa-tatba uhu l-harakah, and: al-falak yatasawwaru l-ghayah ma a tilka l-harakat.

[947]    Al-Farabi (1992, sec. 58, 389-390): ittisal al-harakat al-mustadtrah sababuhu l-iradat al-muttasilah, wa-yakft ftha muharrik wahid ‘ala sabtl al-‘ishq.

[948]    Al-Farabi (1992, sec. 63, 391): iradat al-falak wa-l-kawakib an tustakmala wa- tatashabbaha bi-l-awwal.

[949]    Ibn Sina (2005, 312,20 ff.) and Janos (2011).

[950]     Al-Fârâbi (1992, sec. 27, 382-383): wa-illa la-kanat tataharraku l-harakat kulluha dafatan, wa-hadha muhal.

[951]     Al-Fârâbi (1992, sec. 65, 391; sec. 78, 395-396).

[952]     Al-Fârâbi (1999a, sec. 10-12, 60).

[953]     For some insight into Ibn Sinâ’s celestial dynamics and especially his concepts of motion and inclination, see Hasnaoui (1984).

[954]     Al-Fârâbi (1999a, sec. 17, 62).

[955]     Ibn Sinâ (2005, 312-313, 316).

[956]     Al-Fârâbi (1999a, sec. 13, 60). The Aristotelian theory of the natural motion of the four elements is also developed in section 12.

[957]     See chapter 4, 2.1.

[958]     Al-Fârâbi (1999a, sec. 14, 61).

[959]     See for example Ibn Sina (2005, 315,15 ff.).

[960]     Al-Farabi (1999a, sec. 17, 62).

[961]     See Metaphysics of Shifa in Ibn Sina (2005, 323,20-26), chapter 4, 3.1-2 of this book, and Janos (2011).

[962]     See the entries in Liddell and Scott’s Greek-English Lexicon (1996, 9th Edition), 1275. These terms were used by Damascius, Elias, and other Neoplatonists, some of whose works were translated into Arabic. It is possible that al-Fârâbi is drawing directly from one of the Arabic translations of these Greek works, in which these words would have been rendered by the Arabic term tajawhur. According to Walzer (in al-Fârâbi 1985a, 342), there would be a connection between tajawhara and the Greek term üsiüsthai.

[963]     Goichon (1938, 52).

[964]     Al-Fârâbi (1985a, 92-93 and 1985b, 56).

[965]     Al-Fârâbi (1964, 102).

[966]     Al-Fârâbi (1985a, 120 and 1985b, 70).

[967]    Al-Fârâbi (1964, 34): wa-bi-hadha [the rational soul or intellect] tajawhara l-ajsam al-samawiyyah.

[968]    Al-Fârâbi (1938, 34).

[969]    Translated by Smith (in Aristotle 2001).

[970]    Winosvsky (2003, ch. 1).

[971]     For a comparative analysis of Proclus’ and al-Fârâbi’s theories of actuality as per­fection, see Wisnovsky (2003b, 108-112).

[972]     Al-Fârâbi (1964, 40-41): al-kathrah allatt bi-ha tajawharaha azyad mimma tata- jawharu bi-ht l-thawant.

[973]     Al-Fârâbi (1985a, 66-67, 92-93 and 1985b, 44, 56).

[974]     Al-Fârâbi (1938, 31) and McGinnis and Reisman (2007, 76, translation slightly revised): fa-yastru ‘inda dhalika jawhar al-insan aw al-insan bi-ma yatajawharu bi-ht aqrab shay ila l-‘aql al-fa'al.

[975]     Al-Fârâbi (2001c, 22).

[976]     For tajawhara as applied to the human mind, see al-Fârâbi (1985a, 92 and 1985b, 56); for the celestial intellects, see al-Fârâbi (1985a, 120-121 and 1985b, 69).

[977]     See for example al-Fârâbi (1938, 34-35 and especially 1964, 33-34).

[978]     Al-Fârâbi (1964, 34).

[979]     Al-Fârâbi (1964, 33-34) and McGinnis and Reisman (2007, 82-83, translation slightly revised).

Önceki Yazı
« Prev Post
Sonraki Yazı
Next Post »

Benzer Yazılar